Efficient, Formal, Material, and Final Causes in Biology and Technology
Abstract
:1. Introduction
1.1. Aristotle’s Four Causes (This account is due to Christoph Horn (Bonn). I thank him for it)
- The material cause: “that out of which”, e.g., the bronze of a statue or the silver that makes a bowl.
- The formal cause: “the form”, “the account of what-it-is-to-be”, e.g., the shape of a statue.
- The efficient cause: “the primary source of the change or rest”, e.g., the artisan, the art of bronze-casting the statue, the man who gives advice, the father of the child.
- The final cause: “the end or the good, that for the sake of which a thing is done”, e.g., health is the end of walking, losing weight, purging, drugs, and surgical tools.
1.2. Scientific Discoveries since Then
1.3. Updated Versions of Aristotle’s Causes
1.4. This Paper
2. The Hierarchy of Existence
2.1. A Current View: Modular Hierarchical Structures
- Boundaries and binding: they have some kind of boundary limiting their extent and are more tightly bound with faster internal interactions than the weaker strength and slower speed of interaction between modules.
- Information hiding: a user of a module does not need to know the internal variables and mechanisms of the module; all they are concerned with is that it carries out its required tasks.
- Abstraction (black boxing): the functioning of the module can be characterized by an abstract description relating the input variables to output variables (Ashby 2013 [71]), summarized by a suitable label/name.
- Interfaces: control transfer of energy and information in and out of a module according to a protocol.
- Multiple realizability: A key feature is the multiple realizability of a module’s internal structure consistent with its abstract description and interface protocols (Gillett 2002 [72], Piccinini and Maley 2014 [73], Batterman 2018 [74], Bickle 2020 [75]). This is an inevitable result of evolutionary origins (Edelman and Gally 2001 [76]).
- Origin: Modularity makes possible the coming into being of very complex structures through the inheritance of modules with variation and selection; otherwise, it is simply not practicable (Simon 2019 [77]).
2.2. Reductionism and Holism
“The whole is greater than the sum of its parts.”
“We argue that the causal powers of many systems are determined by) higher-level, macroscopic properties that are neither reducible nor weakly emergent, and that contemporary physics is compatible with some kind of pluralism that affirms that these entities are robustly real.”
2.3. Relation to the Four Kinds of Causes
2.4. Is This Persuasive?
“But there is little work done to actually prove, to a skeptical reader, that this is indeed the right way to think about things. The rejoinder could always be that such causal descriptions are merely convenient and that all the real work is still being done at the level of physical forces—it’s just too complicated for us to grasp”.
“A skeptic might press that the effects Yates cites as pointing to a distinctive kind of higher-level causal power are themselves all higher-level. Assuming that all macroscopic properties are microphysically realized, if one were able to take a wide-angle view of the evolving process in purely micro-physical terms throughout (including in characterizing the targeted token effects), it’s not clear that reference to anything other than the features of and basic relations among microphysical entities is required for explanation. It might well be the case that to explain the token effects under their macroscopic description requires equally macroscopic appeal to molecular geometry (where a given geometric shape is multiple realizable by distinct spatial arrays of atoms). But such explanatory irreducibility is, as we’ve seen, the hallmark of forms of weak emergence.”
3. Efficient Causation
3.1. Updated Version of Efficient Causation
Efficient causation takes place at an emergent level L in the hierarchy of emergence of a system S when effective laws EL(XiL(t)) at level L determine the values at times t > t0 of the relevant variables XiL(t) at that level from initial data XiL(t0) at time t0. This is a characterization of causation at that level.
- Emergent levels are defined by the existence of efficient causation (i.e., well-established effective theories) and associated variables at that level. It will generally take place via a combination of formal and material causation at that level.
- Efficient causation at an emergent level L is enabled by a combination of upward and downwards causation between levels, the latter occurring via formal and material causation, as we discuss below.
- There can be no efficient physical causes without some non-random organization of stuff—a directionality of physical forces arises from physical inhomogeneities. Thus, the notion is intimately linked with the idea of symmetry breaking (Anderson 1972 [15]).
3.2. Biology
3.3. Digital Computers and Technology
3.4. Abstract Causation
4. Formal Causation
4.1. Updated Version of Formal Causation
Formal causation takes place at an emergent level L in the hierarchy of emergence of a system S when the variables XiL(t) in the effective laws EL(XiL(t)) at level L of S obey constraints C(XiL(t),t) = 0. The constraints may depend on time via higher level variables XiM(t), M > L: then C(XiL(t),t) = F(XiL(t), XiM(t)) = 0. Such constraints determine the shapes of entities and perhaps how that shape changes with time.
4.2. Formal Causation and Life
4.3. Formal Causation: Artefacts and Engineering
4.4. Formal Causation: Oscillators
4.5. Formal Causation: Feedback Control/Homeostasis
4.6. Formal Causation: Adaptive Brain Networks and Ion Channels
5. Material Causation
5.1. Updated Version of Material Causation
Material causation takes place at an emergent level L in the hierarchy of emergence of a system S when a set of variables {XiL(t)} characterizes the nature of material stuff at level L of S. This underlies the possible emergent set of such variables {XiN(t)} at levels N > L of S. Material causation is static in an interval I = [t1, t2] if the set of variables {XiL(t)} is constant in that interval and is dynamic if {XiL(t)} changes during this time.
It affects higher levels L > M upwardly and can affect lower levels N < L downwardly.
- DDM1:
- creating or importing new elements;
- DDM2:
- sustaining or altering elements already in place;
- DDM3:
- deleting or exporting elements.
5.2. Material Causation: Materials at the Basis of Engineering, Technology, and Daily Life
5.3. Dynamic Material Causation: Metabolism and the Cardiovascular System
5.4. Dynamic Material Causation: Developmental Processes and Gene Regulatory Networks
5.5. Dynamic Material Causation: Adaptive Selection and Evolutionary Processes
“We treat the slow phylogenetic process (natural selection) as furnishing top down constraints (i.e., top-down causation) on fast phenotypic processes (action selection). In turn, the active exchange of the phenotype with its environment provides evidence that is assimilated by natural selection (i.e., bottom-up causation). This multi-scale ontological account is licensed by describing both phylogenetic and phenotypic processes as selecting (extended) genotypes and (extended) phenotypes with the greatest fitness; where fitness is quantified with (free energy) functionals of probability density functions (a functional is a function of a function).”
Selection shapes all emergent levels L in Figure 1 simultaneously. It has to do so, because they all work together to enable the organism to function (Noble 2012 [3], Ellis 2020 [117]). Selection is therefore not confined to either the gene level or the organism level: it is a process of selection of effective causation at all emergent levels from the macromolecular level up. (It does not of course affect the physics or physical chemistry levels. These are determined by the laws of physics.)
6. Final Causation
6.1. Updated Version of Final Causation
Final causation occurs when values, purpose, or meaning (“Telos”) shape decisions made by organisms, individuals, groups, or organizations and hence shape their actions, with consequent material outcomes at the macrolevel (personal or organizational) that chain down to affect outcomes at all underlying physical levels.
“What is ontologically prior? The metaphysical question is this: are values and meaning just a special cause of final cause (as Aristotle thought), or do they figure in the very definition of final cause (as Ellis proposes)? Which is ontologically prior to which? If Ellis were to embrace Aristotle’s more expansive definition of teleology, this wouldn’t negate any of what he describes about the irreducible role of final causation in the human and social sciences. For Aristotle, the question becomes this: are there real (and even irreducible) powers at the peculiarly human and rational level? If powers exist at that level, like the power of reasoning well or a sensitivity to the real value of actions or states, then final causation also obtains”.
6.2. The Case of Individuals
6.3. The Case of Organizations and Resultant Technology
which is nothing other than the organizational final cause. One should note here the multidimensional nature of goals: they have a cognitive function, a motivational function, a symbolic function, a justification function for actions taken, and an evaluator function (Scott and Davis 2007: p. 184 [155]). Additionally, they have a normative nature: they relate to what is desirable in a moral sense, which is where transformational leadership arises (Burns 2004, 2010 [179,180]). Note that the fact there is such a moral dimension does not imply that actions of any particular individual, group, or organization will necessarily be morally good, rather that they will lie somewhere on the moral spectrum presented in Ellis and Noble (2023) [49] whether they make this explicit or not, and this will be a key aspect of the final causation taking place.“Each member of a set of behavior alternatives Is weighted in terms of a comprehensive scale of values—the “ultimate” ends” (Scott and Davis 2007: p. 54 [155]),
6.4. Foundations of Agency and Free Will
“The distinction between physics and biology is sometimes illustrated via the thought experiment of repeating Galileo’s (almost certainly apocryphal) Tower of Pisa experiment by dropping a cannonball and a pigeon. To the extent that we can predict what the pigeon will do at all, we implicitly invoke its agency. To explain why it does not simply plummet, it is not enough to invoke aerodynamics; we must also in effect allow that the pigeon does not want to plummet. It manifests its agency by virtue of having goals. … Agency evolves precisely because living organisms are liable to encounter challenges that evolution itself is too slow to adapt to.”
Free Will: In the context of the modular hierarchical structure of human life, with multiple realizability of higher-level functions occurring in the context of huge numbers of molecules at the cellular level in a highly dynamic environment (§2.2) and with humans being open systems, dynamic formal and material downward causation underlie the existence of free will.
7. The Outcome
7.1. The Four Causes and Emergence
- Stating that efficient causation occurs at each higher level is essentially the claim that emergence does indeed occur. Novelty arises at each higher level because the nature of efficient causation is different at each emergent level.
- Stating that material causation occurs is essentially stating that supervenience occurs over a material basis.
- Stating that formal causation occurs is essentially the statement that constraints break symmetries and thereby shape outcomes.
- Stating that final causation occurs is a statement that in the case of humans and the abstract and material artefacts they create, purpose and values play a key role in determining outcomes.
- The same level relations between the four causes are that both material and formal causation often play a role in efficient causation at each level. The exception is abstract causation in the case of intelligent beings and organizations.
- The interlevel relations that relate efficient causation at different levels in biology and technology are mediated by static and dynamic material and formal causation.
- Final causation plays a key role in determining what happens at all levels in the cases of human beings, organizations, and technology: it, in effect, provides a topmost level of causation via its associated values, as indicated in Figure 1.
- In each case, outcomes are determined contextually via initial and boundary conditions for the effective laws characterizing efficient causation at each level. The effective laws do not by themselves determine any outcomes at all and that applies inter alia to the efficient causation characterized by physical laws such as Newton’s laws of motion, Maxwell’s equations, and so on. They determine possibilities but not specific outcomes in particular contexts.
7.2. A Specific Example
Why is an aircraft flying from Hamburg to London?
7.3. Causal Closure
“Aristotelians contend, there is no microscopic world that can be exhaustively described in exclusively microscopic terms, because of the irreducible role of macroscopic constraints. This fact renders the usual definition of supervenience (whether global or local) inapplicable, since that definition presupposes that we can disentangle emergent and base properties and facts from each other. Aristotelians should reject the talk of disjoint “levels” of reality in favor of pluralistically-described indivisible whole.”
7.4. Physics by Itself Does Not Give All the Answers
Funding
Institutional Review Board Statement
Data Availability Statement
Acknowledgments
Conflicts of Interest
References
- Shields, C. Aristotle. In The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy; Zalta, E.N., Ed.; Stanford University: Stanford, CA, USA, 2022; Available online: https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2022/entries/aristotle/ (accessed on 11 June 2023).
- Arthur, W.B. The Nature of Technology: What It Is and How It Evolves; Simon and Schuster: New York, NY, USA, 2009. [Google Scholar]
- Noble, D. A theory of biological relativity: No privileged level of causation. Interface Focus 2012, 2, 55–64. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed]
- Feynman, R. The Feynman Lectures in Physics: Volume I: Mainly Mechanics, Radiation, and Heat, Volume II: Mainly Electromagnetism and Matter, Volume III: Quantum Mechanics; Addison Wesley: Boston, MA, USA, 2013. [Google Scholar]
- Sokolowski, R. Matter, elements and substance in Aristotle. J. Hist. Philos. 1970, 8, 263–288. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Emsley, J. Nature’s Building Blocks: An AZ Guide to the Elements; Oxford University Press: Oxford, UK, 2011. [Google Scholar]
- Scerri, E. The Periodic Table: Its Story and Its Significance; Oxford University Press: Oxford, UK, 2019. [Google Scholar]
- Lehn, J.M. Supramolecular chemistry: From molecular information towards self-organization and complex matter. Rep. Prog. Phys. 2004, 67, 249. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Watson, J.D.; Baker, T.A.; Gann, A.; Bell, S.P.; Levine, M.; Losick, R.M. Molecular Biology of the Gene; Pearson: Boston, MA, USA, 2014. [Google Scholar]
- Petsko, G.A.; Ringe, D. Protein Structure and Function; Oxford University Press: Oxford, UK, 2004. [Google Scholar]
- Wagner, A. Arrival of the Fittest: Solving Evolution’s Greatest Puzzle; Penguin: London, UK, 2014. [Google Scholar]
- Booch, G.; Maksimchuk, R.A.; Engle, M.W.; Young, B.J.; Connallen, J.; Houston, K.A. Object-Oriented Analysis and Design with Applications; Addison Wesley: Boston, MA, USA, 2007. [Google Scholar]
- Pezzulo, G.; Levin, M. Top-down models in biology: Explanation and control of complex living systems above the molecular level. J. R. Soc. Interface 2016, 13, 20160555. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed]
- Vooshholz, J.; Gabriel, M. Top-Down Causation and Emergence; Springer: Cham, Germany, 2021. [Google Scholar]
- Anderson, P.W. More is different: Broken symmetry and the nature of the hierarchical structure of science. Science 1972, 177, 393–396. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed]
- Marshall, W.; Albantakis, L.; Tononi, G. Black-boxing and cause-effect power. PLoS Comput. Biol. 2018, 14, e1006114. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed]
- Campbell, N.A.; Reece, J.B. Biology; Benjamin Cummings: San Francisco, CA, USA, 2005. [Google Scholar]
- Atkins, P.; De Paula, J. Physical Chemistry for the Life Sciences; Oxford University Press: New York, NY, USA, 2011. [Google Scholar]
- Alberts, B. The Molecular Biology of the Cell; Garland Science: New York, NY, USA, 2015. [Google Scholar]
- Allen, T.; Cowling, G. The Cell: A Very Short Introduction; Oxford University Press: Oxford, UK, 2011. [Google Scholar]
- Berridge, M.J. Cell Signalling Biology; Portland Press: London, UK, 2014. [Google Scholar]
- Jeong, H.; Tombor, B.; Albert, R.; Oltvai, Z.N.; Barabási, A.L. The large-scale organization of metabolic networks. Nature 2000, 407, 651–654. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Karlebach, G.; Shamir, R. Modelling and analysis of gene regulatory networks. Nat. Rev. Mol. Cell Biol. 2008, 9, 770–780. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Hall, J.E.; Hall, M.E. Guyton and Hall Textbook of Medical Physiology; Elsevier Health Sciences: London, UK, 2020. [Google Scholar]
- Davies, J.A. Human Physiology: A Very Short Introduction; Oxford University Press: Oxford, UK, 2021. [Google Scholar]
- Kandel, E.R. Nerve cells and behavior. Princ. Neural Sci. 1991, 3, 18–32. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Churchland, P.S.; Sejnowski, T.J. The Computational Brain; MIT Press: Cambridge, MA, USA, 1994. [Google Scholar]
- Kandel, E.R.; Schwartz, J.H.; Jessell, T.M.; Siegelbaum, S.; Hudspeth, A.J.; Mack, S. (Eds.) Principles of Neural Science; McGraw-Hill: New York, NY, USA, 2000. [Google Scholar]
- Kandel, E.R. The Age of Insight: The Quest to Understand the Unconscious in Art, Mind, and Brain, from Vienna 1900 to the Present; Random House: New York, NY, USA, 2012. [Google Scholar]
- Franklin, S.; Madl, T.; D’mello, S.; Snaider, J. LIDA: A systems-level architecture for cognition, emotion, and learning. IEEE Trans. Auton. Ment. Dev. 2013, 6, 19–41. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Franklin, S.; Madl, T.; Strain, S.; Faghihi, U.; Dong, D.; Kugele, S.; Snaider, J.; Agrawal, P.; Chen, S. A LIDA cognitive model tutorial. Biol. Inspired Cogn. Archit. 2016, 16, 105–130. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Jacob, A.; Kugele, S.; Newen, A.; Franklin, S. Modeling interactions between the embodied and the narrative self: Dynamics of the self-pattern within LIDA. Cogn. Syst. Res. 2023, 81, 25–36. [Google Scholar]
- Darwin, C. On the Origin of Species by Means of Natural Selection, or, the Preservation of Favoured Races in the Struggle for Life; Natural History Museum: New York, NY, USA, 2019. [Google Scholar]
- Campbell, D. Downward causation in hierarchically organised biological systems. In Studies in the Philosophy of Biology: Reduction and Related Problems; Ayala, F.J., Dobhzansky, T., Eds.; University of California Press: Berkeley, CA, USA, 1974; pp. 179–186. [Google Scholar]
- Dobzhansky, T. Nothing in biology makes sense except in the light of evolution. Am. Biol. Teach. 2013, 75, 87–91. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Gilbert, S.F. Ecological developmental biology: Developmental biology meets the real world. Dev. Biol. 2001, 233, 1–12. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed]
- Wolpert, L.; Tickle, C.; Arias, A.M. Principles of Development, Version 2023/06/08; Oxford University Press: New York, NY, USA, 2002. [Google Scholar]
- Gilbert, S. Developmental Biology; Sinauer Associates: Sunderland, MA, USA, 2019. [Google Scholar]
- Gilbert, S.F.; Opitz, J.M.; Raff, R.A. Resynthesizing evolutionary and developmental biology. Dev. Biol. 1996, 173, 357–372. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed]
- Oyama, S.; Griffiths, P.E.; Gray, R.D. Cycles of Contingency: Developmental Systems and Evolution; MIT Press: Cambridge, MA, USA, 2001. [Google Scholar]
- Carroll, S.B. Endless Forms Most Beautiful: The New Science of Evo Devo and the Making of the Animal Kingdom; WW Norton & Company: New York, NY, USA, 2005. [Google Scholar]
- Carroll, S.B. Evo-Devo and an Expanding Evolutionary Synthesis: A Genetic Theory of Morphological Evolution. Cell 2008, 134, 25–36. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Ellis, G. Quantum physics and biology: The local wavefunction approach. J. Phys. Conf. Ser. (IOP Publ.) 2023, 2533, 012019. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Nurse, P. Life, logic and information. Nature 2008, 454, 424–426. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Farnsworth, K.D.; Nelson, J.; Gershenson, C. Living is information processing: From molecules to global systems. Acta Biotheor. 2013, 61, 203–222. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Farnsworth, K.D. How an information perspective helps overcome the challenge of biology to physics. Biosystems 2022, 217, 104683. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Blockley, D. Engineering: A Very Short Introduction; Oxford University Press: Oxford, UK, 2012. [Google Scholar]
- Dieter, G.E.; Schmidt, L.C. Engineering Design; McGraw Hill: New York, NY, USA, 2021. [Google Scholar]
- Ellis, G.; Noble, D. Economics, Society, and the Pre-eminent Role of Values. Theor. Biol. Forum 2023, 115, 45–70. [Google Scholar]
- Ellis, G. Emergence in solid state physics and biology. Found. Phys. 2020, 50, 1098–1139. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Clayton, P.; Davies, P. (Eds.) The Re-Emergence of Emergence; Oxford University Press: Oxford, UK, 2006. [Google Scholar]
- Murphy, N.; Ellis, G.; O’Connor, T. (Eds.) Downward Causation and the Neurobiology of Free Will; Springer Science & Business Media: Berlin/Heidelberg, Germany, 2009. [Google Scholar]
- Noble, D. Dance to the Tune of Life: Biological Relativity; Cambridge University Press: Cambridge, MA, USA, 2016. [Google Scholar]
- O’Connor, T. Emergent Properties. In The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy; Zalta, E.N., Ed.; Stanford University: Stanford, CA, USA, 2021; Available online: https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2021/entries/properties-emergent/ (accessed on 11 June 2023).
- Ackoff, R. Science in the Systems Age: Beyond IE, OR, and MS. Oper. Res. 1973, 21, 661–671. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Juarrero, A. Dynamics in Action: Intentional Behavior as a Complex System; MIT Press: Cambridge, MA, USA, 2002. [Google Scholar]
- Ellis, G. Top-down causation and emergence: Some comments on mechanisms. Interface Focus 2012, 2, 126–140. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed]
- Tabaczek, M. The metaphysics of downward causation: Rediscovering the formal cause. Zygon 2013, 48, 380–404. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Ellis, G. How Can Physics Underlie the Mind. Top-Down Causation in the Human Context; Springer: Berlin/Heidelberg, Germany, 2016. [Google Scholar]
- Hofmeyr, J.-H. Basic biological anticipation. In Handbook of Anticipation; Poli, R., Ed.; Springer: Cham, Germany, 2017. [Google Scholar]
- Hofmeyr, J.-H. Causation, constructors and codes. Biosystems 2018, 164, 121–127. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed]
- Noble, R.; Noble, D. Can reasons and values influence action: How might intentional agency work physiologically? J. Gen. Philos. Sci. 2021, 52, 277–295. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Menzies, P.; List, C. The Causal Autonomy of the Special Sciences. In Emergence in Mind; Oxford University Press: Oxford, UK, 2010; Available online: https://philpapers.org/rec/MENTCA (accessed on 11 June 2023).
- Kment, B. Causation: Determination and Difference-Making. Noûs 2010, 44, 80–111. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Pietsch, W. A difference-making account of causation. In Proceedings of the 5th Biennial Conference of the European Philosophy of Science Association, Duesseldorf, Germany, 23–26 September 2015. [Google Scholar]
- Pearl, J.; Mackenzie, D. The Book of Why: The New Science of Cause and Effect; Basic Books: New York, NY, USA, 2018. [Google Scholar]
- Ellis, G. Physical time and human time. arXiv 2022, arXiv:2210.10107. [Google Scholar]
- Brewer, C.V.; Burrow, C.D. Life: Form and Function; MacMillan: New York, NY, USA, 1980. [Google Scholar]
- Hartwell l Hopfield, J.; Leibler, S.; Murray, A. From molecular to modular cell biology. Nature 1999, 402, C47–C52. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Hoffmann, P. Life’s Ratchet: How Molecular Machines Extract Order from Chaos; Basic Books: New York, NY, USA, 2012. [Google Scholar]
- Ashby, W.R. Design for a Brain: The Origin of Adaptive Behaviour; Springer Science & Business Media: Berlin/Heidelberg, Germany, 2013. [Google Scholar]
- Gillett, C. The metaphysics of realization, multiple realizability, and the special sciences. J. Philos. 2002, 100, 591–603. [Google Scholar]
- Piccinini, G.; Maley, C.J. The metaphysics of mind and the multiple sources of multiple realizability. In New Waves in Philosophy of Mind; Palgrave Macmillan: London, UK, 2014; pp. 125–152. [Google Scholar]
- Batterman, R.W. Autonomy of theories: An explanatory problem. Noûs 2018, 52, 858–873. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Bickle, J. Multiple Realizability. In The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy; Edward, N.Z., Ed.; Stanford University: Stanford, CA USA, 2020; Available online: https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2020/entries/multiple-realizability/ (accessed on 11 June 2023).
- Edelman, G.M.; Gally, J.A. Degeneracy and complexity in biological systems. Proc. Natl. Acad. Sci. USA 2001, 98, 13763–13768. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed]
- Simon, H.A. The Sciences of the Artificial; MIT Press: Cambridge, MA, USA, 2019. [Google Scholar]
- Mossio, M.; Saborido, C.; Moreno, A. An organizational account of biological functions. Br. J. Philos. Sci. 2009, 60, 813–841. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Farnsworth, K.D.; Albantakis, L.; Caruso, T. Unifying concepts of biological function from molecules to ecosystems. Oikos 2017, 126, 1367–1376. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Ellis, G.; Kopel, J. The dynamical emergence of biology from physics: Branching causation via biomolecules. Front. Physiol. 2019, 9, 1966. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed]
- Gardner, A. Adaptation as organism design. Biol. Lett. 2009, 5, 861–864. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Tanenbaum, A.S.; Austin, T. Structured Computer Organisation; Pearson: Boston, MA, USA, 2013. [Google Scholar]
- Fratzl, P.; Weinkamer, R. Nature’s hierarchical materials. Prog. Mater. Sci. 2007, 52, 1263–1334. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Chen, Y.; Ma, Y.; Yin, Q.; Pan, F.; Cui, C.; Zhang, Z.; Liu, B. Advances in mechanics of hierarchical composite materials. Compos. Sci. Technol. 2021, 214, 108970. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Dove, M.T. Structure and Dynamics: An Atomic View of Materials; Oxford University Press: Oxford, UK, 2003. [Google Scholar]
- Miodownik, M. Stuff Matters: The Strange Stories of the Marvellous Materials that Shape Our Man-Made World; Houghton MIflin: Boston, MA, USA, 2014. [Google Scholar]
- Ellis, G.; Drossel, B. How Downwards Causation Occurs in Digital Computers. Found. Phys. 2019, 49, 1253–1277. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Batterman, R. The tyranny of scales. In Oxford Handbook of Philosophy of Physics; Oxford University Press: Oxford, UK, 2013; pp. 255–286. [Google Scholar]
- Kaeslin, H. Digital Integrated Circuit Design, from VLSI Architectures to CMOS Fabrication; Cambridge University Press: Cambridge, MA, USA, 2008. [Google Scholar]
- Flack, J.C. Coarse-graining as a downward causation mechanism. Philos. Trans. R. Soc. A Math. Phys. Eng. Sci. 2017, 375, 20160338. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed]
- Dasgupta, S. Computer Science: A Very Short Introduction; Oxford University Press: Oxford, UK, 2016. [Google Scholar]
- Greene, B. Until the End of Time: Mind, Matter, and Our Search for Meaning in an Evolving Universe; Knopf: New York, NY, USA, 2020. [Google Scholar]
- Carroll, S.M. Consciousness and the Laws of Physics. J. Conscious. Stud. 2021, 28, 16–31. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Hossenfelder, S. Existential Physics: A Scientists Guide to Life’s Biggest Questions; Viking: New York, NY, USA, 2022. [Google Scholar]
- Cunningham, B. The re-emergence of ‘emergence’. Philos. Sci. 2001, 68, S62–S75. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Chalmers, D.J. Strong and weak emergence. In The Re-Emergence of Emergence; Oxford University Press: Oxford, UK, 2006; pp. 244–256. [Google Scholar]
- Brigandt, I.; Love, A. Reductionism in Biology. In Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy; Zalta, E.N., Nodelman, U., Eds.; Stanford University: Stanford, CA, USA, 2023; Available online: https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2023/entries/reduction-biology/ (accessed on 11 June 2023).
- Paoletti, M.P. Emergent powers. Topoi 2020, 39, 1031–1044. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Santos, G. Integrated-structure emergence and its mechanistic explanation. Synthese 2021, 198, 8687–8711. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Tanaka, J.W.; Kay, J.B.; Grinnell, E.; Stansfield, B.; Szechter, L. Face recognition in young children: When the whole is greater than the sum of its parts. Vis. Cogn. 1998, 5, 479–496. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Glaser, J.R.; Glaser, E.M. Stereology, morphometry, and mapping: The whole is greater than the sum of its parts. J. Chem. Neuroanat. 2000, 20, 115–126. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed]
- Galatzer-Levy, R.M. Emergence. Psychoanal. Inq. 2002, 22, 708–727. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Davison, K.S.; Siminoski, K.; Adachi, J.D.; Hanley, D.A.; Goltzman, D.; Hodsman, A.B.; Josse, R.; Kaiser, S.; Olszynski, W.P.; Papaioannou, A.; et al. Bone strength: The whole is greater than the sum of its parts. Semin. Arthritis Rheum. 2006, 36, 22–31. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed]
- Pérez-Dorado, I.; Galan-Bartual, S.; Hermoso, J.A. Pneumococcal surface proteins: When the whole is greater than the sum of its parts. Mol. Oral Microbiol. 2012, 27, 221–245. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Matthews, L.; Guarné, A. Dbf4: The whole is greater than the sum of its parts. Cell Cycle 2013, 12, 1180–1188. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed]
- Kornblith, L.Z.; Howard, B.M.; Cheung, C.K.; Dayter, Y.; Pandey, S.; Busch, M.P.; Pati, S.; Callcut, R.A.; Vilardi, R.F.; Redick, B.J.; et al. The whole is greater than the sum of its parts: Hemostatic profiles of whole blood variants. J. Trauma Acute Care Surg. 2014, 77, 818–827. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed]
- Taylor, R.; Wood, P.A. A million crystal structures: The whole is greater than the sum of its parts. Chem. Rev. 2019, 119, 9427–9477. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed]
- Fang, S.; Hu, Y.H. Thermo-photo catalysis: A whole greater than the sum of its parts. Chem. Soc. Rev. 2022, 51, 3609–3647. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed]
- Kim, J. Physicalism, or Something Near Enough; Princeton University Press: Princeton, NJ, USA, 2005. [Google Scholar]
- Dawkins, R. The Selfish Gene; Oxford University Press: Oxford, UK, 2016. [Google Scholar]
- Crick, F. The Astonishing Hypothesis; Scribner: New York, NY, USA, 1994. [Google Scholar]
- Harris, S. Free Will; Simon and Schuster: New York, NY, USA, 2012. [Google Scholar]
- Caruso, G.D. Free Will and Consciousness: A Determinist Account of the Illusion of Free Will; Lexington Books: Washington, DC, USA, 2012. [Google Scholar]
- Noble, D.; Ellis, G. Biological Relativity Revisited: The pre-eminent role of values. Theor. Biol. Forum. 2022. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Simpson, W.M.; Horsley, S.A. Toppling the Pyramids: Physics without physical state monism. In Powers, Time and Free Will; Springer International Publishing: Cham, Germany, 2022; pp. 17–50. [Google Scholar]
- Montévil, M.; Mossio, M. Biological organisation as closure of constraints. J. Theor. Biol. 2015, 372, 179–191. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed]
- Ellis, G. The causal closure of physics in real world contexts. Found. Phys. 2020, 50, 1057–1097. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed]
- Yates, D. Demystifying Emergence. Ergo Open Access J. Philos. 2017, 3, 809–841. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Shen, B.-W.; Pielke Sr, R.A.; Zeng, X.; Baik, J.-J.; Faghih-Naini, S.; Cui, J.; Atlas, R.; Reyes, T. Is weather chaotic? Coexisting chaotic and non-chaotic attractors within Lorenz models. In 13th Chaotic Modeling and Simulation International Conference; Springer International Publishing: Berlin/Heidelberg, Germany, 2021; Volume 13, pp. 805–825. [Google Scholar]
- Neyrinck, M.; Genel, S.; Stücker, J. Boundaries of chaos and determinism in the cosmos. arXiv 2022, arXiv:2206.10666. [Google Scholar]
- Noble, D. How the Hodgkin Cycle became the Principle of Relativity. J. Physiol. 2022, 600, 5171–5177. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Laughlin, R.B.; Pines, D. The theory of everything. Proc. Natl. Acad. Sci. USA 2000, 97, 28–31. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed]
- Oerter, R. The Theory of Almost Everything: The Standard Model, the Unsung Triumph of Modern Physics; Penguin: London, UK, 2006. [Google Scholar]
- Noble, D. Modelling the heart—From genes to cells to the whole organ. Science 2002, 295, 1678–1682. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed]
- Fink, M.; Noble, D. Noble model. Scholarpedia 2008, 3, 1803. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Kandel, E.R. The molecular biology of memory storage: A dialogue between genes and synapses. Science 2001, 294, 1030–1038. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed]
- Carpenter, G.A.; Grossberg, S. A massively parallel architecture for a self-organizing neural pattern recognition machine. Comput. Vis. Graph. Image Process. 1987, 37, 54–115. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Carpenter, G.A.; Grossberg, S. The ART of adaptive pattern recognition by a self-organizing neural network. Computer 1988, 21, 77–88. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Bronowski, J. The Ascent of Man; Random House: New York, NY, USA, 2011. [Google Scholar]
- Vogel, S. Cats’ Paws and Catapults: Mechanical Worlds of Nature and People; WW Norton & Company: New York, NY, USA, 2000. [Google Scholar]
- Deacon, T. The Symbolic Species: The Co-Evolution of Language and the Brain; WW Norton: New York, NY, USA, 1998. [Google Scholar]
- Murphy, N.; Brown, W. Did My Neurons Make Me Do It? Oxford University Press: Oxford, UK, 2007. [Google Scholar]
- Davidson, P. Money and the real world. Econ. J. 1972, 82, 101–115. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Harari, Y.N. Sapiens: A Brief History of Humankind; Random House: New York, NY, USA, 2014. [Google Scholar]
- Menzies, P. The Causal Efficacy of Mental States. In Physicalism and Mental Causation; Imprint Academic: Charlottesville, VA, USA, 2003; pp. 195–224. [Google Scholar]
- Robb, D.; Heil, J. Mental Causation. In The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy; Zalta, E.N., Ed.; Stanford University: Stanford, CA, USA, 2021. [Google Scholar]
- Aberle, D.F.; Cohen, A.K.; Davis, A.K.; Levy, M.J., Jr.; Sutton, F.X. The functional prerequisites of a society. Ethics 1950, 60, 100–111. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Wainwright, S.A. Form and function in organisms. Am. Zool. 1988, 28, 671–680. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Deacon, T.W. Emergence: The hole at the wheel’s hub. In The Re-Emergence of Emergence: The Emergentist Hypothesis from Science to Religion; Clayton, P., Davies, P.C.W., Eds.; Oxford University Press: Oxford, UK, 2006; pp. 111–150. [Google Scholar]
- Noble, D. The Music of Life: Biology Beyond Genes; Oxford University Press: Oxford, UK, 2008. [Google Scholar]
- Etzioni, A. Modern Organizations; Prentice Hall: Upper Saddle River, NJ, USA, 1964. [Google Scholar]
- Elder-Vass, D. The Causal Power of Social Structures: Emergence, Structure and Agency; Cambridge University Press: Cambridge, MA, USA, 2010. [Google Scholar]
- Behr, J.P. (Ed.) The Lock-and-Key Principle: The State of the Art—100 Years on; Wiley: New York, NY, USA, 2008. [Google Scholar]
- Norman, D. User Centered System Design. In New Perspectives on Human-Computer Interaction; Lawrence Erlbaum: Mahwah, NJ, USA, 1986. [Google Scholar]
- Norman, D. The Design of Everyday Things: Revised and Expanded Edition; Basic Books: New York, NY, USA, 2013. [Google Scholar]
- Novak, B.; Tyson, J.T. Design Principles of Biochemical Oscillators. Nat. Rev. Mol. Cell Biol. 2008, 9, 981–991. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Li, Z.; Yang, Q. Systems and synthetic biology approaches in understanding biological oscillators. Quant. Biol. 2018, 6, 1–14. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed]
- Tyson, J.J.; Novák, B. Time-keeping and decision-making in the cell cycle. Interface Focus 2022, 12, 20210075. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed]
- Daur, N.; Nadim, F.; Bucher, D. The complexity of small circuits: The stomatogastric nervous system. Curr. Opin. Neurobiol. 2016, 41, 1–7. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Cabral, J.; Castaldo, F.; Vohryzek, J.; Litvak, V.; Bick, C.; Lambiotte, R.; Friston, K.; Kringelbach, M.L.; Deco, G. Metastable oscillatory modes emerge from synchronization in the brain spacetime connectome. Commun. Phys. 2022, 5, 184. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Wiener, N. Cybernetics: Or Control and Communication in the Animal and the Machine, 2nd revised ed.; MIT Press: Camb, MA, USA, 1961. [Google Scholar]
- Ashby, W.R. An Introduction to Cybernetics; Chapman and Hall: Boca Raton, FL, USA, 1964. [Google Scholar]
- Modell, H.; Cliff, W.; Michael, J.; McFarland, J.; Wenderoth, M.P.; Wright, A. A physiologists view of homeostasis. Adv. Physiol. Educ. 2015, 39, 259–266. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Penrose, E.T. Biological Analogies in the Theory of the Firm. Am. Econ. Rev. 1952, 42, 804–819. [Google Scholar]
- Scott, W.R.; Davies, G.F. Organizations and Organizing: Rational, Natural, and Open Systems Perspectives; Pearson Education: Upper Saddle River, NJ, USA, 2007. [Google Scholar]
- Damasio, A.; Damasio, H. Exploring the concept of homeostasis and considering its implications for economics. J. Econ. Behav. Organ. 2016, 126, 125–129. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Leopold, D.A. A redrawn map for the human motor cortex. Nat. News Views 2023, 617, 253–254. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Cornish-Bowden, A.; Cárdenas, M.L.; Letelier, J.C.; Soto-Andrade, J.; Abarzúa, F.G. Understanding the parts in terms of the whole. Biol. Cell 2004, 96, 713–717. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Simon, S.H. The Oxford Solid State Basics; Oxford University Press: Oxford, UK, 2013. [Google Scholar]
- Palmer, T.N. The Primacy of Doubt; Basic Books: New York, NY, USA, 2022. [Google Scholar]
- Kay, J.; King, M. Radical Uncertainty: Decision Making for an Unknowable Future; The Bridge Street Press: London, UK, 2020. [Google Scholar]
- Goelzer, A.; Bekkal Brikci, F.; Martin-Verstraete, I.; Noirot, P.; Bessières, P.; Aymerich, S.; Fromion, V. Reconstruction and analysis of the genetic and metabolic regulatory networks of the central metabolism of Bacillus subtilis. BMC Syst. Biol. 2008, 2, 20. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Buescher, J.M.; Liebermeister, W.; Jules, M.; Uhr, M.; Muntel, J.; Botella, E.; Hessling, B.; Kleijn, R.J.; Le Chat, L.; Lecointe, F.; et al. Global network reorganization during dynamic adaptations of Bacillus subtilis metabolism. Science 2012, 335, 1099–1103. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed]
- Jacob, F.; Monod, J. Genetic regulatory mechanisms in the synthesis of proteins. J. Mol. Biol. 1961, 3, 318–356. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed]
- Monod, J.; Changeux, J.P.; Jacob, F. Allosteric proteins and cellular control systems. J. Mol. Biol. 1963, 6, 306–329. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed]
- Davidson, E.H.; Erwin, D.H. Gene regulatory networks and the evolution of animal body plans. Science 2006, 311, 796–800. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed]
- Kaplow, I.M.; Lawler, A.J.; Schäffer, D.E.; Srinivasan, C.; Sestili, H.H.; Wirthlin, M.E.; Phan, B.N.; Prasad, K.; Brown, A.R.; Zhang, X.; et al. Relating enhancer genetic variation across mammals to complex phenotypes using machine learning. Science 2022, 380, 644. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Collins, J.P.; Gilbert, S.; Laubichler, M.D.; Müller, G.B. Modeling in EvoDevo: How to integrate development, evolution, and ecology. In Modelling Biology; MIT Press: Cambridge, MA, USA, 2007; pp. 355–378. [Google Scholar]
- Friston, K.; Friedman, D.A.; Constant, A.; Knight, V.; Parr, T.; Campbell, J.O. A variational synthesis of evolutionary and developmental dynamics. arXiv 2023, arXiv:2303.04898. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed]
- Szathmáry, E.; Maynard Smith, J. The major evolutionary transitions. Nature 1995, 374, 227–232. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Carney, M. Values: An Economist’s Guide to Everything that Matters; William Collins: London, UK, 2021. [Google Scholar]
- Bellah, R.N.; Madsen, R.; Tipton, S.M.; Sullivan, W.M.; Swidler, A. The Good Society; Alfred Knopf: New York, NY, USA, 1985. [Google Scholar]
- Johnson, S.; Bilovich, A.; Tuckett, D. Conviction narrative theory: A theory of choice under radical uncertainty. Behav. Brain Sci. 2020, 46, e82. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Maslow, A.H. A theory of human motivation. Psychol. Rev. 1943, 50, 370. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Heylighen, F. A cognitive-systemic reconstruction of Maslow’s theory of self-actualization. Behav. Sci. 1992, 37, 39–58. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- MacIntyre, A. After Virtue: A study in Moral Theory; University of Notre Dame Press: Notre Dame, India, 1984. [Google Scholar]
- Heyes, C. Rethinking Norm Psychology. Perspect. Psychol. Sci. 2022. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed]
- Drucker, P. The Practice of Management; Routledge: Oxford, UK, 2012. [Google Scholar]
- Burns, J.M. Transforming Leadership: A New Pursuit of Happiness; Grove Press: New York, NY, USA, 2004. [Google Scholar]
- Burns, J.M. Leadership; Harper Classics: New York, NY, USA, 2010. [Google Scholar]
- Mohr, L.B. The concept of an organisational goal. Am. Political Sci. Rev. 1973, 67, 470–481. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Simon, H.A. Administrative Behavior; Simon and Schuster: New York, NY, USA, 2013. [Google Scholar]
- Etzioni, A. Moral Dimension: Toward a New Economics; Simon and Schuster: New York, NY, USA, 2010. [Google Scholar]
- Dennett, D.C. Elbow Room, New Edition: The Varieties of Free Will Worth Wanting; MIT Press: Cambridge, MA, USA, 2015. [Google Scholar]
- Ismael, J. How Physics Makes Us Free; Oxford University Press: Oxford, UK, 2016. [Google Scholar]
- List, C. Why Free Will Is Real; Harvard: Cambridge, MA, USA, 2019. [Google Scholar]
- Potter, H.D.; Mitchell, K.J. Naturalising agent causation. Entropy 2022, 24, 472. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed]
- Noble, R.; Noble, D. Harnessing stochasticity: How organisms make choices. Chaos 2018, 28, 106309. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed]
- Brown, A.I.; Sivak, D.A. Theory of nonequilibrium free energy transduction by molecular machines. Chem. Rev. 2019, 120, 434–459. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed]
- Ball, P. Organisms as Agents of Evolution; John Templeton Foundation: West Conshohocken, PA, USA, 2023. [Google Scholar]
- Ellis, G. Physics, determinism, and the brain. In Top-Down Causation and Emergence; Vooshholz, J., Gabriel, M., Eds.; Springer: Cham, Germany, 2021. [Google Scholar]
- Carroll, S.M. The Quantum Field Theory on Which the Everyday World Supervenes. In Levels of Reality in Science and Philosophy: Re-Examining the Multi-Level Structure of Reality; Springer International Publishing: Cham, Germany, 2022; pp. 27–46. [Google Scholar]
- Mayer, C. Prosperity: Better Business Makes the Greater Good; Oxford University Press: Oxford, UK, 2018. [Google Scholar]
- Mossio, M.; Moreno, A. Organisational closure in biological organisms. Hist. Philos. Life Sci. 2010, 32, 269–288. [Google Scholar]
- Ellis, G. Physics, complexity and causality. Nature 2005, 435, 743. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Grasso, M.; Albantakis, L.; Lang, J.P.; Tononi, G. Causal reductionism and causal structures. Nat. Neurosci. 2021, 24, 1348–1355. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Horgan, J. The Delusion of Scientific Omniscience. Crosscheck. 2023. Available online: https://blogs.scientificamerican.com/cross-check/the-delusion-of-scientific-omniscience/ (accessed on 11 June 2023).
Level | Agent | Causation | Nature |
---|---|---|---|
L8 | Founder Shareholders | Final | Provide a service; Make a profit |
L7 | Management | Efficient Material | Timetable flights; Buy aircraft; Arrange fuel supply |
L6 | Engineers | Efficient, Material | Design the plane; Manufacture it |
L5 | Passengers | Final | Need for trip |
L4 | Pilot | Efficient | Control aircraft |
L3 | Wing | Formal Material | Provides lift; Provides strength |
L2 | Fluid Flow | Efficient | Bernoulli’s principle |
L1 | Molecules | Efficient | Kinetic theory |
Disclaimer/Publisher’s Note: The statements, opinions and data contained in all publications are solely those of the individual author(s) and contributor(s) and not of MDPI and/or the editor(s). MDPI and/or the editor(s) disclaim responsibility for any injury to people or property resulting from any ideas, methods, instructions or products referred to in the content. |
© 2023 by the author. Licensee MDPI, Basel, Switzerland. This article is an open access article distributed under the terms and conditions of the Creative Commons Attribution (CC BY) license (https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/).
Share and Cite
Ellis, G.F.R. Efficient, Formal, Material, and Final Causes in Biology and Technology. Entropy 2023, 25, 1301. https://doi.org/10.3390/e25091301
Ellis GFR. Efficient, Formal, Material, and Final Causes in Biology and Technology. Entropy. 2023; 25(9):1301. https://doi.org/10.3390/e25091301
Chicago/Turabian StyleEllis, George F. R. 2023. "Efficient, Formal, Material, and Final Causes in Biology and Technology" Entropy 25, no. 9: 1301. https://doi.org/10.3390/e25091301
APA StyleEllis, G. F. R. (2023). Efficient, Formal, Material, and Final Causes in Biology and Technology. Entropy, 25(9), 1301. https://doi.org/10.3390/e25091301