2.1. Deduction
We now understand that approaching the difference between Philosophy and non-Philosophy from the point of view of Philosophy is no contradiction but required by the epistemology of difference as outlined above; the Other must be approached from the Same, and not observed from a presumed neutral point of view.
How is this approach accomplished? The epistemology of difference requires not a theoretical but an ethical approach, desire. However, the designation that Levinas gives for his movement from the philosophical to the prophetic episteme, from totality to infinity, belongs to a highly theoretical discourse: “deduction”. Levinas calls it “the phenomenological method” (TI 14, 28), referring to Husserl.
This method, Levinas explains, departs from vision-based, objectifying thought to “reveal” it as “implanted in…a forgotten experience from which it lives”: “The break-up of the formal structure of thought … into events which this structure dissimulates, but which sustain it and restore its concrete significance, constitutes a deduction—necessary and yet non-analytical.’” (TI 14, 28). De-duction leads from theoretical knowledge back to something else—horizon, experience, event, situation–, from which theory “lives”. Just as Husserl showed our perception of objects to arise from experiences of our own conscience, Levinas wants to show how totalizing knowledge lives from non-totality: “we can trace back the experience of totality to a situation where totality breaks up, a situation that conditions totality itself.” (TI 9–10, 24)
What must be noted at the outset is the ambivalence of this exercise: by tracing back totality to non-totality, namely by deducing non-totality from totality, it establishes a
necessary connection between totality and non-totality and thus overcomes their difference, to reunite them in a new, even more comprehensive totality. More specifically, it presents non-totality not as the opposite of totality, but as its foundation. What Levinas undertakes as resistance to totality, i.e., showing that it is conditioned by difference, at the same time features difference as the basis
of totality.
20From the formal structure of Levinas’s intervention follows its concrete operation. Showing totality to be based on non-totality means integrating the two into a comprehensive total discourse, a total narrative. Levinas identified the paradigm of such a total logos as “the logos of being”, and his demonstration—his “deduction”—in
Totality and Infinity, inasmuch as it mounts an opposition to ontology, is itself accordingly deeply ontological, looks for the “ultimate structure of being” (TI 104, 102). Prophecy is revealed as the condition of Philosophy, but this revelation itself is made on Philosophy’s terms. Levinas’s deduction may therefore be describes as Jewish Greek in the sense that it speaks the language of a Jewish Philosopher, it constitutes a Philonic operation.
21Levinas’s explicit reference and model is not Philo, but Husserl. Its total logos is not only a logos of being, ontology, but also a logos of phenomena, phenomenology, namely an observation, description and depiction of reality. This reality, contemplated as incarnating the ontological plot, is paradigmatically the singular individual subject, a “me”, which defines a primary domain of the real, “interiority” or “experience”. The conceptual movement (the “deduction” of non-totality from totality) is accordingly described as a process that takes place in the subject, some development in its condition. The phenomenological demonstration proceeds as a narrative of this event within the inner experience of the self, which emerges as the overarching totality of non-totality with totality.
This model is prominent in classics of modern philosophy that are directly referenced by
Totality and Infinity, from Heidegger’s
Being and Time, through Husserl’s
Ideen II, Hegel’s
Phenomenology and Descartes’
Meditations. Levinas’s text, in its trans-epistemic performance, renders tangible the affinity of these philosophical narratives to prophetic narratives, such as the biblical myth. In the narratives of modern philosophy, the individual subject embodies the totalizing form of the narrative, which integrates the Other in the Same, God in the world, Beyng in beings. Accordingly, and this is visible also in Levinas’s narrative, the individual drama represents a broader, collective or political event, namely functions as parable for history. Phenomenology epitomizes historiography.
22What I argue is that Levinas’s story, more than similar phenomenological narratives, is built on its own struggle to be a story, namely not only the illustration of logical relations, which arise from formal necessity, but an occurrence of otherness, within totality a breakup of totality, a real encounter. Levinas often designates this happening by the term “event” or “situation”, which implies the lack of necessity, contingency, incommensurable with any theory or objective calculation. The difficulty is however obvious: the phenomenological description of the non-necessary event is supposed to perform the necessary deduction of non-totality from totality. If we take this difficulty as a hermeneutic key for reading Levinas’s narrative, then, beyond its uncontestable poetic beauty and insightfulness and against Levinas’s own structural articulation, his narrative can be shown to fall in two parts, which articulate a—structural, inexplicit—self-reflection of Levinas’s inter-epistemic project on itself.
The first part is the main part of the book, which traces back “the experience of totality to a situation where totality breaks up,” through a phenomenology of subjectivity. Since the experience of totality is narrated as what constitutes subjectivity, the key moment of this narrative is the subject’s encounter with the Other as the event par excellence. However, since this event is deduced from totality, rather than disrupting, it arises as the basis of totality. The main part of the book thus in fact demonstrates rather the unity of Totality “and” Infinity: how Greek philosophy is based on Prophetic ethics, how our world is not split between them, but arises from their unity. The second part of Levinas’s narrative, which takes place in the last sections of the book, is consequently dedicated to showing how the problem of totality arises from the Greek-Jewish unity of ontology and ethics. It is here that the real story transpires not as the encounter with otherness, but as the history of this encounter’s epistemo-political abuse.
2.2. Plato and Moses Meet Descartes
The first part of Levinas’s narrative begins in the “experience of totality”. This notion, and the description to which it gives rise, are built on equivocation. On the one hand, this is an experience of totality; on the other hand, it is an experienced totality, namely that is already predicated on individual subjectivity, and therefore on difference. Accordingly, Levinas portrayal of totality is a phenomenological description of the individual self, the “me”, whose basic principle is to exist as an individual, separate being. Totality lives from separation. The main thrust of Levinas’s narrative is to insist—against any narrative that makes the individual self dependent on a higher order—on the independent being of the individual subject, whose existence is defined by contentment, enjoyment and happiness. Against Heidegger and original sin theology, human being is not “fallen” in worldly life. Levinas’s self is so to speak a Greek one, who is basically “at home” in the world, who exists, so the title of this section, as “Interiority and Economy”.
And yet, inasmuch as the self is independent of unworldliness, it depends on the world. Existing in the world as an individual means subsisting by means of the relation to worldly otherness. This is the essence of enjoyment: breathing, eating, reproduction. The self maintains itself through its relation to worldly others, which are accordingly relative others, only existing as a moment in the self-generation of the individual subject. Separate individual existence consists in a dialectic relation between self and world, which is by definition a relation of non-separation. Inasmuch as Levinas describes a separate being, this description is at the same time designed to portray the “experience of totality”, which means the effacement of the self, namely self-effacement by the very force of self-generation through the world.
This dialectical logic—separation as totalization—underlies Levinas’s rich narrative, which portrays subjective experience as an evolution between two fundamental conditions. In the first, primal stage, the individual has more immediate, sensual relations to the world, which is experienced not as objects or things, but as “elements”. The individual is “bathing in” the elements: enjoying himself (male gender explicit) through them, living from them, but at the same time in constant insecurity and fear of losing himself in them, of becoming them, not dying, but being absorbed into the anonymous “there is”.
In the second, higher evolutionary stage of the individual’s self-identification through the world, the subject establishes relations, beyond the elements, with another subject, another person, who is however encountered not as absolute other, but as a part of the subject’s own world. Levinas’s identifies this inner-worldly otherness as “the feminine”, who is the familiar other, a familiar “you”, a
tu.
23 The relation to the feminine opens up within the elemental world a dimension of familiarity, where the individual finds his interior space out in the world: Home. The home world is no longer the chaotic world of elements, but regulated existence, Economy, the “first civilization” (TI 163). Economic civilization “adjourns” elemental immediacy, so that the individual no longer just “bathes in elements” but acquires hold of things. By the same dialectics of enjoyment, however, the things are only relative others, which exist “for me” and not “in themselves”, as mere phenomena and not as actual beings. The economic world is still a form of interiority, in which self-identification generates an “experience of totality”, which signifies the effacement of the self in its own world. One is reminded of
Dasein’s being-in-the-world, in Heidegger’s
Being and Time, where the human subject “initially and most often” loses himself in the world he dwells.
The main point of Levinas’s demonstration is that totality is always “experience of totality”, namely a subjective experience, a state of the separated self. Totality is a performance of difference. It follows—this is the deduction—that totality requires, as a necessary pre-condition, separation, “a situation where totality breaks up, a situation that conditions totality itself.” This situation is the self’s encounter with the absolute Other.
My point is that, even as Levinas describes this passage from the “experience of totality” to non-totality, to the relation with the absolute Other, as a “situation”, “a new event” (TI 185), “new energy” (TI 183) or even as a moment of “grace” (TI 161), namely as transcending all necessity and logic; and even as this contingency is what enables the narrative, descriptive, phenomenological quality of Levinas’s demonstration, it nonetheless remains a conceptual argument, a deduction, which operates with the force of logical necessity. There is a structural correlation between the experience of totality, interiority and the relation to the Infinite, to exteriority. Totality and the breakup of totality articulate one and the same constellation. This is the hermeneutic key that I propose for reading the centerpiece of Totality and Infinity, the “situation where totality breaks up”, the encounter with the Other.
The encounter with the Other is portrayed by Levinas as a redeeming event of knowledge. This encounter shows parallels to other mythical revelations of redeeming knowledge, such as the “call” that in Gnostic myths or in Heidegger’s Being and Time wakes up the self from worldly self-oblivion. Totality and Infinity explicitly invokes as a reference, within the philosophical archive, the Cartesian ego’s overcoming of doubt by the idea of the infinite. Another explicit acknowledgment reminds here also of the second stage in Rosenzweig’s narrative in The Star of Redemption, the specifically biblical revelation, which is indeed Levinas’s primary reference, namely the prophetic myth.
The center of Levinas’s demonstration is in fact the appearance of biblical prophecy, as an explicit quote, in the world of totality, the emergence of Jewish transcendence in Greek immanence. What Levinas describes as the “situation where totality breaks up” features prophecy as an episteme of difference, characterized by the two elements that I indicated above: ethical relation of self to other, which takes place in language. It is revealing how Levinas’s phenomenology modulates these basic elements such that prophecy appears as enabling the totalizing epistemology of Western philosophy. A central motif in this constellation is how the relation to the other, ethics, operates as the constitutive event in the existence of the separate, independent self.
The encounter with the Other is an event of language. For Levinas, the paradigmatic phenomenon of language, which is the element of prophecy, is the act of spoken language, the living word, parole. Language, as the original relation to the Other, is a relation between speakers, interlocutors. Language originally appears as voice. The Other appears as “voice coming from the other bank” (TI 186). The voice is the Other’s presence to me. For Levinas, this vocal presence is the original experience of presence, of being, namely of something that exists not for me, but for itself, an sich, objectively. In Totality and Infinity, otherness, paradoxically, means presence, being. The relation to the other is the relation to something present. Accordingly, in Levinas’s depiction of this relation, the auditory experience of voice is famously translated into the encounter with a paradigmatically visual object, with the face. Language is phenomenologically a relation of vision.
Here lies the significance of Levinas’s notion that, in the epistemology of difference, ethics is optics. The encounter with the Other is the original event of objective knowledge. The Other is the primal object and so the primal source of knowledge, namely, as Levinas writes, le Maître, “the Master” or “the Teacher”. Knowledge is essentially “teaching”. Even as Levinas invokes in this context Descartes (God teaches me the idea of infinity) against Plato (the teacher only helps me to recall what I already know) (TI 85), his analysis of teaching and the teacher clearly echoes “torah” and “rabbi” as two basic Jewish epistemological categories.
Yet, the basic teaching of the Other, the basic knowledge that he dispenses, does not lie in what he says, but in the voice, which means nothing but itself, namely absolute being. The revelation of absolute being in the inner experience of the self, which is an experience of totality, of permanent effacement of the difference between self and other, means an encounter with resistance to self-identification through others. The encounter with the other’s absolute being means an encounter with something that may not be dialectically made part of the self. As Levinas puts it, it is an encounter with the possibility of “total negation of a being”, with something that is not only relatively, but absolutely different than me, which has an absolutely independent existence, and so which I—through my constant appropriation of the world—may completely negate, annihilate. The concrete phenomenon of absolute negation of being is killing. When Levinas therefore writes that “[t]he Other is the only being that I may want to kill” (TI 216), this arises analytically from the notion that the Other is the only absolute being. Being is being exposed to killing, which means that the Other, as absolute being, is encountered as absolute vulnerability. Levinas expresses this by invoking a prophetic trope, describing the Other not only as teacher, but also as “the foreigner, the widow and the orphan” (TI 237).
Consequently, the self’s experience of the other, as absolute being, is an experience of resistance to the self’s own being, to his self-identification through others. The absolute other, as an absolute object, is encountered as objection, as opposition, as a “no”. “No” is the original word spoken by the face, the original prophecy, first torah. In Totality and Infinity the original speech act that constitutes the encounter with the Other appears as a quote from the paradigmatic instance of biblical prophecy, the sole direct speech of the Divine to the entire community, the Ten Commandments. The core of the Ten Commandments, God’s primal word—this is the “no” that Levinas quotes—would be, to follow Totality and Infinity, the 6th commandment: לא תרצח (lo tirtzach; Exodus 20, 12), “You shall not commit murder” (TI 217).
Positing Commandment Six as First Prophecy is not obvious.
24 In Levinas’s terms, “killing” arises as the possibility of absolute negation, namely of the only being that absolutely
is, the other. This possibility, the essence of my encounter with the other, is experienced as a resistance to my own being, a “no”, which marks an end to my power, to my possibilities. The Other is experienced as impossibility. As Levinas makes clear, this limitation of my power is not imposed by a stronger power, against whom I am too weak, but in contrast by absolute weakness. The other is experienced as something that is essentially beyond my power, that I cannot access with power, that I may only access through self-limitation. Self-limitation generates the experience of “ethical impossibility” (TI 185). This experience constitutes moral conscience, the knowledge of good and bad, which Levinas refers to Plato’s idea of the Good. In this ethical optics, certain entities—speaking others—may only be encountered—known –
as self-limitation of my power, namely as objects with respect to whom I
should not act. Their very being, their objectivity, their resistance to me, their “no”, is a commandment: “you shall not”. This limitation of my action does not mean this act is not in my power, but that it is bad, it is violence. It is only in the optics of ethics that we see certain acts as crimes: killing is murder. The basic experience of the other as absolute being is the encounter with my possibility of killing him, which is experienced as a negative commandment, “You shall not commit murder”.
The phenomenological analysis of the Sixth Commandment as articulating our fundamental experience of being, as fundamental ontology, is one of Levinas’s most powerful and famous interventions. In the narrative of Totality and Infinity, it marks the moment in which, within the subject’s interior “experience of totality”, totality breaks up by the presence of the absolute other. Since the experience of totality is the existence of the self, as self-identifying in (relative, worldly) others, the breakup of totality means the limitation of the self, such that he experiences his power as violence, which essentially implies self-negation, a restrained, moral attitude of “no violence”—ethics.
Nonetheless, and this is my point, according to the logic of Levinas’s deduction, this moment of totality’s break up is also the
condition of totality. It is crucial to note the necessary function of ethical self-restraint in the structure of separation, which means the being of the self. Nietzsche pointed out the self-empowering force of ascetic morality. In Levinas’s plot too, the encounter with the Other, as an event of self-limitation, is exactly the emergence of self-conscience, of the explicit experience of being an individual, the experience of “Me”. A fundamental insight of Levinas is that the encounter with the infinite Other is the encounter with an infinite invocation—assignation, summoning, accusation or “election”—of the Self, as infinite correlation to the Other, as infinite responsibility.
25This is how the situation where totality breaks up, the ethical encounter with the Other, generates the individual self, whose immanent experience is the condition of totality. However, as revelation goes, the emergence of the separate self as the condition of totality does not merely lead to a repetition of the “experience of totality”, but to a higher level of experience, to self-conscience.
The first part of Levinas’s story thus concludes with the developed form of his epistemology of difference. Of Jewish origins, this epistemology is nonetheless visibly Greek. It is founded on the constitutive relation to the absolute other, which, as we saw, is built on the paradigm of objective knowledge, and has the structure of vision. Accordingly, even as epistemic difference exists in language, just as original language, living speech, means presence of face, encounter with objective being, developed language constitutes the language of objectivity, language as logos. Prophetic revelation would be the foundation of theory, “divine veracity that supports Cartesian rationalism” (TI 224). Rationalism is featured in Totality and Infinity as the very performance of ethics, since, Levinas explains, generalization means generosity, the “offering of the world to the other person” (TI 189).
And so, Levinas’s epistemology of difference, which seemed to stand as a subversive, prophetic, Jewish alternative to Greek epistemology of totality, reveals itself rather as a fusion of Moses and Plato, a Philonic vision, whose modern embodiment, in
Totality and Infinity, is the Judeo-Greco-French Descartes. “What is Europe?”, Levinas will write a quarter of a century later, “It is the Bible and the Greeks”.
26 2.3. The State against God’s People
This vision features in Levinas’s narrative as the conclusion of a drama, the completion of the psychological development of the individual subject, or of the historical formation of Western civilization. Yet, as already noted, notwithstanding the dramatic language, Levinas’s phenomenological portrait, by its deductive methodology, in fact outlines a static constellation of necessary correlations, the constellation of separation. Within the structure of separation, the emergent relation to absolute otherness, in the face of the other person, generates the absolute point of departure for this relation, namely the separate individual self, who exists as interiority. In other words, up to this point, which is the great part of Totality and Infinity, Levinas’s narrative does not really feature a story, but a point of departure for one. What this story needs to tell is the birth of totality, not as the “experience” of individual subjectivity, but as a historical episteme, as a tradition of knowledge, Western Philosophy, which stands not only upon but in opposition to Prophecy. The last part of Levinas’s narrative is called to tell the history of how the episteme of totality arises from the episteme of difference.
I therefore claim that the actual drama of Totality and Infinity takes place in its last sections, and goes, as the last section is titled, “Beyond the Face”, namely beyond the momentary “situation” of the individual encounter between self and other. Its concern is indicated in the title of the immediately preceding subsection, “The Ethical Relation and Time”. This may be read as a direct conversation with Heidegger’s Being and Time. Levinas here acknowledges that the phenomenological constellation described in the first part of his narrative, which culminated in the Other’s revelation in inner experience as the ethical event that generates the separated self, Levinas acknowledges that this constellation, the ethical relation, in order to exist, must persist, namely be in time. The second part of Levinas’s narrative thus deals with the episteme of difference not as a structure of the individual conscience, but as a culture or world of knowledge, as a historical episteme, a civilization.
One point should be carefully noted, concerning the trans-epistemic happening. My initial reading of Totality and Infinity suggested that this book stages a confrontation between two distinct traditions of knowledge, two conflicting epistemes, Totality and Infinity, Philosophers vs. Prophets, Greek vs. Jewish. My analysis of Levinas’s narrative, however, produced a more complex picture. The point of departure for history—time—in Levinas’s narrative is not a conflict between two opposite epistemes, Greek and Jewish, but a Jewish-Greek(-French) episteme, a fusion of Moses and Plato, Philosophy founded on Prophecy, moral rationalism. This means that the actual inter-epistemic drama in Totality and Infinity does not play between Greek and Jewish, but between two different performances of their composition, between two different configurations of the West.
The possibility of multiple simultaneous performances of the same constellation requires a certain contingency, a moment of indeterminacy within the conceptual structure. The possibility of multiplicity, where something such as event or history, something such as time, takes place, this possibility, the possible par excellence, marks the real location of otherness in the narrative. The emergence of otherness is a constitutive moment in all narratives, since it established the very possibility of story, the mythical foundation of myth. This event, as the emergence of contingency, of freedom, is marked by a moment when things do not work as they should, where something happens that should not, when things go wrong. History begins with evil. Biblical mythology is based on a story of sin and fall. Fall, Verfall, is also a foundational moment in Heidegger’s narrative, set in motion by Dasein’s fall into improper existence, Uneigentlichkeit. Totality and Infinity uses a different Heideggerian category, more epistemic one: “forgetfulness”.
The possibility of forgetting the other arises from the nature of otherness. The separate individual, constituted in correlation to the other, can forget the other. Levinas identifies this possible oblivion of otherness as the possibility of forgetting God, “atheism” (TI 188, pp. 172–73, 197, 181), which attests to the very power of creation, creating a creature so independent it is capable of forgetting its creator.
In Levinas’s analysis, by forgetting the other, the self closes on itself, oblivious to ethics, generating “the possibility of injustice and radical egoism” (TI 188, 173). Here lies the origin of evil and of history. However, the historical evil that Totality and Infinity is concerned with is the rise of totality, namely the disappearance of the individual ego. This is the epistemo-political pathology that Levinas diagnoses in Western Philosophy “from Plato to Heidegger”—total logos and total state. One of the important insights developed in Totality and Infinity is that totality, the forgetting of individuality, arises from self-identification. Totality arises from individualism. This was visible in the “experience of totality” generated by self-identification through others. The same dynamics now repeats itself in the new dimension opened by the relation to otherness, namely in the realm of reason. Forgetting the ethical foundation of reason, the uninhibited self perverts reason to an instrument of self-identification—to totalizing ontology. This perversion constitutes the being of the separate self in time, “beyond the face”, as history. Philosophy, episteme of totality, would be the historical episteme of Jewish-Greek knowledge that forgot its Jewish origins, its foundation on ethical transcendence and reestablished immanence.
This episteme of totality would be the first, problematic historical configuration of difference epistemology, its perverted version. The pathology appears in both constitutive dimensions of difference epistemology, namely in language and in ethics. We saw that “language” is Levinas’s most fundamental characterization of the medium in which the episteme of difference exists. Separation is a relation of language. Accordingly, the perversion of this relation is a perversion of language. It is language that enables evil, forgetfulness, history, totality.
Totality and Infinity identifies the perversion of language in
writing. Whereas the Other is absolutely present to me in living speech, in the voice, written language would be the diminished form of language. The pathology of spoken language, the origin of evil, would be the sign. “The sign”, Levinas writes, “is a mute language, an impeded language” (TI 199, 182). Built on absence, the sign is the site of negativity.
27The perversion of language, writing, at the same time perverts ethics.
Totality and Infinity identifies the fallen form of morality in politics. Language as writing, as “work”, Levinas notes, constitutes “the tyranny of the State” (TI 191, 176).
28 The State, the
polis, what Levinas calls here “politics”, would be the perverted form of justice. The problem is totality. The State is the materialized manifestation of impersonal logos, which overcomes difference in the total system, and so “reduces all ethics to politics” (TI 239, 216), generating “a tyranny of the universal and of the impersonal.” (TI 271, 242) The historical figure that comes to mind here is Rome, the Judeo-Greek Empire and closer to Levinas, all the phenomena analyzed by Hannah Arendt as 20th century Totalitarianism.
The State is the perverted relation to the Other in time, the disfiguration of the Jewish-Greek, prophetic-philosophical episteme. It seeks to fulfill ethics through historical reason, which abolishes all individuality. Against this pathology, Levinas proposes an alternative, a more authentic West, committed to difference. This figure functions as the telos, the destination of Levinas’s demonstration. It emerges as the dramatic denouement, the rectification of evil, the return of the fallen, a—happy—end of history. In Heidegger’s narrative this eschaton appears as proper existence, Eigentlichkeit, in Rosenzweig’s drama as Redemption. In Levinas’s plot, this ultimate figure embodies the non-perverted, authentic performance of the Jewish-Greek episteme of difference. In opposition to Christian Rome, the enactment of Otherness in Hellenic means, we presume here a more Jewish enactment, a dissenting prophetic agency within the ontologized West. In contrast to the temporal performance of the ethical relation to infinity in the improper form of the State, as politics, Totality and Infinity identifies authentic ethical existence in time as religion.
Against the impersonal tyranny of politics, “the religious order” is “where the recognition of the individual concerns him in his singularity.” (TI 271, 242) The essence of “religious conscience”, Levinas writes, is the acknowledgment of a moral judgment outside history, a “judgment of God” (TI 273). Against time as totality, history, the time of states, religion requires a configuration of time as non-total, temporality that is predicated on infinity, an “infinite and discontinuous time” (TI 336). Infinite time means “infinite being”, which is the temporal being of the Infinite. The infinite being of the Infinite is the infinite being of the individual self’s
relation to infinity, the relation that constitutes individuality. Infinite time implies the infinite being of the separate self, the infinite individual. The infinite individual is individual beyond finitude, beyond the finite, mortal, singular self, beyond “Me”. The individual beyond the singular is the
plural individual self. Accordingly, religion is the dimension in which the relation to the other, ethics, is enacted in time, beyond the singular individual, not as a State, but as a plural Subject, a plural self, a “We”. The authentic performance of the prophetic episteme of difference would be a We, a
people. Indeed, against the common reading of Levinas’s “religion” in
Totality and Infinity as based on individual ethics, I suggest that this is the authentic dimension of collective existence, of society and also of politics.
29It is instructive to note how Levinas’s epistemic configuration of the prophetic collective performance, to which the last section of Totality and Infinity is dedicated, challenges the structure of separation, which this configuration is nonetheless called to perform. This redeeming episode takes the narrative back to its earliest stage, before the situation where totality broke up, before the encounter with the voice, before the face, before the absolute Other, before revelation. We are taken back to interiority. More precisely, we are taken back to the encounter with the relative absolute other, with the Feminine, who is the other that remains interior to the self’s experience, the other who is no master, no vous, but a familiar tu. It is in the familiar relation of the (essentially masculine) subject to the woman, before absolute separation, which infinite being is generated, where infinity comes into being.
Let us look how this realm of being is configured with respect to the two basic features of Levinas’s epistemology of difference, language and ethics. The feminine face does not speak. It signifies by its “feminine beauty”, which signifies the lack of signifying, and therewith the “disfigurement” of the face (TI 294; 263). What the feminine face expresses is ”its renunciation of expression and speech” (TI 295, 263). The feminine other is encountered in silence. Since otherness exists as present in the voice, the silent relation to the feminine brings the subject into contact with no presence, with no absolute being, which means that it is no longer—or not yet—a relation of separation.
The ethical essence of this relation, as an attitude of the self toward the other, is not performed in moral self-restraint, in “no”, but in voluptuosity, in sexuality, in eros. In Levinas’s analysis, eros supersedes separation, unites the self and the other, man and woman, to generate the child, who is “at the same time other and myself” (TI 298). In fecundity, relating to the other, transcendence, means becoming the other, “transubstantiation” (TI 298). This is how the singular individual becomes a plural individual, becomes family. Family is the existence of individuality beyond the finite individual, it is the infinite individual being, the “ultimate structure” of being, “produced as multiple and as split in Same and Other” (TI 301). As a counter-vision to the temporal performance of ethics as politics, namely as State, which is a universal totality, with no individuality, Levinas posits the performance of ethics as the plural individual subject, the “we” of the family. “The family does not only result from a rational arrangement of animality; it does not simply mark a step toward the anonymous universality of the State. It identifies itself outside of the State, even if the State reserves a framework for it.” (TI 342, 306)
The family is the ultimate figure of
Totality and Infinity, as the paradigm of authentic ethical existence in time, not as a total State but as a plural individual self-identifying Subject, as “We”. In other words, the family is the paradigm of collective ethical existence that is not based on the category of the
polis, not “political”, but instead based on the notion of the people as a collective individual subject, what in modern categories is often called
nation. Levinas does not use this category here
30, and as I noted the common reading situates Levinas family in the sphere of individual or private ethics, whose political corollary, “fraternity”, is simply universal bond of all humankind. Nevertheless, it is my contention that the Family functions in
Totality and Infinity as the epitome of the people as the infinite collective
individual being of the infinite, namely of God’s people. God’s people is the multitude that becomes individualized, unified in specific collective self-identity, by being collectively subjected to commandments, by election for infinite responsibility for the Infinite, chosen for the Good, for God. Levinas does not say this explicitly, but once again his text can be decoded to indicate, against a Greek state-based, a Jewish people-based social thought and against a Greek performance of the Jewish-Greek episteme of difference in the historical-political figure of Rome, a Jewish performance in the figure of Israel, whose historicity is not properly speaking historical, and whose politics is not properly political. This reading has the advantage of connecting
Totality and Infinity to the entire discourse of “Israel” in Levinas’s Jewish writings, with the political complexity of messianic “universalist particularism”.
31It is here—in meta-politics—that the surprising affinity to Heidegger appears.
32 Levinas’s positing of the family as a counter-figure to the state, a collective subject against a total object, indeed calls to mind the famous §74 of
Being and Time, where Heidegger portrays
Dasein’s authentic existence as “destiny”, namely—in contrast to the inauthentic, objectified and de-individualized “they” (
man)–, “the event [
Geschehen] of the community, of the people [
Volk]” (BT 384, 436). This passage has become the main piece of evidence brought up by critics of Heidegger to prove his early attachment to nationalism.
33 Heidegger too does not use the term “nation” in this context, and §74 offers different, more nuanced readings of the nature of the community Heidegger is speaking of, which do not necessarily lead to and
völkisch ideology.
And yet, thinking with Levinas himself, whose entire project explicitly seeks to turn away from Heidegger, as an alleged representative of the entire Western philosophy, based on the paradigm of unity, we should ask whether positing the “family” as a corrective to the state does not raise fundamental difficulties. Indeed, Hannah Arendt, whom I already paralleled to Levinas as a contemporary anti-totalitarian thinker, certainly did not consider the genealogical conception of the collective subject, the nation-family, as resistance to totalitarianism, but on the contrary as being, through the category of “race”, the main ideological vehicle of modern totalitarian movements. She showed how it was precisely the combination of divine election (“God’s people”) with statelessness that made the Jewish people into a source of inspiration for race-based imperialism.
34 Arendt identified this inspiration as perversion, but her answer to this imperial perversion was not a better politics of chosen people. On the contrary, her response to Western totalitarian imperialism was a return to the Greek politics of
polis, which is no infinite being, but a territorially—and metaphysically—limited state.
35It is noteworthy that Totality and Infinity provides a last, very brief indication towards a horizon in which the notion of the plural subject as infinite being regains the structure of totality. The collective self remains—this is the whole point—an individual self, which, by the very logic of separation, exists in self-identification, namely in generating—a collective—“experience of totality”. “Truth”, Levinas writes in the last lines of his narrative, “demands both an infinite time and a time that it may seal—a completed time. The completion of time is not death, but messianic time where the perpetual is converted into eternal. Messianic triumph is pure triumph. It is secured against the revenge of evil whose return the infinite time does not prohibit. Is this eternity a new structure of time, or an extreme vigilance of the messianic consciousness?” (TI 318, 284–85).
“Truth” is the epistemic core of religion, as the people’s collective self-conscience. It demands more than the sense of surpassing finite individual destinies, more than “infinite time”. It also demands “a completed time”, namely a notion of ultimate purpose, a destination, an
eschaton, an end of time. In this vision infinity becomes eternity. Redemption is complete and final, total. “Pure triumph” leaves no place for “evil”, which is however, as I indicated in Levinas’s own narrative, precisely the Other in logos. Levinas leaves open—“the problem exceeds the bounds of this book”—whether this total vision of eternity is “a new structure of time, or an extreme vigilance of the messianic consciousness”, namely—to read these words with Rosenzweig in mind
36—a new Christian Israel or an eternal Jewish people.