1. Introduction
The study of early Buddhist Nikāya texts sometimes confronts us with passages which are very enigmatic and puzzling. One such a passage from the
Nibbānasukha-sutta of the
Aṅguttara-nikāya (AN 9.34/iv.413–418) contains a statement which is attributed to Sāriputta, the Buddha’s leading disciple. The passage reads:
Exactly this, friend, is pleasure (
sukhaṃ) here, that nothing is experienced (
vedayitaṃ) here.
1
Sāriputta’s paradoxical proclamation and its implications will serve as a point of departure of this paper. Before examining it in greater detail, it is worthwhile explaining the context in which it is delivered. The sutta starts with the following words spoken by Sāriputta:
This
nibbāna, o friend, is pleasure.
2In itself, this claim can hardly be considered controversial.
Nibbāna is considered the ultimate good in Buddhism, and there are many texts which suggest that it can be attained during life. Therefore, it is not particularly problematic to conceive of someone who has achieved
nibbāna as enjoying the highest form of pleasure. However, upon hearing Sāriputta’s proclamation, his interlocutor, Udāyī, asks:
But friend Sāriputta, what pleasure could be here when nothing is experienced here?
3
It is in response to this question that Sāriputta makes the already mentioned claim that pleasure lies in the fact that nothing is being experienced. In order to illustrate it, he describes the standard Nikāya list of the nine successive meditative states, starting with the first
jhāna and ending with the cessation of apperception and experience (
saññāvedayitanirodha).
4 According to Sāriputta, while being in each of the first eight states, there are apperceptions and acts of attention (
saññāmanasikāra) connected (
sahagata) with the gross mental factors of the directly preceding state of consciousness (e.g., with sensuality [
kāma]) which might assail (
samudācarati) the meditator and which Sāriputta describes as affliction (
ābādha). It is only with regard to the final of the nine meditative states, the cessation of apperception and experience, that no mention is made of any danger of this kind anymore. At this stage, the meditator “having seen with understanding (
paññāya)”, has his effluents (
āsava) completely exhausted (
parikkhīṇa),
5 which is tantamount to achieving the final goal of the Buddhist path.
2. Aims of This Paper
Let us return to the question of the meaning and implications of Sariputta’s paradoxical utterance. If we approach it assuming a commonsense understanding of the terms used within it, it must appear inherently incoherent or even absurd. Pleasure is, after all, a form of experience. Therefore, if nothing is experienced, then by the very definition of this word, there cannot be any pleasure in such a state.
Of course, we must be wary of the possibility that Sāriputta’s statement represents a kind of poetic license, and its author may have simply gotten carried away with religious rhetoric without fully realizing its implications. Therefore, one could perhaps claim that it should not be held to any high philosophical standards and that reading too much into it may be a mistake. We also have no way of knowing whether historical Sāriputta is the real author of this statement and if it is even representative of a hypothetical original Buddhist doctrine, or it is perhaps a crude later insertion.
But could it be that it is we who are missing something here? Perhaps, instead of explaining away Sāriputta’s statement as a form of rhetoric, we should consider it as an inspiration to re-examine some of our most basic commonsense beliefs. Therefore, for the purpose of this paper, let us lay aside the questions regarding the historical authenticity of this statement and the real intentions of its author. The philosophical implications of Sāriputta’s claim are interesting enough to consider them seriously. The history of human thought knows of cases in which chronologically later interpretations of older ideas have brought out their revolutionary implications, which may not have been intended or acknowledged by their original authors.
Let us therefore try to take Sāriputta’s statement at face value and consider its radical implications. It may appear absurd to us when we approach it from a commonsense perspective, but perhaps when viewed against a specific philosophical backdrop, it can appear much less paradoxical and more plausible. In this paper, we will attempt to reconstruct such a backdrop. As we shall see, trying to make sense of Sāriputta’s statement will necessitate a re-examination of other enigmatic passages in the Nikāyas and inspire us to rethink several connected issues, including those related to the structure of experience, consciousness, its relation to our identity and the nature of suffering and pleasure. These are philosophical problems of universal relevance, independent of any historical and cultural context, and our considerations may have implications reaching far beyond the early Buddhist context.
3. On the Meaning of vedayita and sukha
The philosophical meaning of Sāriputta’s statement depends on the understanding of the specific concepts it refers to, in particular those of
vedayita and
sukha.
Vedayita is the past participle form of the verb
vedeti and means “experienced” or “felt” (
Rhys Davids and Stede 2007, p. 648). If we read
vedayita in the sense of “feeling” and as merely referring to affectively valent aspects of our experiences, which may or may not accompany them, then the absence of
vedayita could be interpreted as a way of experiencing in a neutral, equanimous way without any emotional reactions, akin to Stoic
apatheia (
ἀπάθεια). However, the Nikāya context in which this term occurs suggests something different. According to a relatively common stock passage (e.g., MN 148/iii.285), that which is experienced/felt (
vedayita) as either pleasant, painful, or neither pleasant nor painful, arises dependently (
paccaya) on a contact (
phassa) of a particular sense (e.g., eye—
cakkhu), its respective object and consciousness (
viññāṇa). Therefore, even an affectively neutral (i.e., neither pleasant nor painful) visual experience of an object can be said to be a form of
vedayita. Let us again emphasize that when Sāriputta elaborates his claim in the
Nibbānasukha-sutta that
sukha is synonymous with nothing being experienced (
vedayita), he presents lower meditative states as endangered by being assailed by various types of apperceptions and acts of attention (
saññāmanasikāra), which only cease in the state of
saññāvedayitanirodha. The terms
saññā and
manasikāra do not really carry any connotations of affective aspects of experience, and yet for Sāriputta, they are clearly forms of
vedayita. Therefore,
vedayita must refer to conscious experience in its entirety, and not merely its affective tone.
One could also consider the possibility that
sukha does not refer to a momentary form of pleasure, but to happiness in a much more general, lasting and abstract sense, like the Greek philosophical concepts of happiness (
εὐδαιμονία) or lasting joy (
χαρά), as opposed to momentary pleasure (
ἡδονή). In such a case, not experiencing any momentary states could perhaps be interpreted as some abstract, higher form of happiness. However, regardless of whether we translate
sukha as pleasure (
Bodhi 2020, p. 528), wellbeing, happiness, ease, or comfort (
Rhys Davids and Stede 2007, p. 716), in the Nikāya context, this term refers to a positive affect (i.e., subjective affective state of positive valence)
6 felt during a particular timeframe and not to some general abstract form of happiness. In other words, one can only meaningfully speak of
sukha as a state in which a particular person may or may not be at a particular moment. The above considerations show the difficulties associated with translating certain Pali words into English in a way that would perfectly capture their implied meaning in a particular Nikāya passage. This is also the case with the Pali word
dukkha, which has been varyingly translated as pain, distress or trouble.
7 Therefore, for the sake of clarity, we will be generally referring directly to these Pali terms and not to the English words which correspond to them.
4. Vedayita, dukkha and the Aggregates
It is noteworthy that the statements of Udāyī and Sāriputta imply some important views that are not explicitly stated within the text itself. Udāyī’s question assumes that he conceives of nibbāna as a state in which there is no vedayita. The way his question is delivered suggests that, for the author of this text, this seemed to be an uncontroversial truth and as such, it was pretty much taken for granted. It is also clear from Sāriputta’s account of meditative progress through the nine stages that he considered saññāvedayitanirodha to be a perfect exemplification of a state in which there is no vedayita, and which is thus sukha. Sāriputta’s view that perceptions and acts of attention connected with sublime spiritual qualities such as rapture (pīti) and equanimity (upekkhā), which characterize the states of consciousness preceding cessation (e.g., the fourth jhāna), are forms of affliction (ābādha) strongly implies that he considered all forms of vedayita to be dukkha.
This latter view is representative of a much wider trend in the Nikāyas. For example, the
Kaḷāra-sutta (SN 12.32/ii.53) contains a claim that “whatever is
vedayita is [within]
dukkha.
8 One often encounters a stock passage (e.g., SN 22.13/iii.21) describing each of the five aggregates as
dukkha. The famous line in the
Dhammacakkappavattana-sutta9 equates the whole set of the five aggregates connected with grasping (
pañcupādānakkhandha) with
dukkha. We shall consider the implications of these radical claims in the later part of this paper.
It thus appears that, in the Nikāyas, the denotation of
vedayita overlaps at least to a certain extent with that of
pañcakkhandha. The understanding of the latter concept may therefore shed some light on that of
vedayita and, by extension, on the understanding of Sāriputta’s statement. That the denotation of the concept of
vedayita overlaps at least to a certain extent with that of the five aggregates is hardly surprising, as the term
vedayita is etymologically very closely related to
vedanā, the second of the aggregates.
10What are the aggregates then? Recent decades of critical scholarship of early Buddhism have shown that we can no longer take for granted the seemingly obvious, historically dominant Theravādin interpretations of many key early Buddhist concepts, as they are often at odds with the Nikāya sources. While the historically dominant interpretation sees the aggregates as objective constituents of a human being, such a meaning is clearly not intended in the majority of the Nikāya texts. Rather, the
khandhas denote various aspects and elements of the ordinary conscious experience of the world from the first-person perspective. Here, due to the lack of space, we shall only briefly refer to the already existing results of research, without presenting any detailed arguments in their favor as they have already been offered in other places (e.g.,
Gethin 1986;
Hamilton 2000;
Wynne 2010;
Davis 2016;
Polak 2023b).
Furthermore, there are good reasons to believe that the terms constituting the set of the
khandhas in the Nikāyas do not refer to phenomena which can be sharply distinguished from one another, either in a temporal or experiential sense.
11 Rather, each of the aggregates refers to the same conscious experience, but with an emphasis on its different but complimentary aspects.
12 Every conscious phenomenal experience has conceptually structured content that is verbally expressible (
saññā), has an affectively valent tone which may be negative, positive or neutral (
vedanā), is phenomenally conscious (
viññāṇa), is both fabricated and fabricating and perfused by the subjective feeling of agency and will (
saṅkhāra), and is also an embodied experience, not occurring in some vacuum but always in relation to the human body as its central, constant element (
rūpa).
Thus, the denotations of vedayita and pañcakkhandha are pretty much the same, as both these terms refer to an ordinary form of conscious experience. The same conscious experience may be referred to by terms such as saññā, viññāṇa, or vedayita, although they will emphasize its difference aspects. The absence of vedayita spoken about by Sāriputta would thus probably also be tantamount with the absence of the remaining aggregates, such as saññā, viññāṇa or even rūpa, in the sense of the subjective phenomenal awareness of one’s own body.
But how could the absence of experience, understood as being synonymous with the absence of the five aggregates, be considered
sukha? We tend to understand “experience” in an all-or-nothing sense. According to this understanding, either one experiences something, or one does not experience anything at all. We also tend to identify experiencing with being conscious; if one experiences, then one is also conscious, or it can be said that one has a conscious experience.
13 If, in agreement with commonsense views, experiencing is fully synonymous with being sentient and engaged in the world, then having no experience will inevitably entail a state of blankness, akin to that of inanimate objects. While such a state is certainly without
dukkha, it can hardly be considered a state of
sukha, as the latter is, in the Nikāyas, considered a positive quality and not merely understood negatively as
adukkha—an absence of pain.
5. Is vedayita the Only Way of Being Sentient, Cognizant and Engaged in the World?
However, contrary to the historically dominant interpretation, the aggregates in the Nikāyas are not considered all that there is to a human being, or even to human cognition. In several Nikāya texts, crucial bodily and cognitive aspects of a human being are not conceptualized in terms of any of the
khandhas, and sometimes are explicitly juxtaposed to them.
14 Particularly important is the distinction between
citta/
cetas and the aggregates, and especially
viññāṇa. These terms occur in their own specific contexts and are associated with very different mental functions. Whenever the Nikāya texts speak about engaging the mental capabilities of an individual to perform specific tasks or describe their potency to do so, they use terms such as
citta or
ceto/cetas. On the other hand, when they describe the arising of the first-person phenomenal conscious experience, the term
viññāṇa is used.
All this has significant implications for understanding Sariputta’s statement. The type of experience or consciousness conceptualized in Nikāya texts as the aggregates or
vedayita does not need to be seen as the only possible way of being sentient, cognizant and engaged in the world, but rather as a specific mode of consciousness. As
Jay Garfield (
2015, p. 142) aptly notes:
Buddhist psychology recognizes multiple kinds and levels of consciousness including … sensory and conceptual forms of consciousness; consciousness that is introspectible and consciousness that is too deep for introspection … In general, the complex set of phenomena is opaque to casual introspection, and are knowable only theoretically or perhaps by highly trained meditators.
15
Thus, it is possible to conceive of the state of absence of
vedayita not in terms of the total absence of all forms of cognition and sentience, but only of ordinary consciousness in the sense of globally available content, i.e., the one that can be introspected and reflected upon, expressed in speech or movement, and memorized or recollected.
16 Such consciousness is often labelled as access consciousness, due to the fact that its content is accessible to various cognitive systems.
17 Afterall, we remember our conscious states, can attend to them, introspect them, think or talk about them. Ordinary consciousness is also generally considered to be a phenomenal or qualitative consciousness.
18 In modern cognitive science, there is also a general consensus that phenomenal consciousness correlates with global broadcasting (
Carruthers 2015, p. 49). We are leaving aside the question of whether phenomenality may be reduced to global availability, or whether there can be phenomenal consciousness whose content is not globally available. Ordinary consciousness is also a self-consciousness. This need not necessarily be a highly complex type of autobiographical self-consciousness, but may involve something like Damasio’s concept of the “core self”. The core self is said to be inherent in core consciousness, which “provides the organism with a sense of self about one moment, now, and about one place, here” (
Damasio and Meyer 2009, p. 6).
Tsakiris (
2017, p. 597) speaks about the “body self”: the sense of “body ownership that refers to the special perceptual status of one’s own body, the feeling that ‘my body’ belongs to me”.
One may ask at this point how the claim of the existence of the “core self” fits with the non-self approach in Buddhism. In response, it may be said that the notion of the core self merely refers to having a sense of being a self, and not to the objective fact of the existence of self. The former is of course merely an evolutionarily adaptive illusion helping the organism to appropriate its own states and conceive of itself as an individual. The fact that ordinary human beings possess a sense of being or having a self is of course not denied by Buddhism, but merely shown to be unfounded in the true state of things.
One encounters an overwhelmingly negative portrayal of the
khandhas and
vedayita in the Nikāyas, with the former even being defined as personal identity (
sakkāya).
19 In the
Ānanda-sutta (SN 22.21/iii.24–25), each of the aggregates is characterized as
saṅkhata, which, apart from the notion of being “fabricated”, seems to carry connotations of artificiality, being infused with agency, and rooted in ignorance. The
Parileyya-sutta (SN 22.81/iii.94–99) analyzes different types of regarding (
samanupassati) the aggregates as self. Every type of such regarding (
samanupassanā) is described as being a
saṅkhāra itself.
This calls into question whether it is possible to speak of neutral states of
khandhas existing prior to them becoming an object of mistaken appropriation or identification. One should rather consider the possibility that these attitudes are themselves states of
khandhas. In other words, the aggregates are not only mistakenly appropriated and regarded as self, but in themselves already involve an attitude of mistaken appropriation and self-view.
20 It is therefore problematic, if in awakened persons free from grasping and self-view, the aggregates would just continue as before, since their very presence seems to involve some form of cognitive delusion and be connected with maintaining a mistaken attitude. It is noteworthy that there are no accounts of the hypothetical purified aggregates not connected with grasping (i.e., “
anupādānakkhandas”) occurring in the arahants. From the fact that the Nikāyas sometimes speak about the five
khandhas without explicitly qualifying them as
upādānakkhandhas, it does not automatically follow that they are meant to be
anupādānakkhandas. It may just mean that these texts decided not to explicitly emphasize the aspect of grasping. According to the
Parivīmaṃsana-sutta (SN 12.51/ii.82), a bhikkhu who is free from ignorance does not make up (
abhisaṅkharoti)
saṅkhāras, even those meritorious (
puññābhisaṅkhāra) or imperturbable ones (
āneñjābhisaṅkhāra). The
Paramaṭṭhaka-sutta (Snp 4.5/156–158) claims that “a brahmin” does not fashion even the slightest
saññās with regard to the sense data.
It is also noteworthy that the aggregates in the Nikāyas possess some key characteristics of global accessibility. Conscious experience conceptualized in their terms can be attended to (SN 22.89/iii.131), introspected, and expressed in speech (AN 6.63/iii.413). For the sake of the flow of the text, in the remaining part of the paper, I will refer to what, in Pali, is conceptualized in terms of the khandhas (in particular, viññāṇa) and vedayita, as “consciousness” or “conscious experience”, in the ordinary, common-sense meaning of these words. Its features, such as phenomenality and global availability, will be implied, but not mentioned explicitly, unless they are to be specifically emphasized or analyzed in greater detail.
In early Buddhist terms, the absence of such consciousness would correspond to the absence of vedayita and the khandhas, but not necessarily to the insentience of the sensory faculties (indriya) and the inactivity of the mind (citta/cetas), connected with the total shutdown of its cognitive potency.
6. The Notion of Meditative Cessation of vedayita
But do the Nikāya texts actually contain a notion of a state in which the absence of conscious experience would not coincide with total mental and sensory stasis? As we have seen, Sāriputta considered
saññāvedayitanirodha to be the highest exemplification of a state in which there is no
vedayita and which is therefore
sukha. However, according to the historically dominant understanding of
saññāvedayitanirodha within Theravāda, it is a state akin to a vegetative coma in which all forms of cognition, sentience and engagement with the world are absent (e.g., Vism 2.344–351). If this is what Sāriputta meant when speaking about having nothing to experience, then such a state surely cannot be conceived in any way as connected with
sukha. But perhaps Sāriputta’s statement implied a different understanding of this concept. As it was the case with the notion of the aggregates, there is ample evidence to the effect that in the Nikāyas,
saññāvedayitanirodha was understood differently from its later, historically dominant interpretation within Theravāda. Several scholars (e.g.,
Hamilton 2000, p. 77;
Stuart 2013, p. 43;
Shulman 2014, pp. 33–34;
Polak 2023a) have noted that some elements of the Nikāya account of the attainment of cessation imply that this state was not connected with total insentience and mental stasis, but rather with the receptivity of the sense faculties and potency for cognitive insight and psychological transformation. The faculties (
indriya) of the meditator in this state are said to be very clear (
parisuddha), and he is described as “having seen” (
disvā) by means of understanding (
paññā). Understood in such a way,
saññāvedayitanirodha can meet the criteria of a state described by Sāriputta, in which the absence of
vedayita does not preclude the possibility of some form of
sukha.
Furthermore, a case can be made that the concept of
saññāvedayitanirodha was just one of several ways in which the early Buddhist authors attempted to conceptualize a more general notion of an apophatically described state during which even the most basic elements that constitute our ordinary conscious experience cease.
Animitta cetosāmadhi (featureless unification of the mind) may have been one such term used in this context. In the
Cūlasuññāta-sutta (MN 121/iii.103–109), it occupies a similar place to
saññāvedayitanirodha, as the apex of the meditative path, and directly follows the sphere of neither apperception nor non-apperception (
nevasaññānāsaññāyatana).
21 This type of cessation was, however, not supposed to occur through the total shutting down of the mind and the senses, resulting in their stasis, but via the suspension of higher-level processes connected with conceptuality and language, which are responsible for several key features of our standard consciousness. Such suspension could coincide with the unimpeded functioning of more basic processes of cognition, in which the senses remain active, but their input is not transformed into ordinary forms of consciousness. Perhaps exactly such an idea is conveyed by the
Mūlapariyāya-sutta (MN 1/i.1–6), which states that awakened beings do not perceive (
sañjānāti) reality but directly know it (
abhijānāti) as it really is. The already mentioned passage of the
Aṭṭhakavagga (Snp 4.5/156–157) speaks of a direct mode of cognition, where not even a minute
saññā is fashioned (
pakappita) with regard to what is seen, heard and sensed. The
Pārāyanavagga (Snp 5.13/214–215) speaks of a way of practicing mindfulness (
sati) that leads to a state in which “consciousness stops” (
viññāṇaṃ uparujjhati). The
Dutiyasikkhattaya-sutta (AN 3.90/i.235–236) describes the cessation of
viññāṇa coinciding with the release (
vimutti) of the mind (
cetas/ceto).
The notion of the ordinary form of consciousness conceptualized in terms of various
khandhas or
vedayita giving way to some purified mode of cognition parallels, to a certain extent, the Yogācāra idea of
āśraya-parāvṛtti (overturning of the basis). The latter concept refers to a fundamental transformation of cognition resulting from enlightenment. The eight ordinary consciousnesses (
vijñāna) characterized by dichotomous, bifurcating nature cease and are replaced by enlightened cognitive abilities (
jñāna), resulting in immediate, non-conceptual knowledge.
22 7. Is Consciousness an Ever-Present Feature of Our Being in the World?
So far, we have only been considering a hypothetical possibility of a dissociation of ordinary conscious experience from other cognitive processes that are not globally available in the sense of being transparent to introspection and reflection. But is such a dissociation possible from the perspective of modern psychology? As we have already noted, it is one of our most intuitive, commonsense tendencies to consider being conscious, in the common sense of this word, as the only way of being cognizant, sensitive, intelligent and engaged in the world.
However, the progress in psychology and cognitive science clearly shows that our commonsense (i.e., folk psychological) views about mental life are often fundamentally mistaken. There now exists overwhelming evidence that the actual processes responsible for our agency, active cognitive processing and creativity occur through multiple parallel unconscious processes that are not phenomenal in nature.
23 What is then the point of being conscious, if even complex cognitive functions are performed unconsciously?
Neuropsychologist Mark Solms
24 suggests that for an organism, consciousness is a a sort of an “alarm mechanism” (
Solms 2019, p. 13), which arises in response to an unusual situation, when automated and unconscious behavior patterns stored in its memory lead to an error and fail to meet the demands posed by new circumstances (
Solms 2021, pp. 220–22). Solms believes that the key adaptive feature of conscious experience is that it involves feelings, which, due to their range of affective valence (which varies between good and bad or pleasant and painful), guide our voluntary choices made in new, uncertain situations as they allow us to “feel” our way through various potential courses of action. Solms’s idea can be seen as complimentary to very influential theories of consciousness, which define it in terms of global availability, global accessibility or global broadcast.
25These theories claim that most of our cognitive processes occur in disjoint modules, which do not have access to one another’s output. However, especially when we are faced with a new problem that needs to be solved, it is useful to prioritize, within the cognitive system, the data connected with this problem by holding it in the working memory and therefore making it globally accessible for an extended period of time. Thus, instead of dealing with the situation in an automatic manner, various modules can combine their efforts to tackle the situation, and different potential courses of action may be compared and evaluated. It is especially useful for dealing with cognitive problems. By bringing conscious attention to the problem, it is presented to various modules, which can from that point work on it and present their initial solutions in a conscious form, sometimes during the unexpected Eureka moments. By becoming conscious and thus globally accessible, these suggestions can then be worked on further, until a satisfying solution is reached. This mechanism is also helpful for making long-term plans and rehearsing potential social interactions. This may have contributed to a particular prominence of this form of consciousness among humans as opposed to other animals.
Additional evolutionary reasons for developing globally accessible and phenomenally conscious mental states are connected with their representational role. An organism is a conglomerate of disjointed self-less processes that are not separated by any rigid borders from the environment. However, it can create a phenomenal model through which it experiences itself as a relatively unified entity, an agent of actions and subject of experiences. Thus, the self-less processes that are just a semi-autonomous part of the environment may appropriate their actions and the biological “hardware”, and conceive of themselves as individuals or persons (
Metzinger 2009). This occurs through the process in which the organism “identifies”
26 with its phenomenal model.
The fact that the aggregates are collectively defined as the personal identity (
sakkāya: SN 22.105/iii.159), and that they have an inherent potential to be misinterpreted as Self, suggests that they may correspond to what Metzinger calls the “phenomenal Self-model”. Therefore, one of the key aspects of seeing aggregates as self consists of a human being mistakenly identifying with one’s own consciousness.
27According to Solms’s hypothesis, which combines neuropsychology, thermodynamics and information theory, organisms usually tend to maintain their homeostasis and minimize the so-called free energy and entropy of the system. In terms of information theory, this means minimizing uncertainty and energy-inefficient cognitive processing. This, in turn, entails prioritizing fast and automatic unconscious behavior patterns at the expense of slow and less predictable conscious mechanisms whenever possible. This leads
Solms (
2021, p. 221) to what may appear to be a shocking conclusion, that “conscious state is undesirable from the viewpoint of a self-organizing system”, and that the ideal state is one “in which our needs are met automatically, we feel nothing”. Feeling nothing does not mean here that the senses and cognitive system fall into a coma-like state, but that there is no globally available experience of feeling accompanying them.
From the above characteristic, it is clear that despite its great importance, access consciousness need not be considered a constant and necessary feature of our engagement in the world. In fact, a case can be made that there are many moments in our lives when such consciousness is not present, but they cannot be integrated into our memory, and thus “we”, in the common sense of this word, cannot even become directly aware of them, though their existence can be inferred by other means.
8. Is Consciousness Generated at a Constant Rate? Re-Examining the Nature of Absorption
Some recent developments in cognitive science seem to support the notion of the discontinuity of consciousness. According to
Baars and Franklin (
2007, p. 959), “conscious cognition occurs as a sequence of discrete, coherent episodes separated by quite short periods of no conscious content”.
Dean Buonomano (
2017, pp. 216–17) suggests that “while the unconscious brain continuously samples and processes information about events unfolding in time, consciousness itself is generated in a highly discontinuous manner”.
Lionel Naccache (
2018, p. 7) considers the possibility that, during conscious wakefulness, “a form of high-level filling-in process may join discrete conscious states separated by short periods of unconsciousness into what we subjectively experience as a continuous stream of consciousness”. Therefore, according to Naccache, we would only be phenomenally conscious during “temporal islets interspersed with unconscious states”.
All this implies that there are intervals of objective physical time during which the brain does not generate globally available representations correlated with the occurrence of ordinary conscious experience.
28 However, merely establishing that consciousness is discontinuous and is not a constant feature of our being in the world does not allow us to make sense of Sāriputta’s problematic statement. We have not yet found any psychological correlation between the presence or absence of such consciousness and being in the affectively valent states corresponding to what the Nikāyas label as
dukkha and
sukha.
I believe that the evidence of such a correlation may be provided by the study of specific features of the states which have been variously called absorption (
Bronkhorst 2012), immersion, “identification with contents” (
Paoletti and Ben-Soussan 2020), skilled engagement (
Garfield 2015), skillful acting, or the flow experience (
Csikszentmihalyi 2013). While these terms are not entirely synonymous, they share certain common aspects which are of interest to us. They refer to the moments of being completely absorbed or immersed in a particular experience or an act, often connected with activities which are performed in a masterful manner and do not require conscious control. For the purpose of this paper, I will be referring to these states simply as “absorption”.
Mihaly Csikszentmihalyi (
2013, pp. 111–13) has enumerated several characteristics of such states, some of which are of particular importance to us, namely the merging of action with awareness, the distortion of the sense of time and the disappearance of self-consciousness. It is also commonplace that states of absorption are often connected with the feeling of pleasure, satisfaction or happiness (
Csikszentmihalyi 1996, p. 123;
Bronkhorst 2012, p. 11). An important characteristic of this state is that it is not fully transparent to deliberate acts of introspection, or to put it differently, the very feature of forgetting oneself that characterizes absorption precludes the possibility of deliberately introspecting it. The first-person reports of these states are therefore, to a significant extent, based on their memories.
We shall now consider a tentative hypothesis that these specific features of absorption are correlated with the relative level of absence/presence of access consciousness during a particular interval of physical time. It needs to be emphasized at this point that the Nikāyas do not contain a notion of absorption as a state occurring during non-meditative activities. We will also not find in these texts any discussions of the alteration of the sense of psychological time, which is one of the key features of absorbed states. As we shall see, however, considering the question of the mechanism responsible for these specific features of absorption will prove crucial for understanding the nature of the correlation between the absence of ordinary consciousness and being in the state of sukha, which may allow us to make sense of Sāriputta’s claim in the Nibbānasukha-sutta.
9. What Accounts for the Specific Features of Absorbed States?
It is generally recognized that the subjective feeling of the passage of time is not identical to objective, physical time.
Csikszentmihalyi (
2013, p. 113) has noted that during flow (i.e., absorption):
The sense of time becomes distorted. Generally in flow we forget time, and hours may pass by in what seem like a few minutes.
What mechanism accounts for this phenomenon? Is the relative speed of the passage of time at a particular moment of our conscious experience given to us in an immediate and intuitive manner, and can it be immediately known through some inner sense, just like the instantaneous speed of a car is displayed on the speedometer? The currently dominant models in cognitive science suggest that there is no internal “timer” of psychological time, but that its sense is constructed from processed and stored information (
Block and Zakay 1996, p. 189).
In normal conditions, one usually assesses the duration of a particular time interval after it has ended. This corresponds to the so-called retrospective paradigm of psychological timing (
Zakay and Block 2004, p. 320), where duration judgement relies on information retrieved from memory. One of the more interesting versions of the latter model has been proposed by
Ornstein (
1969, pp. 101–5), who has suggested that subjectively perceived duration depends on how much information or mental content connected with the time interval in question has been stored in memory; in other words, it depends “on a number of occurrences in the interval which reach awareness”. This hypothesis assumes that the two time intervals that last the same amount of physical time may be associated with different quantities of mental content or a different number of “occurrences which reach awareness”, to use Ornstein’s wording. While counterintuitive, this claim agrees well with the notion of the discontinuity of ordinary consciousness that we have considered above. This leads to a further question: what mechanism determines the quantity of mental content and the number of “occurrences which reach awareness” during a particular time interval?
The hypothesis I would like to consider is that the subjective estimate of the duration of psychological time is at least to some extent based on the quantity of moments of ordinary consciousness, or in other words, their “density” during a time interval. We have already mentioned the claims made by
Baars and Franklin (
2007),
Buonomano (
2017),
Naccache (
2018) and
Solms (
2021) to the effect that ordinary consciousness is not generated constantly and continuously, and does not faithfully keep up with the processing of sensory stimuli occurring in the brain in physical time. We are not aware of any blank moments, because due to a specific way of processing the original sensory input and filling in the gaps, we experience and remember our consciousness as a continuous stream. There seems to exist some structural affinity between ordinary consciousness and memory. The content of consciousness is correlated with the data that are held in working memory,
29 and which eventually may or may not be integrated into long-term memory. I do not claim that this is the only mechanism that accounts for the assessment of the duration of psychological time, but it is bound to influence it in a significant manner.
To sum things up, different experiences, despite spanning the same interval of physical time, may be connected with a different quantity of moments of consciousness that can be integrated into memory. Thus, upon recollecting, these experiences will be evaluated as having a different duration. A fewer number of occurrences of such consciousness during a particular time interval means that we assess them as involving less psychological time. During moments of flow or absorption, the quantity and frequency of the moments that are conscious in the introspectable sense are relatively low compared to an ordinary state. As a result, we associate them with a quicker passage of time, because when comparing them to ordinary experiences occurring in the same timeframe of physical time, we notice that there is less to recollect. This also accounts for a well-known phenomenon of surprise; when after being absorbed one looks at the clock and is surprised to learn how much time has passed, despite subjectively being aware of a relatively lesser amount of psychological time.
On reading this, one may raise a very natural objection, that the very moments of absorption cannot involve the total absence of both phenomenal and access consciousness, as it is possible to recall their “what it is like” phenomenal character or simply to remember them and talk about their quality. One may also vividly remember being self-conscious during at least particular moments of an absorbed state, even though the general degree of self-awareness associated with the whole time interval of absorption may be substantially lessened. One response to that could be to suggest that this a post hoc result of processing, a sort of a constructed memory or a confabulation.
30 However, I think that the truth is more nuanced. No ordinary experience of absorption involves relatively long, uninterrupted periods of the absence of access consciousness. In other words, even during strong absorption, access consciousness still arises intermittently, though with much lesser frequency than during an ordinary state. Still, the frequency of conscious moments is high enough to prevent us from becoming aware of any discontinuities in our consciousness.
31 Therefore, what one remembers from absorption are just the moments of ordinary access consciousness that intersperse it. It is just that in case of absorption, there is generally less to remember. Absorption proper, in the sense of the absence of access consciousness, cannot be registered by memory.
32 Being able to introspect “what it is like” to be absorbed, i.e., being in a state of access consciousness, implies that one is actually no longer absorbed at that specific moment.
33 Paoletti and Ben-Soussan (
2020, p. 11) acknowledge this paradox by stating that, in the moment we voluntarily pay attention to ourselves, we are no longer completely identified (i.e., absorbed). In cognitive science, the activities of introspecting, thinking about or recollecting our conscious experiences are sometimes labelled as forms of “conscious metacognition”. As
Baars et al. (
2021) note, absorbed experiences are characterized by an attenuation of such metacognition.
Furthermore, the assessments of the speed of the passage of psychological time or the “what it is like” character of absorption occur not only after the absorbed activity or experience has ended completely, but also during the moments of access consciousness that intermittently arise during it. That is why we have a sense that we can assess, to some extent, the quality of an absorbed experience while being absorbed, and not only after it has completely ended.
The relatively fewer number of occurrences of consciousness during absorption would also account for the sense of attenuation of self-consciousness. As we have suggested, every moment of ordinary access consciousness involves a core sense of self-consciousness.
34 Therefore, upon recollecting an absorbed experience, we may acknowledge that there was “less of us” in it, compared to some ordinary experience occurring within the same interval of physical time.
On this account, the relative strength of absorption could be ultimately explained in terms of a more basic factor, namely the number of occurrences of consciousness with which it would be negatively correlated. This implies that the maximal level of absorption would result in the total absence of conscious experience during the time interval in which such an absorption would take place. Were such an absorption to last long enough, it could not but result in a blank moment or a memory gap.
35 10. What Makes a State Pleasant? Absorption and Pleasure
Another important aspect of the states of absorption is their connection to pleasure and satisfaction. This is especially relevant to our investigation, as it may bring us closer to understanding the nature of the connection between the absence of vedayita and the presence of sukha proclaimed by Sāriputta, especially as we have already hypothesized that absorption is characterized by a relatively higher degree of absence of an ordinary form of consciousness.
Csikszentmihalyi (
1996, p. 123) has observed that:
[W]hen we are in flow, we do not usually feel happy—for the simple reason that in flow we feel only what is relevant to the activity… It is only after we get out of flow, at the end of a session or in moments of distraction within it, that we might indulge in feeling happy.
This appears to be the same type of paradox as the one we have already discussed in connection with the impossibility of being introspectively conscious of the state of absorption in the exact moment in which it occurs. But why would absorption be pleasurable? In a series of valuable contributions,
Bronkhorst (
2012,
2016,
2019,
2022,
2023) has adapted the theory of absorption to the context of early Buddhist studies. He (
Bronkhorst 2012) has hypothesized that pleasure and happiness are directly connected to the states of lowered bodily tension. According to
Bronkhorst (
2012, pp. 126–27), in normal states of consciousness, there is always a certain degree of tension that is either mobilized in anticipation of future social interaction, or to resist the urges inducing us to actions which may have negative consequences from the perspective of the reality assessment of the “main unit” of our mind. This main unit is the central element of our personality responsible for reality assessment and regulating the fulfilment of our urges. In other words, in normal states of consciousness, we are bound to feel a certain amount of displeasure, as we just cannot be completely free of tension. The idea that the level of bodily tension is negatively correlated to that of pleasure is certainly promising and agrees with some commonly shared human experiences,
36 but is yet scientifically unconfirmed in its entirety.
37 However, let us for the sake of our argument assume that it may be true and see where it leads us.
The question of what exactly makes us consider a particular state pleasant or unpleasant has been the subject of intense academic debate. We experience states connected with very diverse contents as pleasant, and they include images, sounds, tastes, smells, tactile sensations and thoughts. But what is it exactly that makes us consider them pleasant? What common denominator, if any, do they share? According to the so-called phenomenological theories, what makes us experience something as pleasant, is how it feels. One such theory is the “distinctive feeling theory” which claims that “for an experience to be pleasant (or unpleasant) is just for it to involve or contain a distinctive kind of feeling, one we might call ‘the feeling of pleasure itself’,” (
Bramble 2013, p. 202). The same can be said regarding the experience of pain. The problem with phenomenological theories is that despite their appeal to commonsense views, it is very problematic to distinguish any specific, universal phenomenal “feel” present in each pleasant state from its unique, particular content (e.g., a certain combination of images, sounds, or tactile sensations). A different approach is taken by the “attitudinal theories”, which claim that pleasant experiences are those which are liked, wanted, or approved of when they last, while the opposite is true regarding the unpleasant ones. However, such theories only affirm the fact that we want or do not want certain experiences to continue, but do not explain why exactly we do. Therefore, they do not explain the fundamental mechanism responsible for our assessment of certain states as pleasant.
Above, we have hypothesized that the strength of absorption is negatively correlated with the number of occurrences of consciousness within the time interval in which absorption happens. If, in accordance with commonly shared experiences, the pleasant character of absorption is directly correlated with its strength, then it should also be negatively correlated with the “density” of moments of conscious experience. If the level of tension is negatively correlated with the strength of absorption, then this would imply that it is also positively correlated with the frequency of occurrences of access consciousness. It is commonplace that we find tension unpleasant, while relaxation is comfortable. Therefore, the presence of consciousness would be correlated with displeasure and possibly tension, while its absence with pleasure and possibly relaxation. This would explain the fact observed by Csikszentmihalyi, namely, that we cannot directly attend to our happiness while in the state of absorption proper, since according to our hypothesis, the latter is correlated with the absence of access consciousness. This would also perfectly harmonize with Sāriputta’s statement, which suggests that the absence of vedayita is sukha. But this leads to another question, namely, why would exactly tension be correlated with the presence of consciousness and relaxation with its absence?
11. Tension and Self-Consciousness
There have been some attempts in Western psychological thought to show the connection of tension with the sense of agency and selfhood. For example, psychologist Kurt Lewin claimed that when there is a wish or intention (i.e., a form of conscious agency), there arise tensions which strive for a discharge and make us ready to perform an action (
Lindorfer 2021). Gestalt psychologist Kurt Koffka believed that the Ego is made up of tension systems which owe their existence to one’s needs and interact with the environment. Upon the satisfaction of these needs, the tensions will be relaxed and redistributed throughout the whole system (
Stemberger 2021). In
Bronkhorst’s (
2012) theory, which heavily draws on Freud, tension is used by what he calls “the main unit”, which “incorporates the reality assessment of the person as a whole” and “directs, and often redirects the majority of that person’s urges” (
Bronkhorst 2012, p. 100); it can thus be seen as a sort of a central element of our personality, a type of an acting self. The tension is used to keep in check the urges which originate within parts of our psyche that are not integrated with the main unit and are unwanted from its perspective.
As we have hypothesized, every instant of ordinary conscious experience involves a form of very basic self-consciousness. We have considered Solms’s hypothesis stating that, from an evolutionary standpoint, the generation of consciousness is supposed to be reserved for special conditions in which automatized responses are not sufficient, and that it is actually preferable for the organism to stay in a state of non-conscious automaticity. Therefore, generating and maintaining consciousness may put some strain on the organism, resulting in displeasure. By that, I do not mean that dukkha is precisely the tension that supposedly accompanies every instance of self-consciousness. As I will be trying to show in the following sections, “tension” may not even be the most apt term to describe the fundamental mechanism that is connected with the generation of consciousness. It is safest to speak merely about the correlation of the presence of self-consciousness, dukkha and the state of the body, which we have tentatively labelled as “tension”. Just as is the case with pleasure, the actual cause of displeasure may not be available for introspection. Displeasure is an evolutionary signal motivating the organism to do something in order to amend its situation, so that it can return to a comfortable state of homeostasis, in which its needs are taken care of in an automatic way. Thus, the arising of consciousness, the generation of “tension” and the feeling of displeasure are closely correlated aspects of the mechanism that organisms use in order to deal with problematic situations.
However, for ordinary people, self-consciousness seems to be present on an almost constant basis, even during periods of idleness, when they engage in mental monologue or mind wandering. It seems that due to the acquisition of language, and the demands of our complicated social life, it is evolutionarily adaptive to consciously rehearse potential verbal interactions and courses of actions, thus making them globally accessible for various cognitive systems for further evaluation and potential modification. Let us note that such moments seem to be the opposite of absorption in the sense of an enhancement of one’s self-consciousness, the slow passage of psychological time, boredom and mental discomfort. According to our hypothesis, this would be explainable by the higher frequency of the occurrences of moments of consciousness during such a time interval.
Secondly, due to what in
Metzinger’s (
2009) terms may be conceptualized as the identification of the organism with its own phenomenal self-model, the former considers the latter’s absence to be tantamount to one’s own annihilation. The Ego is the content of the phenomenal self-model (
Metzinger 2009, p. 8), and is constituted by bodily sensations, emotional states, perceptions, memories, acts of will and thoughts. The phenomenal self-model pretty much corresponds to the globally available contents of our phenomenal consciousness. Therefore, the organism will keep generating such consciousness to maintain what it mistakenly perceives to be its own existence (i.e., the presence of consciousness), and prevent what it considers to be its annihilation (i.e., absence of consciousness). This idea has a direct parallel in the Nikāya notion of an ordinary person believing oneself to be the aggregates and thus producing them (
abhinibbatteti: SN 22.100/iii.152), just like a painter paints a faithful but ultimately inanimate effigy of a human being, and to taking up the uncomfortable burden (
bhāra) of the
khandhas (SN 22.22/iii.25–26). Of course, on such a reading, this production must not be understood in an ontic sense of generating constituents of the mind-independent reality, but in an epistemic sense of producing a specific form of experience.
38 This process results from cognitive delusion and actually leads to an intensification of discomfort. This explains why instead of falling into a pleasurable state of effortless absorption whenever we are idle, we constantly maintain self-consciousness and thus bring
dukkha upon ourselves.
According to a very interesting hypothesis by
Bronkhorst (
2012), our ignorance regarding the real source of pleasure generates the psychological mechanism of craving or desire (
taṇhā). Due to the fact that memory traces do not record absorption itself, we mistakenly associate pleasure with the objects and situations which once accompanied it, and not with its actual cause, which is the state of the absence of tension. Afterwards, we desire to repeat the experience of these objects and situations, unaware that they were not the actual proximal cause of pleasure. And indeed, it is commonplace that despite trying to repeat certain experiences, we usually fail to find that special quality with which we associate them in our memory. As
Bronkhorst (
2012, p. 147) aptly points out, this means that most of our life’s pursuits are fundamentally misguided.
Based on our considerations so far, we can suggest one additional aspect of craving. Due to the organism identifying itself with its own consciousness (i.e., believing oneself to be consciousness inhabiting the body or the conscious self), it also wants to repeat states of pleasure in a self-conscious, introspectable way, in order to fully indulge in experiencing pleasure. However, as we have suggested, introspectability is a feature of access consciousness that is incompatible with full absorption, and is correlated with tension, thus preventing the occurrence of pleasure. Therefore, through much of our lives, we are engaged in a vicious cycle, trying to re-experience in a self-conscious way the states that we remember as pleasant, but in a way that actually prevents them from being such.
12. The Limits of Introspection for Self-Understanding
On such an account, both phenomenological as well as attitudinal theories of pleasure would be inadequate, as they would fail to explain the reasons for us feeling pleasure.
39 This would also imply that these reasons are not available to our conscious introspection, and we are unable to pinpoint the exact cause or “feel” which makes us experience a particular state as pleasant. Actually, according to our hypothesis, the very act of consciously attending to pleasure makes it impossible to capture its essence, as it lies exactly in the absence of consciousness.
This suggests that, in general, the fundamental causes of our behavior may not be transparent to our introspection. What happens on the level of introspectable consciousness is merely resultant of some deeper processes, which are not introspectable themselves and cannot become the content of our declarative knowledge. All explanations that attribute direct causal efficacy to what is occurring in our consciousness seem to be wrong. It appears that the causes of our feeling of pleasure do not lie in any phenomenal quality that we may introspect or attend to.
We may also consider the possibility that we are absorbed not because of any act originating from our consciousness, e.g., its supposed successful concentration on an object or an activity. We may actually become absorbed because on a deeper, unconscious level, the organism is “satisfied” with its current state—probably because its needs are efficiently taken care of in an automatic, globally unavailable way. Let us note that this is the case with the states of skillful coping, which are examples of an activity performed in a masterful, i.e., non-conscious, automatized way. In such moments, the organism does not need to generate consciousness, which originally developed as a tool for dealing with novel situations for which the automatic systems are insufficient. Therefore, due to a lesser number of moments of consciousness occurring (or none at all), we find ourselves absorbed and not the other way around.
We can therefore agree with
Garfield (
2015, p. 170) when he states that “we are not introspectively authoritative regarding the objects and properties to which we are responding” and that “while it appears that we know ourselves and our inner life intimately from a first-person point of view, … in fact, we are strangers to ourselves, and what we take to be immediate data may be nothing more than illusion”.
13. Saṅkhāras, Conscious Exertion and dukkha
In the first part of the paper, I have hypothesized that the states conceptualized in terms of the five
khandhas and
vedayita may correspond to the notion of ordinary conscious experience, which has a globally available content, i.e., access consciousness. Therefore, the idea that such consciousness is inherently correlated with some form of fundamental discomfort for the organism
40 could be seen as directly paralleling the Nikāya notion that the five
khandhas or
vedayita are
dukkha. Such an understanding would allow us to take this radical claim at face value and see it as an objective, universal truth, and not just a question of subjective assessment dependent on a particular perspective and the emotional makeup of a specific person.
41The Nikāya texts seem to be committed to a radical thesis that every instance of conscious experience (i.e.,
vedayita) is inherently dissatisfactory. But this claim is not as unplausible as it may seem at first. Let us again refer to
Solms’s (
2021, pp. 221–22) statements that “conscious state is undesirable from the viewpoint of a self-organising system” and that “consciousness is undesirable in cognition”.
Solms (
2019, p. 7) suggests that we feel unpleasure when we deviate from homeostasis, and when uncertainty increases. This, of course, is correlated with the necessity of generating consciousness in order for us to amend the situation and return to a state of homeostasis and the certainty characterizing automatic unconscious processes. In the ideal state in which consciousness is not needed, because our needs are taken care of by our automatic and unconscious systems, “we feel nothing”, which
Solms (
2021, p. 222) describes as “[p]eace at last”. In his article (
Solms 2019), he goes as far as to label this state as “Nirvana”, though he uses the term in the general sense adopted in popular culture, without referring to any specific Buddhist understanding of it. However, as Sāriputta’s statement attests, Solms may have in fact unknowingly come very close to at least one of the aspects of
nibbāna in early Buddhist thought.
On such an account, the notion of sukha coinciding with the total absence of vedayita does not appear that self-contradictory anymore. Freed from the strain that is correlated with maintaining consciousness, the organism can enjoy deep comfort on a very basic bodily level. However, such a state cannot be consciously acknowledged, incorporated into memory and declarative knowledge, or expressed verbally.
Is the idea of the correlation between tension and the presence of self-consciousness present in the Nikāyas? A somewhat similar meaning may have been conveyed by the term
saṅkhāra, especially when it was used in a meditative context. By that, I do not claim that this was the main meaning of this term, as from the etymological standpoint, it has no connection with tension whatsoever.
42 Its literal meaning is that of “being made together” and refers to the fabricated and fabricating character of our experience. Many Nikāya texts imply that
saṅkhāras are involved in the generation of conditioned existence, but whether they are directly causally efficacious, or whether their presence is merely a necessary condition of this process, is an open issue.
However, in some passages, this term is used in a similar sense to
cetana and refers to conscious intention or volition.
43 As shown by
Wegner (
2002) and
Metzinger (
2009), the phenomenon of conscious will allows the organism to develop a sense of agency and appropriate one’s own acts. Therefore, it is constitutive of the very basic sense of self-consciousness. Furthermore, in certain texts,
saṅkhāra refers to the exertion, striving and deliberate, forceful mental effort involved in meditative concentration. One occasionally encounters the phrase
sasaṅkhāraniggayhavāritagata (lit: held down by restraint of
saṅkhāras e.g., AN 3.101/i.254), which refers to a lower stage of meditation, at which it has not yet become fully effortless and spontaneous.
Bodhi (
2012, p. 336) translates it as “reined in and checked by forcefully suppressing”. The
Sasaṅkhāra-sutta (AN 4.169/ii.155–156) uses the term
asaṅkhāraparinibbāyī (one who attains full
nibbāna without
saṅkhāras), with reference to a meditator who reaches the final goal through the practice of the four
jhānas.
Bodhi (
2012, p. 534) translates the term
asaṅkhāraparinibbāyī as “[one who] attains
nibbāna without exertion”. The fourth
jhāna is sometimes described as a state in which the meditator has tranquilized his bodily
saṅkhāra (e.g., in AN 10.20/v 31:
passaddhakāyasaṅkhāra). It is noteworthy that according to
Bronkhorst’s (
2012) interpretation, the fourth
jhāna is a state in which bodily tension has become maximally reduced. In the stock account of the mindfulness of breathing (
ānāpānassati), the calming (
passambhayanta) of the bodily
saṅkhāra directly precedes experiencing rapture (
pīti) and then
sukha, which implies a possible connection between the lack of forceful exertion and pleasure.
44 While the historically dominant interpretation sees the four
jhānas as meditative states requiring deliberate mental effort to concentrate on an object, several scholars have suggested that in the Nikāyas, they may have been a type of spontaneous, objectless meditation (e.g.,
Polak 2011;
Bronkhorst 2012;
Arbel 2017;
Wynne 2018).
45 It seems that the Nikāyas imply the existence of a link between the
jhānas,
sukha (which is present in the first three
jhānas), the absence of
dukkha and the calming of
saṅkhāras.
The Nikāyas, therefore, do not explicitly associate saṅkhāras with bodily tension per se, but rather with volitional striving, deliberate mental concentration and forceful exertion. Nevertheless, it seems psychologically plausible that when one strives, deliberately concentrates on something, or exerts oneself, this also involves a significant amount of tension. However, this tension may just be an outward manifestation of a much more fundamental mechanism connected with striving.
Is this specific meaning of
saṅkhāra occurring in the meditative context somehow connected with the other, more basic meanings of this term? We have already noted that from the etymological standpoint, this word means making together or being made up together, and conveys the notion of fabrication. Furthermore, according to the scheme of dependent arising,
saṅkhāra is directly conditioned by ignorance (
avijjā).
Saṅkhāras are also described as
dukkha, both collectively with the other
khandhas, as well as individually. A famous passage of the
Dhammapada states that all
saṅkhāras are
dukkha.
46 It is noteworthy that, in this context,
saṅkhāra refers to experience in its totality, while emphasizing its fabricated aspect.
Are these various meanings somehow connected? In the preceding sections of this article, we have hypothesized that from the evolutionary perspective, consciousness was supposed to be generated to deal with situations that challenge the homeostasis of the organism. It might be the case, as Solms has suggested, that the actual cause of displeasure lies in the disturbance of homeostasis, while consciousness and “tension” arise to deal with this situation and their occurrence is merely correlated with more fundamental displeasure, the causes of which are opaque to introspection. But if, as we have suggested, the organism mistakenly believes itself to be a conscious self, then its goals and actions will reflect this cognitive delusion. Instead of just coming to terms with what it really is, i.e., a conglomerate of self-less processes, it will strive to maintain and prolong what it mistakenly believes to be its existence and will pursue the goals reflecting that misconceived sense of identity. It will attempt to do so by continuously generating consciousness, which corresponds to the Nikāya notion of an uninstructed individual producing (abihinibbatteti) the aggregates (SN 22.100/iii.152). This, of course, disturbs the state of homeostasis even further, and thus intensifies the fundamental sense of displeasure. The organism will strive to amend this by generating even more consciousness since this is the only tool it instinctively uses in such situations, thus intensifying the vicious cycle of dukkha.
What also seems to be implied here is that every instance of ordinary conscious experience is not just a passive awareness of a certain cognitive content, but inherently involves the attitudes of reaching out, striving and trying to become something different from what one really is. The fact that every instance of ordinary consciousness involves the presence of
saṅkhāra can be also taken to mean that it (i.e., consciousness) is artificially made up, in the sense that its presence is not obligatory and it might have just as well not been generated, were it not for the deeply rooted ignorance (
avijjā) regarding one’s own identity. Perhaps it is this non-obligatory character of conditioned experience that is referred to by the enigmatic Nikāya line: “it may not be, and it may not be for me”,
47 which will become the subject of our analysis in the next section.
On such a reading, the generation of ordinary conscious experience involves all the aspects of
saṅkhāra enumerated above: striving and effort, discomfort, fabrication, and ignorance. Since
saṅkhāras are given such a negative evaluation in the Nikāyas, it is not surprising that a relatively frequent stock passage identifies the stilling (
samatha) of all
saṅkhāras with
nibbāna.
48This would imply that nibbāna involves the stilling of all forms of volitional, effortful striving (which is correlated with “tension”) and the ending of ordinary conscious experience conceptualized in terms of the khandhas or vedayita, since saṅkhāras cannot be disconnected from the remaining aggregates. Thus, it would be a state in which “nothing is experienced” and, as a result, it would be the opposite of displeasure.
In light of such an understanding, Sāriputta’s proclamation that the essence of the pleasantness of
nibbāna lies in the fact that nothing is experienced could be considered plausible. Earlier, we suggested that
saññāvedayitanirodha may have been just one of the terms used to denote an apophatic state of the deconstruction of conscious experience resulting in its absence, and that
animitta cetosamādhi may have at some time occupied a similar position as the former state. It is noteworthy that in the famous passage of the
Mahāparinibbāna-sutta (DN 16/ii 100), the aged, ailing Buddha claims that it is only in the state of
animitta cetosamādhi that his body (
kāya) is more at ease (
phāsutara).
49 The specific wording, suggesting that it the body which is at ease, and not, say, that the mind is enraptured (
pītimana), is in perfect harmony with the notion of deep bodily comfort we are considering.
14. The Terror of Having No Consciousness
The idea that conscious experience is the source of our misfortune is very much at odds with our most basic, commonsense intuitions. Particularly revolting, however, is the perspective of the absence of consciousness as a supposedly desired state of the organism, synonymous with the absence of strain and suffering. As we have noted in the earlier part of the paper, consciousness in the common sense of the word involves a phenomenal, qualitative aspect. Phenomenal consciousness is often conceptualized as a unique, distinct inner space filled with irreducible, qualitative phenomena. Supposedly, were the light of consciousness to go out, the inner space in which phenomenal experience takes place would grow dark. From this perspective, the goal of the absence of conscious experience cannot be seen as anything but tantamount to the annihilation of our innermost essence. As
Solms (
2021, p. 224) puts it, “we seem to strive for a kind of zombiedom. The ideal form of cognition is automaticity, and so the sooner we can get rid of consciousness, the better”. But why would anyone sane aspire to zombiedom?
The Nikāya authors may have been aware that the perspective of the cessation of consciousness or the absence of conscious experience may appear terrifying. In the preceding section, we have briefly mentioned the statement of the Buddha in the
Udāna-sutta (SN 22.55/iii 55–58), which is now worth quoting in its entirety. It reads: “It might not be, and it might not be for me; it will not be, [and] it will not be for me”,
50 and is meant to serve as a resolve for severing (
chindati) the fetters (
saṃyojāna) of what is lowly (
orambhāgiya). According to the next part of this text, one realizes this resolve by seeing the aggregates as they really are (i.e., as impermanent, painful and not-self), and by understanding that each of the aggregates “will cease to exist” (
vibhavissati). Therefore, the first line (
no cassaṃ, no ca me siyā) seems to refer to the very possibility of the aggregates ceasing for a practitioner, while the second one (
nābhavissa, na me bhavissatī’ti) represents a firm resolve to personally realize this goal. Since, as we have suggested, the notion of the aggregates is used to convey various aspects of conscious experience, their non-being (
vibhava) would be also tantamount to the absence of consciousness. The author of the text acknowledges that this perspective is a terror (
tāsa) to an unlearned commoner (
assutavant puthujana), while claiming that in fact this state is not frightening (
atasitāya) at all.
Of course, the non-being (vibhava) mentioned in this terse and enigmatic passage may be interpreted in various ways. It may be read as referring to the final cessation of the aggregates coinciding with the post-mortem state of the final nibbāna without any residue remaining (anupādisesa). It may also be understood as referring to the momentariness of the aggregates, which constantly rise and fall. Vibhava may also be read in the sense of the meditative cessation of ordinary consciousness (as the khandhas refer to various aspects of such consciousness) and the resultant transformed state of being, which involves the significant diminishment of occurrences of such consciousness. Regardless of which form of non-being of the aggregates is implied in the text, they must all appear fearsome to an ordinary person who identifies with one’s consciousness and assumes its continuous and constant presence.
Such an attitude is aptly characterized in the passage of the
Mahātaṅhāsaṅkhaya-sutta (MN 38/i.258), in which the fisherman’s son Sāti proclaims his belief that
viññāṇa is that which speaks (
vada), feels (
vedeyya) and experiences (
paṭisaṃvedeti) the results of action. In a similar passage of the
Sabbāsava-sutta (MN 2/i.8), the same characteristics are applied not to
viññāṇa, but to the self (
attā), which in addition to other epithets, is described as continuous/constant (
nicca), stable (
dhuva) and eternal (
sassata). Both accounts complement each other and provide an apt characteristic of the belief that consciousness is the self. For someone holding such a belief, the prospect of the non-being of consciousness must be indeed terrifying. Despite the fact that Solms repeatedly claims that the organism strives for automaticity, the state of as little consciousness as possible, and “zombiedom”, he writes in the same book that the topic of consciousness has great significance, because “you
are your consciousness” (
Solms 2021, p. 8). In this belief, he is certainly not alone, as it is very intuitive and natural, and lies at the heart of various philosophies, including Cartesianism and Sāṃkhya-Yoga.
15. Are We Our Consciousness?
But is this intuitive belief justified? At any moment, there occur within our organism a multitude of parallel activities of registering and processing information. Relatively few of the results of these processes get synthesized into a unified and specifically structured form of data that is then globally broadcast within the whole cognitive system, making it available to various modules in our mind, including those responsible for reality assessment, view formation, action guidance, memory and speech. Are we justified in identifying ourselves with this relatively small, though certainly very important, part of human cognitive architecture, at the expense of its other elements? Can it be said that I am, or we are, this consciousness, and that it is intimately connected to our innermost essence of being? Is the belief “I am consciousness” justified?
From a simple logical standpoint, for this belief or attitude to be correct, its author or the agent maintaining it would actually need to be consciousness. If it is some other faculty or element of our cognitive system that is responsible for the generation of this belief or attitude, then it must be considered mistaken.
Throughout this paper, we have repeatedly stated that consciousness cannot be considered as active and causally efficacious in the direct sense,
51 as it is itself a passive and highly processed end-product of the active but unconscious processes that are the true “cogs and wheels” of our cognition.
That in us, which is responsible for our intelligence, reality assessment, view formation and maintaining certain attitudes, is simply not consciousness.
52 Therefore, the belief “I am consciousness” is not justified, as it simply is not generated and maintained by consciousness, but rather by an element of our cognitive architecture that is unconscious itself. As such, it is a result of its mistaken identification with consciousness, which corresponds to the Nikāya notion of an individual mistakenly considering the aggregates in terms of “I am this” (
esohamasmi).
Likewise, in order for Solms’s commonsense, intuitive statement that “you are your consciousness” to be justified, the element of our cognitive system which registers this statement, analyzes and comprehends it would need to be consciousness. It is not, however. At best, the function of consciousness lies in a particular mode of presenting specifically structured data and making it available throughout the cognitive system. To use a helpful analogy, believing oneself to be consciousness would be tantamount to some AI software running on some hardware producing a statement in response to a question about its identity, to the effect that it is actually a monitor to which it is connected and which displays its output. Were even consciousness able to exist after death in some hypothetical pure form, perhaps being conscious of itself, it would have no significance for us whatsoever. That in us which fears suffering, wants to be liberated and strives for nibbāna is simply not our consciousness. It is our identification with consciousness that is actually the source of our misfortune.
All this of course harmonizes with the Nikāya view that
viññāṇa and other
khandhas are not self (
attā). The historically dominant interpretation of the
anattā teaching emphasizes that although we are ultimately a combination of the five aggregates, there is no stable self among them, and therefore, we are self-less. However, it seems that the original point of the no-self teaching was not just that the
khandhas are not our “self”, but that they are literally not ourselves, i.e., they are not us, or in other words, we are not the
khandhas. The point is therefore not just that
viññāṇa or the other aggregates are self-less, but that we are not our
viññāṇa.
53 16. Conclusions: Psychological Transformation as a Radical Change of Perspective
One of the key aspects of the psychological transformation spoken about in the Nikāya texts may thus be conceptualized in terms of a radical change of perspective. An ordinary person identifies himself with his consciousness, which in Nikāya terms corresponds to viññāṇa, other khandhas and vedayita. From this perspective, the prospect of the aggregates undergoing cessation or non-being (vibhava), or even of their discontinuity, must be terrifying (tāsa), as it seems to be tantamount with the destruction of one’s innermost essence. However, an awakened person knows that his being cannot be reduced to his consciousness, as the latter is merely a small subset of data within a much wider framework of processes.
In this way, the processes which constitute us finally come to terms with what they really are and stop functioning under a mistaken assumption that they are consciousness. From that point of view, the perspective of a cessation or the non-being of the aggregates is no longer terrifying, since it only involves a specifically structured form of cognition. That in us which fears this cessation is actually untouched by such a cessation. The absence of conscious experience in the sense discussed in this paper does not mean that one becomes insentient or stops being intelligent, creative and engaged in the world. It does not follow from the fact that no information at a given moment is introspectable, stored in memory or expressible in speech, that a person in such a state is unconscious in the traditional sense of this word. Throughout his book,
Garfield (
2015) repeatedly emphasizes the limitations of the view of consciousness as the special inner domain that is transparent to introspection and verbal report; “a unitary phenomenon” or “a simple thing or property that one either has or does not” (
Garfield 2015, p. 169). Instead, he invites us to consider the view (which he considers essentially Buddhist) that “consciousness is a many-leveled phenomenon”, of which only the coarsest levels “are on all accounts introspectible by ordinary agents in ordinary states”, while other levels are opaque to introspection and verbal report. For example, one can speak of responsive consciousness as being “responsive to a stimulus, even if that responsiveness is not introspectible and has no phenomenal character” (
Garfield 2015, p. 123).
From this perspective, the absence of
vedayita may be seen as pleasant in the sense of comfort on a deep bodily level, resultant from relaxation and the lack of strain created by the necessity of constantly generating conscious experience. Interestingly, modern cognitive science begins to consider the possibility of “unconscious emotions”.
Berridge and Winkielman (
2003, p. 205) suggest that “there appears to be a subcortical network available to generate core ‘liking’ reactions to sensory pleasures”. They claim that these “‘liking’ reactions may influence a person’s consumption behaviour later, without a person being able to report subjective awareness of the affective reaction at the moment it was caused” (ibid.).
54 Interestingly, they also suggest that this type of core emotion manifests itself in “positive affective facial reactions”.
It is noteworthy that the Nikāyas also allude to the possibility of an elevated meditative state of the mind manifesting itself through facial appearance. For example, when the newly awakened Buddha is met by the Ājīvika ascetic Upaka, the latter greets him by commenting that his features (
indriya) are very clear/calm (
vippasanna), and that his skin complexion (
chavivaṇṇa) is very pure and bright (
parisuddha pariyodāta).
55 What is especially important in the context of our considerations is that clear faculties are also ascribed to a person in the state of
saññāvedayitanirodha, which may indicate that this state was not a comatose one, but was rather characterized by the presence of cognizance and sentience, or to use
Garfield’s (
2015) term, “responsive consciousness”, and perhaps even a form of non-introspectable, deep bodily comfort.
We may expect that the fundamental change in perspective that results from ceasing to identify with one’s consciousness would have a very significant influence on everyday functioning. One can speculate that, for such a person, ordinary access consciousness would return to its original role and be generated only on occasions when the organism would truly need to address a novel challenge. In times of idleness, one would be able to spontaneously return to a state of comfortable absorption and relaxation associated with the absence of introspectable and reportable form of conscious experience. Were we to express this using Nikāya terms, this would be synonymous with the pleasure of not experiencing anything, the casting off (nikkhepana) of the burden (bhāra) of the aggregates, and the ending of dukkha.