1. What Is Policy on Religion?
What is policy on religion? Although we use this concept relatively often, especially in post-communist countries in which dedicated ministries or their confessional departments existed, generally when someone speaks on this matter, one does not speak about policy but about law on religion, i.e., the law regarding religion, religious communities, and religious institutions. The law, however, is something different than policy. It is, in a sense, a tool, and the fruit of policy. Therefore, we create law in order to achieve certain political goals, and at the same time, we use law as one of the instruments of political action. Thus, if policy is a conscious action striving to achieve goals that directly or indirectly concern the life of the polis, i.e., a political community (in the etymological sense), then the law is only its element in the above sense.
If the state were to pursue policy on religion, i.e., policy regarding religious communities and institutions, the question arises about the reasons for, and objectives of such action. In other words, why should the state be interested in religion and religious communities at all? It seems that at least five reasons for such interest can be enumerated. Firstly, there exist theocratic countries in the world, in which policy is treated (at least theoretically) as a tool for realizing God’s will and a help in bringing their subjects to salvation. Secondly, we had and have ideological countries in the world (e.g., China or North Korea) in which the given ideology plays the role of a “secular religion”. Any other religion in this situation is the competition in the struggle for the “souls” of citizens. The existence of any institutions, including religious ones, which would not be subject to state control, is also unacceptable. Therefore, the state is interested in religion in order to “neutralize” it. Thirdly, ever since Plato’s time, religion has been seen as one of the potential instruments of political action. Plato did not mean that religious leaders could set themselves political goals, but on the contrary: he was convinced that the state could not be governed without reference to religious motivation. Religion gives political power legitimacy, and at the same time motivates people to obey despite the fact that this power does not promise perfect justice, for a religious man knows that this is meted out by the gods in another aeon. We are dealing here with an attempt by the state to instrumentalize religion for political purposes, which can be done in good or bad faith, although in both cases it is an offense against religious freedom.
1 Fourthly, a multicultural state may perceive religion as a source of potential social conflict. Therefore, it may be afraid of something like “religious wars” between religiously diverse sectors of society, or the melting of religion and some ideology considered dangerous, such as religious fundamentalism or nationalism. Feeling responsible for social peace, the state may want to take action aimed at establishing or maintaining it. It seems that nowadays in Europe this is the main reason for the state’s interest in Islam, as it is the religion of the majority of immigrants arriving on the Old Continent. Here, an important question arises about the ability of European societies to integrate new arrivals and about the willingness of immigrants themselves to become part of Western society. Fifthly, the state may perceive religion as one of the essential elements of the common good. A little American style, it may be interested in people being religious, but without supporting any particular religion. This list is certainly not exhaustive.
The question arises as to what substantive competences the state has to deal with religion at all. In the first case, the state, most often due to some form of integration of spiritual leaders into political institutions, considers itself an expert, most often the best expert in religious and political matters. In the second and third cases, the state deems the above question explicitly or implicitly irrelevant, i.e., actually performs the act of usurpation. In the fourth and fifth cases, it can be expected that this question will be dealt with by the state with due seriousness. In fact, this is not always the case. Still, it is worth trying to describe the nature of the problems we face in these cases.
First, to deal with religion competently, one must answer the question of what religion is. Even when it comes to the etymology of the word, the matter is not clear whether it comes from
relegere or from
religare.
2 The question also arises whether it is right to use the same term “religion” for phenomena as diverse as animism, Hinduism, Buddhism, Confucianism, Islam, Judaism, and Christianity. Are faith in personal and impersonal god(s), monotheistic and polytheistic beliefs, or referring to transcendence and “intra-worldliness” focused on dogma and concentrated on rituals? Aware of the incompatibility of these such different phenomena, some thinkers came to conclusion that Christianity is not a religion, or is a religion that goes beyond the concept of religion (
la religion de la sortie de la religion) (
Marion 2017, pp. 74–77). Others concluded that Christianity is the sole religion that it is a religion only, while other beliefs are something else, as they have some additional, non-religious element built in.
3 If there is ambiguity in defining this phenomenon, both in terms of philosophy and theological debates, then how would the state know what religion is and what it should be? The recognition of the incompetence of the state in this area is the basic premise underlying the idea of the separation of state and religion. This thesis should also be considered true when it was demanded—as in the case of John Locke—in the name of social peace. Locke does not promote the idea of a crypto-religious state that, due to social agreement, conceals its religious preferences. What he means is recognizing that beliefs that do not have an impact on social life are not relevant from the point of view of state power and, therefore, should be removed from the field of political disputes.
4 The idea of tolerance understood in this way implicitly believes that, at least in the said area of doctrinal disputes, state authority is not competent. It does not know, therefore, which religious doctrine is more effective when it comes to the possibility of getting to heaven (
Locke 1983).
Jean-Luc Marion proposes that Pascal’s distinction of the “three orders” be used to explain the causes of state incompetence. In his “Thoughts”, Pascal clearly distinguishes the “order of the flesh” (
l’ordre de la chair), the “order of the mind” (
l’ordre de l’esprit), and the “order of the heart” (
l’ordre du coeur). These orders are infinitely distant from one another and radically different, such that people living in one of them do not need what is considered great in the other, and do not understand what this greatness is about. “The greatness of clever men is invisible to kings, to the rich, to chiefs, and to all the worldly great. The greatness of wisdom, which is nothing if not of God, is invisible to the carnal-minded and to the clever. These are three orders differing in kind” (
Pascal 1958, 792, p. 234). Pascal sees these three orders as hierarchically arranged (
Manon 2009). Therefore, the carnal-minded have their temporal kingdom in which power, wealth, and other temporal goods are valued. “Great geniuses have their power, their glory, their greatness, their victory, their lustre, and have no need of worldly greatness, with which they are not in keeping. (...) The saints have their power, their glory, their victory, their lustre, and need no worldly or intellectual greatness, with which they have no affinity; (...). They are seen of God and the angels, and not of the body, nor of the curious mind. God is enough for them.” (
Pascal 1958, 792, p. 234). The self-sufficiency of the inhabitants of the “kingdom of holiness” stems from the fact that “All bodies together, and all minds together, and all their products, are not equal to the least feeling of charity. This is of an order infinitely more exalted.” (
Pascal 1958, 792, p. 235). The tyranny of state power—according to Pascal—“consists in the desire of universal power beyond its scope.” (
Pascal 1958, 332, p. 94). Therefore, whoever, having power in one sphere, tries to extend it to other orders outside his competence, deserves only the name of usurper. “Tyranny is the wish to have in one way what can only be had in another.” (ibid). Therefore, the basis of the properly understood principle of separation of state and religion is the state recognizing its incompetence in the religious field and giving up any attempts to usurp. State power belongs to a different order.
It seems that this way of explication needs to be slightly nuanced. Even though the state does not know what religion is, it does not follow that among state officials no one knows it. After all, among them there are also religious people. Their knowledge and religious sense somehow translate into the functioning of the state, although they do not extend to it any additional competence. This state could be called
docta ignorantia—learned ignorance, with learnedness rooted in individuals as private persons.
5 Therefore, the state, using the resources of private knowledge of its officials, knows at least where it is not competent, which means that at the interface of these two areas it does not have to move like a bull in a china shop. Secondly, since the School of Salamanca, we have known that between the two spheres, temporal and spiritual, there spreads the area of so-called mixed matters (
res mixtae), the management of which is a concerted decision of both authorities: spiritual and secular. Over time, this led to the development in Europe of a model of autonomy, independence, and healthy cooperation between the institutions of the state and the Church, as enshrined, for example, in the Council Constitution
Gaudium et Spes6.
2. The Specificity of EU’s Policy on Religion
Thinking of the European Union as a political body, we are facing another difficulty. It is undoubtedly an international organization, but with a very specific status, with a much broader scope of competence vis-à-vis its member states. We say that it is sui generis, or one of a kind. Therefore, unlike the member states, it does not enjoy a presumption of competence arising from the principle of state sovereignty. It only has as many competences as the member states have explicitly delegated to it, and these competences are exercised jointly, whatever that may mean.
When answering the question regarding the Union’s competences in the religious field, it must be said that it has far fewer than any member state. However, this is not only a presumption based on the fact that the member states did not transfer any power in this area, but a claim firmly established in EU primary law. This was expressed positively first in the so-called Amsterdam Declaration, and then in Art. 17 of the Treaty on the Functioning of the European Union, where in paragraph 1 we read: “The Union respects and does not prejudice the status under national law of churches and religious associations or communities in the Member States.” This sentence should be interpreted primarily in a negative sense. If political entities in Europe have any competence to create law regarding religion, it is reserved only for the member states. It can be concluded from some acts of secondary law that the EU institutions do not always feel comfortable with this provision of primary law and sometimes they happen to cite it with some inaccuracy. Suffice it to look at the EU regulation on personal data protection (GDPR), which entered into force in May 2018.
7 This lack of comfort indicates that in the EU institutions there exists a desire, not quite articulated, to have competence also in the religious field. However, this is not just idle desire.
So how is EU policy and law regarding religion actually formulated? Certainly, one can speak here of a sui generis policy on religion, understood and implemented entirely differently than at the level of the nation-state. In view of the lack of EU competence in the religious field, it would be interesting to track how EU institutions are making an increasing number of decisions that have a direct impact on the lives of churches and religious communities. In general, we can say that EU practice, not only in this area, most often involves “processing” issues that fall outside the Union’s competence into issues falling within the competence of the EU institutions. For example, education is perceived as a service, an abortion pill as a manifestation of concern for the health of consumers, an in vitro procedure as an element of care for the quality of medical equipment, the issue of ritual slaughter of animals as an environmental protection problem, the issue of availability of kosher meat in shops as an issue of consumers’ access to food information, and the issue of work-free Sunday as a transport organisation issue. It would be interesting to trace thoroughly the legal bases cited in EU acts in which the word religion or the Church appears, as well as in those that actually have a significant impact on the life of religious communities. Given the lack of competence, elements of policy on religion are often articulated in documents belonging to the so-called soft law, e.g. in declarations and resolutions of the European Parliament. The mechanism for transforming issues not covered by EU competences into issues falling under these competences has been described in detail in the context of bioethical issues, as included in
An Overview Report on Bioethics in the European Union (
COMECE 2009), prepared by the COMECE Secretariat. Simply put, lack of competence is not an insurmountable barrier when it comes to the ability of the European Commission to conduct policy and make decisions. The effect of this approach to policy on religion is something that could be called the body of EU law on religion in statu nascendi with quite specific content, because the Union often regulates those aspects of the life of religious communities that, from the point of view of the nation-state, are not associated with religion at all. The method of regulating these issues is also specific, as it is most often an indirect action, e.g. officially the labelling of goods is addressed, but the result of the solutions taken may be depriving Judaism and Islam followers of access to food that meets the requirements imposed by their religion. Another example can be the dispute about non-discrimination in the labour market, which could have resulted in an EU order to ordain women as priests in the Catholic Church. The most frequently cited counterargument to accusations of non-compliance by the EU institutions with the principle of non-interference in religious matters is that this is not about intervening in the lives of churches and religious communities as religious entities, but interventions only to the extent that their activities fall under EU competence (
Puza 2012, p. 53). Admittedly, this body of EU law on religion is just being created, but undoubtedly, in recent years the network of EU law, which determines some aspects of the life of religious communities, is definitely thickening.
It is also characteristic that the EU generally is rather generous regarding financial support for churches and religious associations (e.g., Caritas, Diakonia). These are primarily earmarked for the conservation and restoration of monuments, charitable activities, the integration of immigrants, etc. Behind the scenes in the EC, however, one can hear the advice to prepare applications in such a way that they are not associated with religion. It seems that this type of generosity might result from both realism and the desire to ensure the goodwill on the part of churches.
3. EU Primary Law
Although, as has been said, the law is not the same thing as policy, we can give substance to begin our reflection by showing the elements of policy on religion, which emerged during the discussion of EU law. Let us begin with EU primary law. Firstly, the disputes should be mentioned over the attempt to include in the preamble of the EU treaty a reference to Christian inspiration in the history of Europe: first in connection with the establishment of the Charter of Fundamental Rights, and then the Constitutional Treaty (later: the Lisbon Treaty)
8. Both debates showed that, among member states, there is a deep division regarding attitude towards Christianity and diversity of views with regard to the understanding of the principle of state’s neutrality vis-à-vis religion. It should be noted that the subject of the dispute was not an intention to make the EU a religious organization, but only the inclusion in the preamble of the aforementioned documents of reference to the Christian cultural heritage, which was a historical, cultural, and sociological information/declaration. During the debates, it was not proposed to use the formula invocatio Dei, but only—in the maximalist versions—nominatio Dei, and in the minimalist versions the word “Christianity” itself. In both cases, it turned out to be impossible due to opposition from Belgium and France. The representative of the latter country made use of the argument that such a reference would be inconsistent with the constitutional tradition of France and the principle of secularism (
laicité) contained in it
9. This dispute shows that one “important” member state is able to block the will expressed by many or even the majority of member states and significantly influence the legal solutions adopted in this field. We witnessed a similar situation in the context of the dispute over the so-called Amsterdam Declaration. In each of the three cases cited, a compromise was finally reached, although the path that led to reaching the final solution was different. In the case of the Amsterdam Declaration, it was finally adopted thanks to the persistence of Germany, and more specifically, Chancellor Helmut Kohl, but at the same time lowering the rank of the document from the proposed protocol to the level of the declaration. In the case of the Charter of Fundamental Rights, it was agreed that there would be a discrepancy between the official French and German versions of its text, responsibility for which would be placed on EU translators. The French text thus recalls
le patrimoine spirituel et moral, and the German text recalls
das geistig-religiösen und sittlichen Erbe. The English text is consistent with the French. Officially, both expressions are synonymous. In the case of the preamble to the Treaty on European Union, instead of recalling the Christian roots of Europe, we have a reference to the “cultural, religious and humanist heritage of Europe”. At the same time, EU politicians in their talks often used the argument that “religious” in Europe means “Christian”, which is obvious to everyone and therefore the expressions are synonymous. If we ask where the reluctance to use the word “Christianity” came from, apart from the possible ideological hostility of some politicians, one can cite an argument closely related to the sense of invocatio or nominatio Dei in constitutional documents, or rather to avoidance of this reference. It can be seen either as an attempt to distance oneself from the European tradition of separation of state and religion (a shift from the model of friendly separation to the French model of hostile separation) or as the intention to part with invoking religious arguments to justify the inviolability of human rights. If the latter argument were true, it would be equivalent to striving to bring about an anthropological change in EU policy and, consequently, a reinterpretation of the entire doctrine of human rights.
10The correctness of the above assumption seems to be proved by the change introduced by the EU Charter of Fundamental Rights in the way of defining the institution of marriage. Article 9 of the Charter reads: “The right to marry and the right to found a family shall be guaranteed in accordance with the national laws governing the exercise of these rights.” The meaning of this sentence can be read only in the context of the change it introduces in relation to Article 12 of the European Convention on Human Rights—ECHR, which expressly states that such a right applies to a man and woman of marriageable age. The resignation from explicitly mentioning a man and a woman is explained in the Explanations to the CFR by the desire to “modernize” the definition of marriage.
11 We often witness a similar approach with regard to other human rights at the level of secondary law.
The third area of primary law, significant from this point of view, is the description of the right to religious freedom in Article 10 of the Charter of Fundamental Rights. It must be admitted that in this case there were no modernization attempts. The description contained in paragraph 1 is “classic” and includes all aspects of the right to religious freedom, with the exception of its institutional dimension. “Everyone has the right to freedom of thought, conscience and religion. This right includes freedom to change religion or belief and freedom, either alone or in community with others and in public or in private, to manifest religion or belief, in worship, teaching, practice and observance.” In the explanations to the Charter, it was stated that this right has the same content and scope as Article 9 of the European Convention, also when it comes to the possibility of limiting this right in accordance with Article 9 (2) of the ECHR. In this context, Article 10 (2) of the Charter additionally mentions the right to conscientious objection. “The right to conscientious objection is recognised, in accordance with the national laws governing the exercise of this right.”
The institutional dimension of religious freedom is referred to in the already mentioned Article 17 of the Treaty on the Functioning of the European Union, where in paragraph 1 we read: “The Union respects and does not prejudice the status under national law of churches and religious associations or communities in the Member States.” This provision is seemingly conservative. Therefore, the Union does not intend to change anything when it comes to the functioning of churches in the member states, and therefore—one would like to say—it does not conduct any policy on religion. However, Article 17 is not limited to the first paragraph, but also contains two more. In paragraph 2—a complete novelty—the Treaty repeats almost literally the same formula but with regard to philosophical and non-confessional organizations. Placing them in the same article, and not, for example, in Article 15 concerning civil society or in a separate article designated only to them means that from the point of view of EU law, they are entities of the same or very similar type as churches and religious communities. It is a political decision whereby the Union grants philosophical and non-confessional associations, with a total number of around 100–200 thousand members in Europe, the same status as churches and religious communities representing around 85 per cent of EU citizens. This is of particular significance in the context of paragraph 3 of the same article, in which we read: “Recognising their identity and their specific contribution, the Union shall maintain an open, transparent and regular dialogue with these churches and organisations.”
12 This paragraph applies to the same extent to entities falling under paragraphs 1 and 2.
Strictly political elements also appear in the way this dialogue is to be organized. The first question is, are these organizations and churches to conduct this dialogue together, i.e., in the framework of the same meetings, or separately? Secondly, in the latter case, how numerous should be the representations of the respective entities? Thirdly, what is the practical implementation of the postulate of neutrality vis-à-vis religion on the part of EU institutions? Regarding the first question, attention should be paid to a completely different dynamic of the debate when, on the one side, we have the representatives of EU institutions, and on the other, representatives of churches and religious communities, as the perception of political reality by organizations of a religious nature is, despite all the differences, quite similar. The dynamics of meetings is completely different, when representatives of churches and non-confessional associations (which, in practice, denotes atheistic and masonic organizations) sit together in front of EU officials. In the latter case, the demands made by the participants usually cancel each other out. In the first case, it is possible to reach some common conclusions; in the second, we have a zero-sum debate. Regarding the second question, it should be stated that it is possible to organize such a meeting according to the principle of geometric (proportionate) equality (the number of members of delegations of individual entities is proportional to the number of their members in the EU). However, it should be taken into account that in such situation we would have to deal with Catholic domination, as approximately 50% of EU citizens belong to this Church. The use of the principle of degressive proportionality could be conceivable, as in the case of national representations in the European Parliament. Although there exist practical ways of addressing the issue of fair representation of the different entities, in practice they are never used, which in itself is a political decision. For example, one of the meetings of the dialogue in the European Parliament in 2012 was attended by 15 representatives from various entities falling under Article 17. Seven were religious in nature, seven were secular, and one could be placed somewhere in between. This means that a small atheistic organization or Masonic lodge had as many representatives (one per each entity represented) as the Catholic or Protestant Church and had the same length of time allotted in discussion. Perhaps this would not pose a major problem if it were not for the practical answer to the third question regarding neutrality, for it is sometimes understood in such a way that equal weight is attached to each statement. Therefore, we are dealing here with a declared weighting of votes, but a very specific one,
à rebours, as if to assume that the largest representation in parliament is granted to the one who obtains the fewest votes in the parliamentary elections. This leads to a drastic overrepresentation of marginal voices. As a result, the initiative to define the outcome of such organized consultations falls upon the given EU institution. Looking at this practice from the point of view of EU policy on religion, one must say that the EU consciously promotes the secular position represented mainly by small entities.
13 This is accompanied by a debate held mainly in the European Parliament, in which there also appears a proposal by secularists that the churches should be reduced to the level of large non-governmental organizations, i.e., for example without the right to conclude concordats, which—in such a case—the Union would treat as null and void. One of the tools of conducting such a policy is the
European Parliament Platform for Secularism in Politics (
https://www.secularism.org.uk/defend-equality-laws/european-parliament-platform-for.html), established in 2009. The fact that its representatives are involved in each decision-making process on matters relating to religious freedom shows the idea that potential enemies of religious freedom must also co-decide about religious freedom in the EU. It must be said that this procedure is practiced not only in the field of policy on religion, but also, for example, in the area of non-discrimination policy, as discussed below.
14 4. EU Secondary Law
Despite the lack of competence to regulate the status of churches and religious communities, EU law and policies significantly affect this status, although, as already mentioned, it happens differently than in the case of the influence of domestic law. Regarding secondary law, terms such as religion or churches appear mainly in the lists of, for example, various forms of diversity or bases of non-discrimination. We are dealing with similar lists also in primary law. Often in acts of secondary law we deal with exclusion clauses, and therefore with the exclusion or possibility of excluding religious entities from the obligation to apply a directive or regulation, most often only referring to some of their specific provisions. One of the recent regulations introducing such a clause of significant practical importance is the aforementioned regulation on the protection of personal data, which provides for the possibility of excluding churches from its jurisdiction, provided that on the date of the GDPR’s entry into force a given church had an autonomous data protection system and adjusted its standards to those contained in the regulation.
Issues important from the point of view of religious communities, and which may have a significant impact on their functioning, appear in various, sometimes the most surprising documents, e.g., on transport or child labour (the only mention of Sunday as a special day of the week in EU law), animal welfare (regulations regarding ritual slaughter), prohibition of discrimination (e.g., regarding the possibility of preventing women (priesthood of women) or people of different religious background (Catechesis) from entering certain professions, or selecting students of religious schools according to religious criteria, etc.). On the other hand, churches are keenly interested in the ethical side of many EU decisions, regarding, e.g., funding research on human embryonic stem cells (which involves the destruction of human embryos), transplantation, or development aid (under which the EU funds abortion, contraception, and sterilization in developing countries). Sometimes, a risk appears that the decisions made will directly violate the right of religious communities to spread freely their moral teachings (e.g., the prohibition of homophobia is sometimes understood as a prohibition of moral condemnation of homosexual acts).
The list of this type of potentially conflicting issues increases with the expansion of the scope of competences of EU institutions. The essence of the problem is a phenomenon that can be called a conflict of two anthropologies. National diversity, with its associated different cultural traditions; the quantitative advantage of the “old Union” over the “new” in EU institutions; the left-wing’s overrepresentation among the EU elites, with their simultaneous disconnection from their own societies, make the worldview dispute in the EU institutions (in which on the one hand, we have a Christian position, and on the other, a left-materialist position; on one side, a vision of constrained anthropology—through the awareness of being a creature that must take into account the will of the Creator and through the awareness of the existence in the world of consequences of original sin—and on the other, unconstrained anthropology, where a human being is perceived as a random fruit of the blind forces of evolution, and at a next stage he may try to direct this process, transforming his nature without any predetermined constraints) take on an intensity unheard of elsewhere in Europe. This phenomenon was well described by Michał Gierycz in the book entitled
European Dispute over Man (
Gierycz 2017)
15.
5. Migration Policy and Accession Policy
The accession policy and migration policy are special tools of policy on religion. They are, in a sense, macro-tools. Given that for some time (especially since 2014), the flow of immigrants reaching Europe has been strongly dominated by followers of one non-European religion, decisions regarding the preferred countries of origin from which EU Member States accept immigrants and the number of immigrants admitted have, in the long term, a significant impact on the religious demographic structure of the Old Continent
16. It should be noted that, generally, the fertility rate is also religiously differentiated. One can therefore say that, to a large extent, it is politicians who decide the future proportions between the various faiths and religions in Europe. It is also politicians who decide whether the European landscape will be dominated by the spiers of Gothic cathedrals or, rather, by the spikes of minarets.
17Sometimes, the opinion is expressed that the decisions made in this area are largely motivated by ideological reasons. It is about the ideology of multiculturalism, which—as Samuel Huntington pointed out—is essentially anti-European, as its aim is to oppose the homogeneity of European societies. It should be emphasized, however, that if Europe is homogeneous in any respect, then only in the sense that it is/was Christian (
Huntington 2005, pp. 173–80;
Bock-Côté 2019;
Mazurkiewicz 2020). Thus, an attempt to break down this social homogeneity and replace it with heterogeneous societies means nothing less than the desire to replace societies dominated by Christian culture with multicultural societies in the name of “cultural enrichment.” A symbolic gesture was the removal from the three million copies 2010/2011 calendar, intended for school students across Europe, of Christian holidays, including Christmas and Easter, and replacing them with holidays of other religions, including those with marginal representation in the EU (
Chayet 2011). The expected results of the ideological policy of multiculturalism seem to find good reflection in the forecasts presented by the Pew Research Center, showing the dynamics of religious changes in individual EU countries until 2060 (
Pew Research Center 2017b).
The change in the religious demography of Europe, which may take place in the next 40 years due to the migration policy, can come about in a much shorter time as a result of decisions on future accessions to the EU. A decision to admit to the Union, at one fell swoop, either 83 million Muslims or 43 million Christians, would fundamentally change the religious structure of the EU community for many years to come. This is, of course, about a possible EU accession of Turkey or Ukraine. It is difficult not to take into account certain gestures of hostility towards Europe made by the Turkish government. I am thinking of both the use of “migrant blackmail” and the transformation of Hagia Sophia into a mosque, which is an event with a very strong symbolic meaning (
Schinas 2020;
Orthodox Times 2020). I am not advocating here to recognize that Christians are better suited to be EU citizens than Muslims are, but only to note that a political decision to admit this or that country has a significant impact also on the religious structure of the EU population.
The EU’s policy on religion will probably also change under the influence of smaller scale decisions. So far, the Muslim community is represented in the EU through minorities in individual member states, and politicians who profess Islam join EU institutions on behalf of the same parties as their non-Muslim colleagues. The accession to the Union of countries such as Albania or Bosnia and Herzegovina would result in Muslims also gaining an independent vote in the EU Council, and over time, perhaps, would also lead to the appearance of an Islamic party in the European Parliament. Probably, this independent voice would not determine the overall shape of EU policies, but even in the case of countries with relatively small populations, it would certainly have an impact on these decisions and would force the integration of the Islamic point of view into decisions taken. However, raising the rank of the opinion of the Muslim community from being represented by individual persons (MPs, politicians representing a member state, EU officials who are followers of Islam), or by a Muslim delegation participating in meetings under Article 17, to the voting level of a member state would represent a qualitative change.
6. EU’s External Policy
Issues related to religion also arise in the field of EU’s external policy. All the EU institutions actually participate in shaping it, and the intergovernmental element characteristic of the EU Council is relatively strong. This fact, as well as the fact that the policy is addressed to third countries, means that the approach to religious freedom within its framework is less saturated with Brussels jargon and EU correctness, and more similar to the concept present in international law documents related to human rights.
Calls for respect of freedom of religion appear frequently in declarations and resolutions of the European Parliament, most often in the context of condemning of specific crimes committed in a third country. We sometimes see condemnation of such acts in the conclusions of the meeting of the Council of Ministers of Foreign Affairs, much less often in the speeches of the High Representative for external action. Characteristic for these appeals is their ambiguity, which is a consequence of a specifically understood political correctness. Firstly, for a long time, mentioning the religious affiliation of victims of condemned terrorist attacks, if they were Christians, was avoided with a shudder. Later it became customary to use a general formula for victims of persecution belonging to different religions, “Christians included”. This was driven by the concern to avoid the slightest appearance that the Union prefers Christianity or somehow identifies with it, or that it associates specific acts of terrorism with any particular religion. Secondly, condemning the perpetrators of a particular attack was eschewed, always including in the given document a list of acts of terror that took place over a long period, so as not to stigmatize any single state. As a result, the published statements showed that we dealt with violations of religious freedom everywhere, and that the victims were representatives of all religions, Christians included.
18A positive gesture was the Foreign Affairs Council’s adoption, in 2013, of the EU guidelines on the promotion and protection of freedom of religion or belief, which were to guide EU ambassadors regarding the monitoring of the state of religious freedom in third countries (
Council of the European Union 2013). In practice, however, the guidelines did not play a significant role until the appointment in 2016 of the Special Envoy for promotion of freedom of religion or belief outside the EU in the person of Ján Figeľ, which “activated” this document. It draws attention that the EU Special Envoy, whose mission ended in 2019 with the election of the new European Commission, was not anchored in the EEAS, but inside the European Commission as a special advisor to the Commissioner for International Cooperation and Development.
19 This significantly weakened the Special Envoy’s ability to influence the EU’s external policy, as compared to his potential placement within the EEAS. In this situation, one of the main potential tools to influence the state of religious freedom in third countries are possible conditionality clauses in trade agreements, making the level of economic relations dependent on the state of religious freedom in a given country.
We can say that in the framework of EU’s external policy one can note a desire to create the appearance of genuine commitment of EU institutions to defend religious freedom, including Christians. It seems that this is mainly because of the public opinion within the Union itself, which is to a large extent shaped by Christians.
7. Jurisprudence of the ECtHR and the ECJ
In general, at least two more factors are mentioned that link the process of European integration with changes in the status of churches and religious communities. One is the, let us call it spontaneous, process of harmonization of laws and the so-called good practice within the Union itself. Over the last few decades, the Member States have gradually become more similar to one another when it comes to their internal regulations concerning the relations between the state and the church/religious communities. Extreme solutions, e.g. in the form of a confessional state, have either been abandoned (Sweden in 2000) or have lost much of their “severity” (Finland, Greece).
The second factor is the jurisprudence of European courts. In the field of religious freedom, the vast majority of jurisprudence is “produced” by the European Court of Human Rights—ECtHR, which is not an EU institution but whose jurisdiction binds all EU member states.
20 However, sometimes the European Court of Justice—ECJ also gives rulings on matters directly related to religion. I am thinking, for example, of the ECJ decision in case C-84/94, United Kingdom v Council, which abolished the legal protection in the EU of Sunday in the Working Time Directive, stating that the Council did not provide justification confirming the link between Sunday rest and the health and safety of workers (
European Court of Justice 1996). Other examples may include the ECJ rulings in cases C-157/15, G4SSecure Solutions (
European Court of Justice 2017a) and C-188/15, Bougnaoui and ADDH (
European Court of Justice 2017b) relating directly to the possibility of wearing visible signs of religious beliefs at the workplace. Undoubtedly, the number of judgments issued in matters relating to religion is much greater in the case of the ECtHR than in the case of the ECJ. However, the prospect of EU’s accession to the ECHR may make this last remark redundant.
One of the most symptomatic expressions of the above-mentioned a conflict of two (Christian and materialistic) anthropologies at the European Court of Justice level is the case of
Brüstle vs. Greenpeace (Case C-34/10) and the controversy that arose as a consequence of the judgment. It is worth devoting a little more space to its analysis because, as mentioned, potential restrictions on religious freedom in the EU generally do not take place directly, but mainly due to divergent positions on fundamental ethical issues and political and legal pressure to persuade churches and religious associations to “correct” proclaimed ethical beliefs, which usually form integral part of their doctrine. As we read in the ECJ judgment: “Mr Brüstle is the holder of a German patent, filed on 19 December 1997, which concerns isolated and purified neural precursor cells, processes for their production from embryonic stem cells and the use of neural precursor cells for the treatment of neural defects” (
European Court of Justice 2011, 15). On application by Greenpeace, the Bundespatentgericht (Federal Patent Court) ruled that the patent obtained by Olivier Brüstle was invalid “so far as it covers precursor cells obtained from human embryonic stem cells and processes for the production of those precursor cells” (ibid. 19). Brüstle appealed against that judgment to the Bundesgerichtshof (Federal Court of Justice) which decided to refer three extensive questions to the European Court of Justice for a preliminary ruling. The first one, concerning the definition of a human embryo used in the Directive 98/44/EC of the European Parliament and of the Council of 6 July 1998 on the legal protection of biotechnological inventions, was the most important. Other two, concerning the meaning of the expression “uses of human embryos for industrial or commercial purposes” and the patenting of technical teaching related to the use of human embryos, were of an auxiliary nature. It seems, they were added to unequivocally suggest the ECJ to narrow down the interpretation of the exclusions provided for in the Directive, to make it more “friendly” to the development of inventions based on the use and destruction of embryos (
Maśnicki 2013). The first question was as follows: “What is meant by the term “human embryos” in Article 6(2)(c) of [the Directive]? (a) Does it include all stages of the development of human life, beginning with the fertilisation of the ovum, or must further requirements, such as the attainment of a certain stage of development, be satisfied? (b) Are the following organisms also included: unfertilised human ova into which a cell nucleus from a mature human cell has been transplanted; unfertilised human ova whose division and further development have been stimulated by parthenogenesis? (c) Are stem cells obtained from human embryos at the blastocyst stage also included?” (
European Court of Justice 2011, 23).
The opinion of advocate general delivered on 10 March 2011 was crucial to the case. He proposed a legal definition of a human embryo which was then integrated into the final decision of the Court (
Bot 2011). In the Judgment ECJ states that, on the one hand, “the definition of human embryo is a very sensitive social issue in many Member States, marked by their multiple traditions and value systems” (30), on the other hand, that there must be a common definition of the human embryo to avoid at least chaos link with a forum searching for the patenting. “The lack of a uniform definition of the concept of human embryo would create a risk of the authors of certain biotechnological inventions being tempted to seek their patentability in the Member States which have the narrowest concept of human embryo and are accordingly the most liberal as regards possible patentability, because those inventions would not be patentable in the other Member States” (28). In this situation, the ECJ decided to avoid questions of medical or ethical nature, restricting itself to a legal interpretation of the relevant provisions of the Directive. Frist of all, the Directive was issued to protect dignity of the person and his fundamental rights. In particular, “patent law must be applied so as to respect the fundamental principles safeguarding the dignity and integrity of the person” (32). This leaded the Court to the conclusion, which is opposite to the intention of the German Constitutional Court: “It follows that the concept of ‘human embryo’ within the meaning of Article 6(2)(c) of the Directive must be understood in a wide sense” (34). Finally, the Court shared the legal definition of the human embryo proposed by the Advocate General. In the conclusions we find negative answers on three questions posed by the German Constitutional Court:
Article 6(2)(c) of Directive 98/44/EC of the European Parliament and of the Council of 6 July 1998 on the legal protection of biotechnological inventions must be interpreted as meaning that:
- –
any human ovum after fertilisation, any non-fertilised human ovum into which the cell nucleus from a mature human cell has been transplanted, and any non-fertilised human ovum whose division and further development have been stimulated by parthenogenesis constitute a ‘human embryo’;
- –
it is for the referring court to ascertain, in the light of scientific developments, whether a stem cell obtained from a human embryo at the blastocyst stage constitutes a ‘human embryo’ within the meaning of Article 6(2)(c) of Directive 98/44.
The exclusion from patentability concerning the use of human embryos for industrial or commercial purposes set out in Article 6(2)(c) of Directive 98/44 also covers the use of human embryos for purposes of scientific research, only use for therapeutic or diagnostic purposes which is applied to the human embryo and is useful to it being patentable.
Article 6(2)(c) of Directive 98/44 excludes an invention from patentability where the technical teaching which is the subject-matter of the patent application requires the prior destruction of human embryos or their use as base material, whatever the stage at which that takes place and even if the description of the technical teaching claimed does not refer to the use of human embryos” (53).
In its judgment, the ECJ adopted the legal definition of the human embryo and recognized the moment of the creation of the human embryo as the beginning of the development of the human person. This way the EU established a legal definition of the human embryo which is totally in line with the European and Christian tradition of understanding the human person. Two people played a very important role in this procedure: Yves Bot, advocate general, and Marek Safjan, rapporteur.
The elaboration of a definition of the human embryo by ECJ has placed at the heart of EU policy the question of whether all activities related to the life and dignity of human embryos, carried out under different competences, are consistent with each other. The organisers of European Citizens Initiative “One of Us” claimed that to grant that consistency the EU should prohibit and end funding of activities that imply the destruction of human embryos, in particular in the areas of research, development and public health. In the “One of Us” proposal, one read: “i) There shall be excluded any political support and a fortiori the funding from the Union of actions that assume or carry out the destruction of human embryos; l) The objective of the citizens’ initiative is to get the commitment of the Union in all these areas not to allow and not to fund actions that assume or carry out the destruction of human embryos and to provide suitable control tools for the use of allocated funds in order to ensure that they are never used to destroy human life” (
European Citizens’ Initiative “One of Us” 2012).
Despite the fact that the Initiative gained the support of almost two million EU citizens from different countries (against one million required by law), the European Commission decided not to pursue it any further. Mainly because the decision-making procedures applied by the European Commission in the areas covered by the Initiative meet “the highest ethical standards”; “the highest” and therefore impossible to be improved by ordinary citizens. “EU primary legislation explicitly enshrines human dignity, the right to life, and the right to the integrity of the person. The EU Financial Regulation states that all EU expenditure should comply with EU primary legislation. Therefore, the Commission does not see a need to propose changes to the Financial Regulation” (
European Commission 2014).
This way of treating the will expressed by EU citizens clearly shows what was reflected in the discussions on the Lisbon Treaty: the “democratic deficit” in the EU does not only result from the objective difficulties of empowering EU citizens, but above all from the fear of EU bureaucrats concerning what citizens can request of them. In other words, the instrument of the citizens’ initiative is structured in such a way that the Commission takes a specific legislative initiative only when the will expressed by the citizens agrees with the will of the bureaucrats, and it does nothing if the citizens dare to disagree with their elites on a matter. The only reason for the discrepancy may be a lack of competence or “lower ethical standards” represented by ordinary citizens.
On 25 July 2014, the European Citizens’ Initiative “One of Us” filed a complaint with the Court in Luxembourg against the European Commission, the Council of the European Union and the European Parliament, requesting annulment of the decision of the European Commission not to forward the initiative to the European Parliament and the Council of the European Union (
European Court of Justice 2014a). The Second Chamber, dismissing the complaint on 23 April 2018, found convincing arguments of the European Commission justifying the necessity to finance “safe abortion” in developing countries (
European Court of Justice 2018). Which, from the point of view of common sense, seems to reinforce the anthropological and ethical inconsistency in the EU policy. In the meantime, between 2012 and 2018, the Court of Justice delivered its judgment in Case C-364/13
International Stem Cell Corporation vs. Comptroller General of Patents, Designs and Trade Marks, on whether methods of producing pluripotent human stem cell lines from parthenogenetically-activated oocytes and stem cell lines produced according to the claimed methods can be patented. In the judgment ECJ declared that “an unfertilised human ovum whose division and further development have been stimulated by parthenogenesis does not constitute a ‘human embryo’, within the meaning of that provision, if, in the light of current scientific knowledge, it does not, in itself, have the inherent capacity of developing into a human being, this being a matter for the national court to determine” (39) (
European Court of Justice 2014b). In both cases, on
One of Us and on
International Stem Cell Corporation, it can be seen that the Court was trying to narrow down the legal definition of an embryo developed in
Brüstle and limit the consequences of its application to the European law. This clearly shows how it seems that the Tribunal is trying to reconcile both contradictory anthropologies in its jurisprudence, by favoring, on in essence the same issue, sometimes the side of one of them, sometimes more of the other. Nevertheless, the ethical sensitivity of the Tribunal in this respect was undoubtedly greater than that of other EU institutions.
8. Res novae in the Field of Religion and EU Policy
The density of mutual relations between the EU institutions and churches and religious associations is constantly increasing, but at the same time, there is a growing tendency in EU policy to change these religions from within through their own actions. To illustrate this issue, it is sufficient to cite the Regulation (EU) 2016/679 of the European Parliament and of the Council of 27 April 2016 on the protection of natural persons with regard to the processing of personal data and on the free movement of such data (
Official Journal of the European Union 2016). Although Article 91 (1) leaves churches and religious associations the right to retain an autonomous system of personal data protection, it is only at the cost of transferring to the canon law system the model of data protection enshrined in EU law. Politicians, therefore, set the standards for the protection of these data in the churches. An analogy can also be seen in the ongoing debates on non-discrimination and sexual abuse. Under the influence of political and media pressure, churches often take over from the secular debate not only the sensitivity (which is good in itself) but also the terminology and standards for the protection of persons, in particular minors. It is not about condemning such a practice, but about the need to be aware of the very fact of its existence.
A small thought experiment can be helpful in understanding the essence of another innovative element present in the EU’s policy towards religion. Imagine that we take up a photo taken in Germany in May 2018. It shows the interior of a Roman basilica from the time of Constantine, currently used by the Protestant Church. In the center of the photography, there is an altar with the slogan: “1818–2018. Karl Marx—Trier”.
21 On the other side of the altar, in the place where normally Pastor is holding the liturgy, we see Jean-Claude Juncker, President of the European Commission, addressing the audience. This raises a few naive questions: Why did this meeting take place in the church? Are we dealing with a service or is it a political rally? Why is this “pastor”, a member of Christian democracy, promoting in the church “the creator of international communism”? Has the Church changed its attitude towards atheist Marxism and no longer treats it as a synonym of godlessness? Is the European People’s Party the successor of the Communist International and the European Union the heir of the Soviet Union? These questions may seem frivolous, but the photograph undoubtedly shows an encounter of two worlds: religion and politics, with the former giving its space as the host, and the latter taking over the teaching mission. The ceremony in Trier ended with the unveiling of a few meters’ high statue of the “great philosopher”, gifted by the People’s Republic of China.
Another example of politicians’ new approach to religion was the behavior of many national governments in Europe in connection with the COVID 19 pandemic. Adopted procedures for imposing restrictions on churches and religious communities varied across Europe. In some of them, the state made its own decisions in this matter, in others, these decisions were post-factum authorized by the bishops, in others—they were the result of dialogue between the government and the episcopal conference. Nevertheless, almost always the restrictions imposed on the participation of the faithful in the services were more restrictive than, for example, related to the possibility of doing everyday shopping. In itself, this means that material needs were considered more important than spiritual one. In France, for example, the Council of State considered “a general and absolute prohibition [to organize religious ceremonies] disproportionate” and ordered its abolition. However, it happened only after two months of the restrictions (
Sugy 2020). Interestingly, in the briefing published by the European Parliamentary Research Service on the restrictions imposed on EU citizens in connection with the pandemic, the topic of religion does not appear at all (
European Parliamentary Research Service 2020).
9. Risk of Resacralisation of Law and Policy
After the terrorist attack at the Zaventem airport in 2016, there was a discussion in the Belgian press about possible tools for the effective integration of immigrants. One idea was to introduce a compulsory subject in Belgian schools, which was originally called les cours de rien, lessons about nothing. The originator of the idea assumed that the schools in Belgium (where lessons of Catholic, Protestant, Christian Orthodox, Islamic, and Judaic religions, as well as ethics lessons, are conducted) are not neutral enough, which is the cause of the emerging religious fundamentalism, hence the idea to introduce a new compulsory subject that would serve to educate children and adolescents within a worldview that goes beyond each of these particular points of view. Eventually, the subject was introduced to schools, albeit under a different name.
Looking at the EU’s policy on religion, highlighting its unique character, it can be said that, despite the fact that schools for children of European officials conduct religion lessons, the vision of worldview neutrality comes quite close to the one espoused by the proponent of the idea of Belgian cours de rien. When making decisions, political realism requires the existence of religious communities to be taken into account as a social fact, and therefore to try to win their goodwill or at least cold indifference, but it seems to be accompanied by a hope that thanks to long-term policy, religions will change, somehow becoming similar to Belgian cours de rien. Churches and religious communities are therefore an important partner of EU consultations, but at the same time, by involving them in this process, efforts are made to neutralize their religious message. The aim is to create a religion consistent with EU standards, devoid of a critical edge vis-à-vis the political sphere, legitimizing, if only tacitly (qui tacit consentire videtur), above all, the process of European integration itself, but also the project of ideological reconstruction of European societies. Looking at EU policy on religion in statu nascendi, one may get the impression that it primarily expresses the need of EU leaders for a religion of political optimism that will nurture faith in earthly success, even if the political actions taken could seem utterly irrational. The European Union is trying to “domesticate” churches and religious associations, mute their tendency to political pessimism and criticism of political power, and “hollow out” religions from their theological core. The idea is to create a new political religion, built on the rubble of traditional beliefs, but without violent revolution, demolition of churches, and removal of hierarchs. All this should be done in an evolutionary manner, using the mechanism of co-opting religious elites into the EU establishment. We observe a similar process, albeit with the use of different instruments, at the level of nation states.
Two inevitable consequences of such a process are worth noting. The first is the emergence of a kind of “secular theocracy”.
22 If Christianity served as a natural barrier to the aspirations of secular power to over-accumulate sovereign powers, the “taming” and “domestication” of Christian churches results in the resacralisation of the secular power, which in fact takes over the leadership in both the temporal and spiritual spheres. Then the dual division of powers, characteristic of Europe, the feature of which was the coexistence of two competing centres of power in the same area and in relation to the same people (if they are believers); secular and spiritual, disappears from the scene of social life. This type of separation of powers protects against the possibility of emergence of absolute/total power to a much greater extent than Montesquieu’s known and valued
trias politica division of power. The former has a more primal character.
The second consequence is the observed process of resacralisation of the law. Jacek Salij OP notes that the abandonment of natural law as the foundation of social life as a result of legal positivism has led today to a kind of sacralization of statutory law (
Salij 2018) thus a process opposite to the one mentioned by Benedict XVI in his speech to members of the German parliament.
23 Attempts to legally redefine the institution of marriage and family are one of the manifestations of this phenomenon. The aforementioned resacralisation of the law results from the fact that the legislator—perhaps not fully consciously—arrogates to itself divine prerogatives. At the same time, depriving religion of a transcendent authority reminding the ruler that he is not God and that his powers of authority are limited by the mere fact of being a creature, leaves him without an intellectual and institutional barrier. Moreover, in the context of legal positivism, as a rule, the links between law and morality are loosened. Going beyond the paradigm of the Creator and creation, “objective and subjective reason (...) rooted in the creative reason of God” (
Benedict XVI 2011), and consequently causes the questioning of the very idea of human nature, and therefore also the common and unchanging moral norms common to all people (
John Paul II 1993, 32). Morality itself is treated as a product of man, which can be processed depending on the goals man sets for himself at a given moment in history.
Perhaps in today’s world, not only in EU policy, we are seeing a return to the conviction mentioned at the beginning and expressed by Plato that without reference to religion it is impossible to effectively govern society without making it totalitarian. Religion is, therefore, necessary for the political power to survive, and at the same time the temptation of the political elite is to seek that the content and form of (at least) the dominant religion be controlled by this power. It is not about the aggressive secularism or outright hostility to any religion, but about the pursuit of soft control of religion and the actual transformation of religion through real politics. In this context, we should particularly defend freedom of religion and inviolable ethical principles against usurpation by any political authority, constantly reminding all politicians of the above, regardless of the party they come from and notwithstanding at what level: national or the EU, they exercise this power. Paradoxically, celebrations such as the one in Trier, also pose a good opportunity to launch a public appeal for a re-secularization of EU policy.
Cardinal Joseph Ratzinger, analysing the attitude of Jeremiah, the prophet during the siege of Jerusalem, notes that he was convicted and imprisoned due to his pessimism. “The official optimism of the army, nobility, priests, and official prophets demanded that God would guard his city and temple. God was thus relegated to the role of guarantor of human success and used as an excuse for irrationalism.” (
Ratzinger 2014, p. 439). For it was obvious that in the face of the overwhelming forces of the Babylonians, the attempt of fighting with an unwavering faith in victory was irrational from the military and political points of view. Ratzinger sees the essence of this dispute between the optimists and pessimists as a conflict between “political and irrational theology aimed at ideological power, and the realism of believers who embody morality and political rationality” (ibid). “The criterion of judgment, which Jeremiah gives in verse 9, remains valid: the announcement of success must be judged by empirical criteria, and it cannot be based on theology. Whoever announces today an ultimately idyllic and perfect society of tomorrow must confirm this announcement empirically and must not embellish these remarks with theological arguments. The message about the kingdom of God and about salvation must not be used as proof that certain sociological techniques will produce an intra-historical and therefore empirically functioning society.” (ibid, p. 440).
In religions with blunt shafts of criticism, priests “tamed” by politicians will not bring anything significant to the world of politics, and therefore in the long run will be of no use to politicians.