Phishing for (Quantum-Like) Phools—Theory and Experimental Evidence †
Abstract
:1. Introduction
2. Quantum Persuasion
2.1. Bayesian Persuasion
2.2. The Quantum Persuasion Approach
2.3. A 2 × 2 Quantum Decision Model
2.3.1. The Representation of a Choice Alternative
2.3.2. Preferences
2.3.3. Choice
2.3.4. Persuasion
2.3.5. The Impact of Measurements
Compatible Measurements
Incompatible Measurement: Distraction
Example
2.3.6. The Classical Uncertainty Approach
3. Experimental Design
3.1. Testing for the Incompatibility of Perspectives
“About a million refugees (a majority of women and children) escaped persecution in Myanmar. Most of them fled to Bangladesh. The Bengali Red Crescent is the primary humanitarian organization that is providing help to the Rohingyas. They are in immediate need of drinkable water, food, shelter and first medical aid.”
3.2. Main Experiment
“Elephant crisis fund: A virulent wave of poaching is on-going with an elephant killed for its tusks every 15 min. The current population is estimated to around 700,000 elephants in the wild. Driving the killing is international ivory trade that thrives on poverty, corruption, and greed. But there is hope. The Elephant Crisis Fund closely linked to World Wildlife Fund (WWF) exists to encourage collaboration, and deliver rapid impact on the ground to stop the killing, the trafficking, and the demand for ivory.”
“Tiger Forever: Tigers are illegally killed for their pelts and body parts used in traditional Asian medicines. They are also seen as threats to human communities. They suffer from large scale habitat loss due to human population growth and expansion. Tiger Forever was founded 2006 with the goal of reversing global tiger decline. It is active in 17 sites with Non-Governmental Organizations (NGOs) and government partners. The sites host about 2260 tigers or 70% of the total world’s tiger population”
“When considering donating money in support of a project to protect endangered species, different aspects may be relevant to your choice. Let us know what counts most to you:
-The urgency of the cause: among the many important issues in today’s world, does the cause you consider belong to those that deserve urgent action? or
-The honesty of the organization to which you donate: do you trust the organization managing the project to be reliable; i.e., do you trust the money will be used as advertised rather than diverted.”
“Did you know that most Elephant and Tiger projects are run by Non-Governmental Organizations (NGOs)? But NGOs are not always honest! NGOs operating in countries with endemic corruption face particular risks. NGOs are created by enthusiastic benevolent citizens who often lack proper competence to manage both internal and external risks. Numerous scandals have shown how even long standing NGOs had been captured by less scrupulous people to serve their own interest. So a reasonable concern is whether Tiger Forever respectively Elephant Crisis Fund deserves our trust.”
“Did you know that global wildlife populations have declined 58% since 1970, primarily due to habitat destruction, over-hunting and pollution. It is urgent to reverse the decline! “For the first time since the demise of the dinosaurs 65 million years ago, we face a global mass extinction of wildlife. We ignore the decline of other species at our peril–for they are the barometer that reveals our impact on the world that sustains us.” —Mike Barrett, director of science and policy at WWF’s UK branch. A reasonable concern is how urgent protecting tigers or elephants actually is.”
The General Information Screens
3.3. Theoretical Predictions
- The Bayesian model predicts no effect in both treatment groups.
- The quantum model predicts that the distraction treatment group should exhibit a significantly different allocation of responses compared with the control group’s choice profile. It also predicts some milder impact of the question in the compatible treatment compared with the control group. It should be emphasized that since we lack information about the correlation coefficients between the two perspectives and the utility values, we do not have quantitative predictions. Generally, the less correlated two perspectives (in the example of Section 2 they were fully uncorrelated) the larger the expected impact in terms of switching the choice for given utility values.
4. Results
4.1. Descriptive Statistics
4.1.1. Data Analysis
General Results
Advanced Results
4.1.2. Interpretation
5. Concluding Remarks and Discussion
Author Contributions
Funding
Institutional Review Board Statement
Informed Consent Statement
Data Availability Statement
Acknowledgments
Conflicts of Interest
Appendix A
Dependent Variable: | ||||
---|---|---|---|---|
Decision_ECF | ||||
(1) | (2) | (3) | (4) | |
QComp | −0.176 | −0.170 | −0.172 | −0.186 |
(0.134) | (0.134) | (0.134) | (0.137) | |
QIncomp | −0.475 | −0.476 | −0.477 | −0.451 |
(0.160) | (0.160) | (0.160) | (0.162) | |
Honesty | 0.267 | 0.356 | 0.258 | |
(0.128) | (0.185) | (0.129) | ||
ET | 0.039 | 0.160 | 0.045 | |
(0.116) | (0.216) | (0.117) | ||
Honesty:ET | −0.171 | |||
(0.256) | ||||
Reread_ Descriptions | −0.093 | |||
(0.185) | ||||
Age | 0.005 | |||
(0.006) | ||||
Male | −0.189 | |||
(0.121) | ||||
Education | 0.021 | |||
(0.083) | ||||
NGO | 0.006 | |||
(0.121) | ||||
Constant | 0.371 | 0.158 | 0.096 | 0.066 |
(0.103) | (0.151) | (0.177) | (0.306) | |
Observations | 1211 | 1211 | 1211 | 1211 |
Log Likelihood | −829.852 | −827.610 | −827.387 | −825.591 |
Akaike Inf. Crit. | 1665.704 | 1665.219 | 1666.775 | 1671.183 |
Bayesian Inf. Crit. | 1681.002 | 1690.715 | 1697.370 | 1722.175 |
References
- P & G: Thank You, Mom|Wieden+Kennedy. Available online: https://www.wk.com/work/p-and-g-thank-you-mom/ (accessed on 16 January 2021).
- Packard, V. The Hidden Persuaders; McKay: New York, NY, USA, 1957. [Google Scholar]
- Cialdini, R.B.; Cialdini, R.B. Influence: The Psychology of Persuasion; Collins: New York, NY, USA, 2007; p. 55. [Google Scholar]
- Petty, R.E.; Cacioppo, J.T. Communication and Persuasion: Central and Peripheral Routes to Attitude Change; Springer Science and Business Media: Berlin, Germany, 2012. [Google Scholar]
- Festinger, L.; Maccoby, N. On resistance to persuasive communications. J. Abnorm. Soc. 1964, 68, 359. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed]
- Baron, R.S.; Baron, P.H.; Miller, N. The relation between distraction and persuasion. Psychol. Bull. 1973, 80, 310. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Petty, R.E.; Wells, G.L.; Brock, T.C. Distraction can enhance or reduce yielding to propaganda: Thought disruption versus effort justification. J. Personal. Soc. Psychol. 1976, 34, 874. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Petty, R.E.; Cacioppo, J.T. The elaboration likelihood model of persuasion. In Communication and Persuasion; Springer: New York, NY, USA, 1986; pp. 1–24. [Google Scholar]
- DellaVigna, S.; Gentzkow, M. Persuasion: Empirical evidence. Annu. Rev. Econ. 2010, 2, 643–669. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
- Dudukovic, N.M.; DuBrow, S.; Wagner, A.D. Attention during memory retrieval enhances future remembering. Mem. Cogn. 2009, 37, 953–961. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed] [Green Version]
- Fernandes, M.A.; Moscovitch, M. Divided attention and memory: Evidence of substantial interference effects at retrieval and encoding. J. Exp. Psychol. Gen. 2000, 129, 155. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Kahneman, D. Thinking Fast and Slow, 1st ed.; Farrar, Straus and Giroux: New York, NY, USA, 2011. [Google Scholar]
- Akerlof, G.; Shiller, R. Phishing for Phools—The Economics of Manipulation and Deception; Princeton University Press: Princeton, NJ, USA, 2015. [Google Scholar]
- Tversky, A.; Kahneman, D. The framing of decisions and the psychology of choice. Science 1981, 211, 453–458. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
- Chong, D.; Druckman, J. Framing Theory. Annu. Rev. Polit. Sci. 2007, 10, 103–126. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Dehaene, S.; Naccache, L.; Le Clec’H, G.; Koechlin, E.; Mueller, M.; Dehaene-Lambertz, G.; Le Bihan, D. Imaging unconscious semantic priming. Nature 1998, 395, 597–600. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Taylor, S.E. The Availability Bias in Social Perception and Interaction. In Judgment under Uncertainty: Heuristics and Biases; Kahneman, D., Slovic, P., Tversky, A., Eds.; Cambridge University Press: New York, NY, USA, 1982. [Google Scholar]
- Latham, G. Unanswered questions and new directions for future research on priming goals in the subconscious. Acad. Manag. Discov. 2019, 5, 111–113. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Bargh, J.A. The historical origins of priming as the preparation of behavioral responses: Unconscious carryover and contextual influences of real-world importance. Soc. Cogn. 2014, 32, 209–224. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Bargh, J.A. Before You Know It: The Unconscious Reasons We Do What We Do; Simon & Schuster: New York, NY, USA, 2017. [Google Scholar]
- Dijksterhuis, A.; Aarts, H. Goals, attention, and (un) consciousness. Annu. Rev. Psychol. 2010, 61, 467–490. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed] [Green Version]
- Dubois, F.; Lambert-Mogiliansky, A. Our (represented) world and quantum-like object. In Contextuality in Quantum Physics and Psychology; Advanced Series in Mathematical Psychology; Dzhafarov, E., Scott, J., Ru, Z., Cervantes, V., Eds.; World Scientific: Singapore, 2016; Volume 6, pp. 367–387. [Google Scholar]
- Danilov, V.I.; Lambert-Mogiliansky, A. Targeting in Persuasion Problems. J. Math. Econ. 2018, 78, 142–149. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Benjamin, D.J. Errors in probabilistic reasoning and judgment biases. In Handbook of Behavioral Economics—Foundations and Applications 2; Bernheim, B.D., DellaVigna, S., Laibson, D., Eds.; North-Holland: Amsterdam, The Netherlands, 2019; Chapter 2; pp. 69–186. [Google Scholar]
- Camerer, C. Bounded rationality in individual decision making. Exp. Econ. 1998, 1, 163–183. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Edwards, W. Conservatism in human information processing. In Judgment under Uncertainty: Heuristics and Biases; Kahneman, D., Slovic, P., Tversky, A., Eds.; Cambridge University Press: Cambridge, UK, 1982; pp. 359–369. [Google Scholar]
- Grether, D.M. Testing Bayes rule and the representativeness heuristic: Some experimental evidence. J. Econ. Behav. Organ. 1992, 17, 31–57. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
- Tversky, A.; Kahneman, D. Extensional versus intuitive reasoning: The conjunction fallacy in probability judgment. Psychol. Rev. 1983, 90, 293. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Zizzo, D.J.; Stolarz-Fantino, S.; Wen, J.; Fantino, E. A violation of the monotonicity axiom: Experimental evidence on the conjunction fallacy. J. Econ. Behav. Organ. 2000, 41, 263–276. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Bruza, P.; Busemeyer, J.R. Quantum Cognition and Decision-Making; Cambridge University Press: Cambridge, UK, 2012. [Google Scholar]
- Haven, E.; Khrennikov, A. The Palgrave Handbook of Quantum Models in Social Science; Macmillan Publishers Ltd.: London, UK, 2017; pp. 1–17. [Google Scholar]
- Khrennikov, A.; Basieva, I.; Dzhafarov, E.N.; Busemeyer, J.R. Quantum models for psychological measurements: An unsolved problem. PLoS ONE 2014, 9, e110909. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
- Ozawa, M.; Khrennikov, A. Application of theory of quantum instruments to psychology: Combination of question order effect with response replicability effect. Entropy 2020, 22, 37. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
- Bagarello, F.; Basieva, I.; Khrennikov, A. Quantum field inspired model of decision making: Asymptotic stabilization of belief state via interaction with surrounding mental environment. J. Math. Psychol. 2018, 82, 159–168. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
- Basieva, I.; Cervantes, V.H.; Dzhafarov, E.N.; Khrennikov, A. True Contextuality Beats Direct Influences in Human Decision Making. J. Exp. Psychol. Gen. 2019, 148, 1925–1937. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed] [Green Version]
- Aerts, D.; Haven, E.; Sozzo, S. A proposal to extend expected utility in a quantum probabilistic framework. Econ. Theory 2018, 65, 1079–1109. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
- Danilov, V.I.; Lambert-Mogiliansky, A. Expected Utility under Non-classical Uncertainty. Theory Decis. 2010, 68, 25–47. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Danilov, V.I.; Lambert-Mogiliansky, A.; Vergopoulos, V. Dynamic consistency of expected utility under non-classical (quantum) uncertainty. Theory Decis. 2018, 84, 645–670. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
- Danilov, V.I.; Lambert-Mogiliansky, A. Preparing a (quantum) belief system. Theor. Comput. Sci. 2018, 752, 97–103. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
- Cohen-Tannoudji, C.; Diu, B.; Laloë, F. Mécanique Quantique; Hermann, EDP Sciences: Paris, France, 2000. [Google Scholar]
- Kamenica, E.; Gentzkow, M. Bayesian Persuasion. Am. Econ. Rev. 2011, 101, 2590–2615. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
- Bloedel, A.W.; Segal, I.R. Persuasion with Rational Inattention. Available online: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3164033 (accessed on 16 April 2018).
- Lipnowski, E.; Mathevet, L. Disclosure to a psychological audience. Am. Econ. J. Microeconom. 2018, 10, 67–93. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
- Galperti, S. Persuasion: The Art of Changing Worldviews. Am. Econ. Rev. 2019, 109, 996–1031. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
- De Clippel, G.; Zhang, Z. Non-Bayesian Persuasion; Working Paper; Brown University: Providence, RI, USA, 2020. [Google Scholar]
- Broekaert, J.B.; Busemeyer, J.R.; Pothos, E.M. The disjunction effect in two-stage simulated gambles. An experimental study and comparison of a heuristic logistic, Markov and quantum-like model. Cogn. Psychol. 2020, 117, 101262. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Busemeyer, J.R.; Wang, Z.; Shiffrin, R.S. Bayesian model comparison favors quantum over standard decision theory account of dynamic inconsistency. Decision 2015, 2, 1–12. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
- Denolf, J.; Martínez-Martínez, I.; Josephy, H.; Barque-Duran, A. A quantum-like model for complementarity of preferences and beliefs in dilemma games. J. Math. Psychol. 2016, 78, 96–106. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
- Moreira, C.; Wichert, A. Are quantum-like Bayesian networks more powerful than classical Bayesian networks? J. Math. Psychol. 2018, 82, 73–83. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Dzhafarov, E.; Scott, J.; Ru, Z.; Cervantes, V. (Eds.) Contextuality from Quantum Physics to Psychology; Advanced Series in Mathematical Psychology; World Scientific: Singapore, 2016; Volume 6, ISBN 978-981-4730-62-4. [Google Scholar]
- Wang, Z.; Busemeyer, J.R.; DeBuys, B. Beliefs, action and rationality in strategical decisions. Top. Cogn. Sci. 2020, in press. [Google Scholar]
- Bartneck, C.; Duenser, A.; Moltchanova, E.; Zawieska, K. Comparing the similarity of responses received from studies in Amazon’s Mechanical Turk to studies conducted online and with direct recruitment. PLoS ONE 2015, 10, e0121595. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed]
- Kees, J.; Berry, C.; Burton, S.; Sheehan, K. An analysis of data quality: Professional panels, student subject pools, and Amazon’s Mechanical Turk. J. Advert. 2017, 46, 141–155. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Festinger, L. A Theory of Cognitive Dissonance; Stanford University Press: Stanford, CA, USA, 1957; Volume 2. [Google Scholar]
- Lambert-Mogiliansky, A.; Zamir, S.; Zwirn, H. Type-Indeterminacy a Model of the KT (Kahnemann and Tversky) Man. J. Math. Psychol. 2009, 53, 349–361. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
- Lambert-Mogiliansky, A. Quantum Type Indeterminacy in Dynamic Decision-Making: Self-Control through Identity Management. Games 2012, 3, 97–118. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
Dependent Variable: | |||||||||
---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|
Decision_ECF | |||||||||
General | Hon | Urg | ET | TE | ET-Hon | TE-Hon | ET-Urg | TE-Urg | |
Compatible condition | −0.170 | −0.142 | −0.231 | −0.181 | −0.175 | −0.164 | −0.154 | −0.216 | −0.263 |
t = −1.363 | t = −0.938 | t = −1.030 | t = −1.063 | t = −0.958 | t = −0.807 | t = −0.683 | t = −0.669 | t = −0.833 | |
Incompatible condition | −0.363 | −0.336 | −0.455 | −0.249 | −0.488 | −0.142 | −0.523 | −0.510 | −0.404 |
t = −2.791 | t = −2.152 | t = −1.953 | t = −1.307 | t = −2.763 | t = −0.591 | t = −2.563 | t = −1.658 | t = −1.129 | |
Honesty | 0.294 | 0.196 | 0.407 | ||||||
t = 1.998 | t = 1.007 | t = 1.809 | |||||||
Order (ECF-TF) | 0.046 | −0.014 | 0.209 | ||||||
t = 0.383 | t = −0.101 | t = 0.868 | |||||||
Reread Descriptions | −0.088 | −0.178 | 0.341 | −0.057 | −0.117 | −0.139 | −0.209 | 0.374 | 0.241 |
t = −0.502 | t = −0.941 | t = 0.720 | t = −0.225 | t = −0.467 | t = −0.508 | t = −0.777 | t = 0.566 | t = 0.354 | |
Age | 0.005 | 0.008 | −0.002 | 0.006 | 0.003 | 0.002 | 0.015 | 0.019 | −0.022 |
t = 0.894 | t = 1.198 | t = −0.186 | t = 0.826 | t = 0.394 | t = 0.227 | t = 1.455 | t = 1.245 | t = −1.513 | |
Male | −0.172 | −0.128 | −0.262 | −0.067 | −0.274 | −0.086 | −0.184 | −0.119 | −0.390 |
t = −1.566 | t = −0.952 | t = −1.348 | t = −0.414 | t = −1.836 | t = −0.447 | t = −0.968 | t = −0.393 | t = −1.518 | |
Education | 0.021 | 0.006 | 0.072 | 0.002 | 0.026 | −0.011 | 0.012 | 0.032 | 0.116 |
t = 0.252 | t = 0.064 | t = 0.450 | t = 0.019 | t = 0.210 | t = −0.085 | t = 0.080 | t = 0.147 | t = 0.479 | |
NGO | 0.006 | 0.038 | −0.062 | 0.190 | −0.187 | 0.356 | −0.272 | −0.167 | 0.137 |
t = 0.051 | t = 0.259 | t = −0.287 | t = 1.058 | t = −1.154 | t = 1.554 | t = −1.446 | t = −0.589 | t = 0.392 | |
Constant | 0.068 | 0.251 | 0.317 | −0.028 | 0.303 | 0.292 | 0.253 | −0.213 | 1.559 |
t = 0.216 | t = 0.617 | t = 0.534 | t = −0.068 | t = 0.597 | t = 0.528 | t = 0.419 | t = −0.329 | t = 1.240 | |
Observations | 1211 | 864 | 347 | 638 | 573 | 458 | 406 | 180 | 167 |
Log Likelihood | −825.591 | −586.663 | −237.452 | −436.394 | −385.940 | −311.893 | −269.413 | −122.258 | −112.568 |
Akaike Inf. Crit. | 1671.183 | 1191.325 | 492.904 | 890.788 | 789.879 | 639.786 | 554.825 | 260.515 | 241.136 |
General | Hon | Urg | ET | TE | ET_Hon | TE_Hon | ET_Urg | TE_Urg | |
---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|
Difference | −0.111 | −0.101 | −0.149 | −0.070 | −0.163 | −0.037 | −0.179 | −0.174 | −0.125 |
p-value | 0.005 | 0.031 | 0.051 | 0.191 | 0.006 | 0.555 | 0.010 | 0.097 | 0.259 |
Publisher’s Note: MDPI stays neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations. |
© 2021 by the authors. Licensee MDPI, Basel, Switzerland. This article is an open access article distributed under the terms and conditions of the Creative Commons Attribution (CC BY) license (http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/).
Share and Cite
Lambert-Mogiliansky, A.; Calmettes, A. Phishing for (Quantum-Like) Phools—Theory and Experimental Evidence. Symmetry 2021, 13, 162. https://doi.org/10.3390/sym13020162
Lambert-Mogiliansky A, Calmettes A. Phishing for (Quantum-Like) Phools—Theory and Experimental Evidence. Symmetry. 2021; 13(2):162. https://doi.org/10.3390/sym13020162
Chicago/Turabian StyleLambert-Mogiliansky, Ariane, and Adrian Calmettes. 2021. "Phishing for (Quantum-Like) Phools—Theory and Experimental Evidence" Symmetry 13, no. 2: 162. https://doi.org/10.3390/sym13020162
APA StyleLambert-Mogiliansky, A., & Calmettes, A. (2021). Phishing for (Quantum-Like) Phools—Theory and Experimental Evidence. Symmetry, 13(2), 162. https://doi.org/10.3390/sym13020162