Necessary Existence and Necessary Mercy: Ibn ‘Arabī’s Reformulation of Ibn Sīnā’s Ontological Proof
Abstract
:1. Introduction
2. Modalities of Existence in Ibn Sīnā’s Ontology
The first category of existence is thus the type of existence in which something is ‘necessary in itself’. Ibn Sīnā describes this modality of existence as ‘necessarily existent’ because ‘it is completely independent’ of anything else since its very essence guarantees its existence, and it therefore does not need to depend on anything else for its existence. Ibn Sīnā, through careful argumentation, proves that only God can have this sort of existence (Mayer 2001, pp. 18–20).If every being is considered in terms of its essence (dhāt), and not in terms of other things, then its existence is either necessary in itself (yajib lahū al-wujūd fī nafsih), or it is not. If [its existence] is necessary, then it is the truth in itself, and it is necessarily existent (wājib al-wujūd) in itself, and it is completely independent (qayyūm).
If something is not necessarily existent, says Ibn Sīnā, the immediate assumption cannot be that it is impossible. This is because it may yet exist due to a cause (‘illa) that is attached to its essence, even though the essence itself does not ensure its existence. Therefore, if such a condition is found to be attached to the essence, then the entity becomes ‘necessary’ and it exists. In other words, if the cause ensures existence because the essence is not doing it itself, then the thing becomes necessary. However, this is clearly not the type of necessary existence that God has. Instead, it is a necessary existence due to the existence of the cause, or necessary through another, but it is contingent in terms of itself because its existence is contingent on the cause (God). This, then, is the next modality of existence: necessary in terms of another, or contingent in terms of itself.If it is not necessary, then it is [still] not permissible to say that it is impossible in itself after it was deemed to be existent. However, if in terms of its essence a condition is attached to it, like saying that its cause does not exist, [only] then does it become impossible (mumtani‘). Or [conversely], if its cause does exist, then it becomes necessary (wājib).
Every thing that exists is ‘either necessary in itself’, if its essence ensures its existence, as is the case for God, or it is ‘possibly existent it itself’ if it does not. This means that it could exist, but the cause to push it into existence is lacking, not because there is anything intrinsically present in its essence that precludes existence. This is why it is ‘neither necessary nor impossible’ because the essence does not guarantee its existence, so it is not necessary, but neither does it rule out its existence, so it is not impossible. It is significant that Ibn Sīnā says this about all things that exist because even things that do not have the cause to push them into existence, and therefore do not have a sensible existence in the world, still enjoy mental existence because their essence does not preclude existence.If no condition (sharṭ) is attached to its essence—neither of the cause existing nor not existing—then there remains a third option for its essence: possibility (imkān), so in terms of its essence, the thing is neither necessary nor impossible. Therefore, every existent being is either necessary in itself, or possibly existent in itself.
- Necessary existence (wājib al-wujūd). This is when something exists due to its very essence, which means it is not dependent on anything for its existence; it is a modality of existence that is reserved for God.
- Possible existence (imkān). This is when the essence does not guarantee existence, which means that the being is dependent on a cause to push it into existence. If the cause is present, then the being becomes necessary through another, or contingent in itself. All things that exist in the sensible world, like humans, animals, plants, and physical objects, have this modality of existence.
- Impossible (mustaḥīl) existence due to another (Ibn Sīnā 1993). This is the impossibility of existence in the sensible world due to a lack of cause. Things of this type are contingently impossible and have essences that could accept existence if there was a cause. Therefore, they have mental existence, like a centaur, a pegasus, a minotaur, etc.
- Impossible in itself. This is when something does not exist in the physical world or the mental world because its essence itself rules out its existence, such as a square circle. This modality of existence is diametrically opposed to necessary existence because in necessary existence, the essence guarantees a thing’s existence, whereas in this type of existence, the essence precludes a thing’s existence (Ibn Sīnā 1985, pp. 547–49; Black 1997, pp. 425–53; Thom 2008, pp. 361–76; Druart 2012, pp. 51–74).
3. Necessary Existence as the Source of All Other Divine Attributes for Ibn Sīnā
If the essence (dhāt) of the Necessary Existent (wājib al-wujūd) were composed of two things (shay’ayn), or many things that came together, it would be made necessary through them. One of these things, or all of them, would be prior to the Necessary Existent, and it would be a component (muqawwim) of it/them. Thus, the Necessary Existent is indivisible (lā yunqasam), both conceptually (fi’l-ma‘nā) and quantitatively (fi’l-kamm).
It is not just an amalgamation of different parts that constitutes composition, says Ṭūsī, but also the composition of one part, like wood that a bed is made from, which is attached to a certain form, that is, the form of the bed. In this latter case, even though there is only one thing that the bed is made from, i.e., wood, the form of the bed is still dependent on the wood for its existence. Ibn Sīnā, therefore, not only rejects composition that entails multiple parts for the Necessary Existent, but also composition that entails a hylomorphic combination of matter and form (Ibn Sīnā 1993, p. 45).… a primary part (juz’ aṣl), which is prior to the composed thing, such as the wood of a bed, and another part (juz’ ākhar) is attached to it so that the composed thing is made due to its attachment, like the form of the bed.
4. Modalities of Existence in Ibn ‘Arabī’s Ontology
That which has possibility (imkān) does not exist due to its essence (dhāt), for its existence is not more apt for it than its nonexistence because it is simply possible. Thus, if one of these states [existence or nonexistence] becomes more appropriate for it, it is due to the presence or absence of something. Therefore, the existence of every possible thing is due to another.
5. Necessary Mercy as the Source of All Other Divine Attributes for Ibn ‘Arabī
It is only through the divine Name, Al-Raḥmān, which is the Name Ibn ‘Arabī employs to refer to God’s necessary mercy (Izutsu 1983, pp. 116–40), that all the other divine Names were relieved from the constraint of non-existence that they were suffering from. It is for this reason, observes Toshihiko Izutsu, that God’s Name Al-Raḥmān contains all the other divine Names (Izutsu 1983, pp. 116–40). Izutsu writes,The world is manifested through the breath (nafas) of The Compassionate (Al-Raḥmān). God released the divine Names from [the torture] they were going through because they could not manifest themselves.
There is a difference of ranks among the Divine Names, and that a higher Name virtually contains in itself all the Names of lower ranks. If such is the case, then it is natural for us to suppose that there must be in this hierarchy the highest, i.e., the most comprehensive, Name that contains all the rest of the Names. And in fact, according to Ibn ‘Arabī, there actually is such a Name: … Raḥmān.
The divine Name The Merciful being contained within the Name The Compassionate is a clear indication that emotive mercy only becomes operational once there exist entities upon whom the emotive mercy of God can act, which is only made possible by the Name The Compassionate. Izutsu explains this point in the following way:The mercy that is freely given (raḥmat al-imtinān) and the mercy that is compelled [by human actions] (raḥmat al-wujūb). These [two types of mercy proceed from the Names] The Compassionate (Al-Raḥmān) and The Merciful (Al-Raḥīm) [respectively]. Therefore, God gives freely through the Name The Compassionate and He is compelled through the Name The Merciful, but the compulsion is from what He gives freely, therefore, The Merciful is contained within The Compassionate.
Mercy in this sense is nothing but bestowing upon everything existence qua existence. And this is done by the Absolute’s manifesting itself in the creaturely forms. This ontological act has in itself nothing to do with moral judgments. In other words, it does not matter essentially whether a thing as an object of the Mercy be good (khayr) or bad (sharr). Things assume these and other evaluational properties only after having been given existence by the act of the universal Mercy.
The ‘breath’ (nafas) is ascribed to The Compassionate (Al-Raḥmān) because He had mercy on the divine relations (al-nasab al-ilāhiyya) through it by bringing forth the forms of the cosmos (ṣuwar al-‘ālam), which we have said is the manifest aspect (ẓāhir) of God since He is The Manifest (Al-Ẓāhir), and He is their hidden aspect (bāṭin) since He is The Hidden (Al-Bāṭin). He is The First (Al-Awwal) since He existed when they did not, and He is The Last (Al-Ākhir) since He is their essence when they are manifested.
The breath of The Compassionate (al-nafas al-Raḥmān) brought about the existence of the cosmos which enabled the divine Names—what Ibn ‘Arabī describes as ‘the divine relations’ (al-nasab al-ilāhiyya) in the previous passage—to become manifest and relieve them from the ‘torture’ (karb) of non-manifestation. This makes the Name The Compassionate the fundamental Name because all the other divine Names are manifested through this Name.The cosmos (‘ālam) is manifested in the breath of The Compassionate (al-nafas al-Raḥmān) by which God relieved (naffas) the divine Names (al-asmā’ al-ilāhiyya) from what they were experiencing due to not manifesting their traces (āthār).
Zamakhsharī gives two reasons that Al-Raḥmān is linguistically more forceful than Al-Raḥīm: (1) the fa‘lān form is a more exaggerated form than the fa‘īl form, and (2) there is an ‘addition in the construction’ of the fa‘lān form that the fa‘īl form does not have. In other words, Raḥmān has more letters than Raḥīm, as it has five letters as opposed to four for its counterpart. This ‘addition in construction’ leads to an addition in the forcefulness of the term. This is the reason, Zamakhsharī says, that the Name Al-Raḥmān applies to the world and the hereafter, whereas the Name Al-Raḥīm is restricted to this world.Al-Raḥmān is the fa‘lān form of the verb ‘to have mercy’ (raḥima), in the same way as ‘anger’ (ghaḍbān) and ‘intoxicated’ (sakrān) are derived from the verbs ‘to be angry’ (ghaḍiba) and ‘to be intoxicated (sakira) [respectively]. Likewise, Al-Raḥīm is a fa‘īl form of it, just as ‘sick’ (marīḍ) and ‘ill’ (saqīm) are derived from the verbs ‘to be sick’ (mariḍa) and ‘to be ill’ (saqima) [respectively]. However, Al-Raḥmān has exaggeration (mubālagha) that Al-Raḥīm does not. This is why they say, ‘[He is] compassionate in the world and the hereafter, and merciful in the world’. And they also say, ‘the addition in construction leads to an addition in meaning.
6. Conclusions
Author Contributions
Funding
Data Availability Statement
Conflicts of Interest
1 | René Decartes employs a similar ontological proof for God’s existence when he writes, ‘existence can no more be separated from the essence of God than we can separate from the essence of a triangle that the sum of its three angles adds up to two right angles’ (Decartes 2008, p. 66). |
2 | This proof was employed and refined by Thomas Aquinas in his magnum opus, the Summa Theologiae, as one of the five ways of proving the existence of God through a posteriori argumentation (Aquinas 1997, pp. 18–24). Aquinas attributed not only absolute goodness to the entity at the summit of the hierarchy, but also causation. Therefore, the entity that enjoyed the maximal position of any genus was also the cause of all the things in that genus. Based on this, he asserted that ‘there must also be something which is to all beings the cause of their being, goodness, and every other perfection; and this we call God’ (Cahn 2009, p. 61). |
3 | It is noteworthy that Izutsu translates Raḥmān as The Merciful, but we have translated it as The Compassionate and translated the Name that refers to the mercy of God in the more traditional and restricted sense as The Merciful (Al-Raḥīm). This is consistent with more recent works that touch on the difference between the two types of divine mercy, referred to by the divine Names, Al-Raḥmān and Al-Raḥīm. See, for instance, the treatment of the subject by Sachiko Murata (Murata 1992, p. 55). |
References
- Adamson, Peter. 2013a. Interpreting Avicenna. In Interpreting Avicenna: Critical Essays. Edited by Peter Adamson. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. i–ii. [Google Scholar]
- Adamson, Peter. 2013b. From the Necessary Existent to God. In Interpreting Avicenna: Critical Essays. Edited by Peter Adamson. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 170–89. [Google Scholar]
- Adamson, Peter. 2016. Philosophy in the Islamic World: A History of Philosophy without Any Gaps. Oxford: Oxford University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Adamson, Peter, and Michael-Sebastian Noble. 2022. Intuition in the Avicennan tradition. British Journal for the History of Philosophy 31: 657–74. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Addas, Claude. 1993. Quest for the Red Sulphur: The Life of Ibn ‘Arabī. Translated by Peter Kingsley. Cambridge: Islamic Texts Society. [Google Scholar]
- Ahiwānī, Aḥmad, ed. 1948. Kitāb al-Kindī ilā al-mu‘taṣim bi Allāh. Cairo: Dār Iḥyā’ al-Kutub al-‘Arabiyya. [Google Scholar]
- Aquinas, Thomas. 1997. Basic Writings of Saint Thomas Aquinas, Volume 1. Edited by Anton Pegis. Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing Company. [Google Scholar]
- Austin, Ralph. 1980. Ibn al-‘Arabī: The Bezels of Wisdom. Mahwah: Paulist Press. [Google Scholar]
- Ayāzī, Muḥammad ‘Alī. 2009. Al-Mufassirūn: Ḥayātuhum wa manhajuhum. Tehran: Wizārat al-Thaqāfa wa’l-Irshād al-Islāmī. [Google Scholar]
- Bäck, Allen. 1992. Avienna’s Conception of the Modalities. Vivarium 30: 217–55. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Bertolacci, Amos. 2006. The Reception of Aristotle’s Metaphysics in Avicenna’s Kitāb al-Shifā’: A Milestone of Western Metaphysical Thought. Leiden and Boston: Brill. [Google Scholar]
- Bertolacci, Amos. 2017–2018. Avicenna’s Kitāb al-Šifāʾ (Book of the Cure/Healing): The Manuscripts Preserved in Turkey and Their Significance. In The Reception of the Classical Arabic Philosophy in the Ottoman Empire. Edited by Jawdath Jabbour. Beirut: Mélanges de l’Université Saint-Joseph, pp. 265–304. [Google Scholar]
- Black, Deborah. 1997. Avicenna on the Ontological and Epistemic Status of Fictional Beings. Documenti e Studi Sulla Tradizione Filosofica Medievale 8: 425–53. [Google Scholar]
- Cahn, Steven. 2009. Exploring Philosophy of Religion: An Introductory Anthology. New York and Oxford: Oxford University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Chittick, William. 1982. The Five Divine Presences: From al-Qūnawī to al-Qaysarī. The Muslim World 72: 107–28. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Chittick, William. 1992. Faith and Practice of Islam: Three Thirteenth Century Sufi Texts. Albany: State University of New York Press. [Google Scholar]
- Corbin, Henry. 1997. Alone with the Alone: Creative Imagination in the Sūfism of Ibn ʿArabī. Princeton: Princeton University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Dagli, Caner. 2016. Ibn al-‘Arabī and Islamic Intellectual Culture: From Mysticism to Philosophy. London and New York: Routledge. [Google Scholar]
- Decartes, René. 2008. Meditations on First Philosophy. In Meditations on First Philosophy: With Selections from the Objections and Replies. Edited by Michael Moriarty. Oxford: Oxford University Press. [Google Scholar]
- De Cillis, Maria. 2014. Free Will and Predestination in Islamic Thought: Theoretical Compromises in the Works of Avicenna, al-Ghāzālī and Ibn ‘Arabī. London and New York: Routledge. [Google Scholar]
- Druart, Thérèse-Anne. 2012. Avicennan Troubles: The Mysteries of the Heptagonal House and the Phoenix. Topicos 42: 51–74. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
- Ghurāb, Maḥmoud. 1983. Ibn ‘Arabī: Tarjumāt ḥayātih min kalāmih. Damascus: Dār al-Murtaḍā. [Google Scholar]
- Gutas, Dimitri. 1987–1988. Avicenna’s Madhhab with an Appendix on the Question of his Date of Birth. Quaderni di Studi Arabi 5/6: 323–36. [Google Scholar]
- Gutas, Dimitri. 2014. Orientations of Avicenna’s Philosophy: Essays on His Life, Method, Heritage. London: Routledge. [Google Scholar]
- Ḥakīm, Su‘ād, ed. 1981. Al-Mu‘jam al-ṣūfī/Al-Ḥikma fī ḥudūd al-kalimāt. Beirut: Dandara. [Google Scholar]
- Harris, Rabia Terri. 1989. On Majesty and Beauty: The Kitâb Al-Jalâl Wa-l Jamâl of Muhyiddin Ibn ‘Arabi. Journal of the Muhyiddin Ibn ‘Arabi Society 8: 5–32. Available online: http://www.sufi.ir/books/download/english/ibn-arabi-en/jalalwajamal-en.pdf (accessed on 2 February 2023).
- Hirtenstein, Stephen. 1999. The Unlimited Mercifier: The Spiritual Life and Thought of Ibn ‘Arabī. Oxford: Anqa Publishing. [Google Scholar]
- Ibn ‘Arabī, Muḥyī al-Dīn. 1983. Al-Ḥubb wa’l-maḥabba al-ilāhiyya. Damascus. [Google Scholar]
- Ibn ‘Arabī, Muḥyī al-Dīn. 1999. Al-Futūḥāt al-makkiyya. Beirut: Dār al-Kutub al-‘Ilmiyya. [Google Scholar]
- Ibn ‘Arabī, Muḥyī al-Dīn. 2002. Fuṣūṣ al-ḥikam. Beirut: Dār al-Kitāb al-‘Arabī. [Google Scholar]
- Ibn Sīnā, Abū ‘Alī. 1899. Risāla fi’l-‘ishq. Leiden: E. J. Brill. [Google Scholar]
- Ibn Sīnā, Abū ‘Alī. 1985. Kitāb al-najāt min al-gharaq fī baḥr al-ḍalālāt. Tehran: Dāneshgha. [Google Scholar]
- Ibn Sīnā, Abū ‘Alī. 1993. Al-Ishārāt wa’l-tanbīhāt ma‘ sharḥ Naṣīr al-Dīn al-Ṭūsī. Beirut: Mu’assasat al-Ghamān. [Google Scholar]
- Ibn Sīnā, Abū ‘Alī. 1998. Al-Ilāhiyyāt min kitāb al-shifā’. Qom: Maktaba Āyatollāh Mar‘ashī. [Google Scholar]
- Inati, Shams. 2014. Ibn Sina’s Remarks and Admonitions: Physics and Metaphysics. New York: Columbia University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Izutsu, Toshihiko. 1983. Sufism and Taoism. Berkeley and London: University of California Press. [Google Scholar]
- Izutsu, Toshihiko. 1998. God and Man and the Koran. North Stratford: Ayer Company Publishers. [Google Scholar]
- Jāmī, Nūr al-Dīn ‘Abd al-Raḥmān, ed. 2009. Sharḥ al-Jāmī ‘alā fuṣūṣ al-ḥikam. Beirut: Dār al-Kutub al-‘Ilmiyya. [Google Scholar]
- Jandī, Mu’ayyid al-Dīn, ed. 2007. Sharḥ Mu’ayyid al-Dīn al-Jandī ‘alā fuṣūṣ al-ḥikam. Beirut: Dār al-Kutub al-‘Ilmiyya. [Google Scholar]
- Janssens, Jules. 2018. Ibn Sina and His Influence on the Arabic and Latin World. London: Routledge. [Google Scholar]
- Knysh, Alexander. 1999. Ibn ʿArabī in the Later Islamic Tradition. Albany: State University of New York Press. [Google Scholar]
- Lizzini, Olga. 2003. Wujūd-Mawjūd/Existence-Existent in Avicenna: A Key Ontological Notion of Arabic Philosophy. Quaestio 3: 11–38. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Mayer, Toby. 2001. Avicenna’s Burhān al-Ṣiddīqīn. Journal of Islamic Studies 12: 18–39. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- McGinnis, Jon. 2010. Avicenna. Oxford: Oxford University Press. [Google Scholar]
- McGinnis, Jon. 2022. Simple is as simple does: Platinga and Ghazālī on divine simplicity. Religious Studies 58: 97–109. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Menn, Stephen. 1992. Aristotle and Plato on God as Nous and as the Good. The Review of Metaphysics 45: 543–73. [Google Scholar]
- Morris, James. 1987. Ibn ‘Arabī and his Interpreters’, part II-B. Journal of the American Oriental Society 107: 101–19. Available online: www.ibnarabisociety.org.uk/articlespdf/hi_interpreters3.pdf (accessed on 7 February 2023). [CrossRef]
- Morrissey, Fitzroy. 2020. The Origins of the Fuṣūṣ: Early Explanations of Ibn ‘Arabī’s “Vision” of the Prophet. The Maghreb Review 45: 763–94. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Murata, Sachiko. 1992. The Tao of Islam: A Sourcebook on Gender Relationships in Islamic Thought. Albany: State University of New York Press. [Google Scholar]
- Nettler, Ronald. 1978. Ibn ʿArabī’s Conception of Allah’s Mercy. Israel Oriental Studies 7: 219–29. [Google Scholar]
- Nettler, Ronald. 2003. Sufi Metaphysics and Qur’ānic Prophets. Cambridge: The Islamic Texts Society. [Google Scholar]
- Qāshānī, ‘Abd al-Razzāq. 1892. Sharḥ ‘Abd al-Razzāq al-Qāshānī ‘alā Fuṣūṣ al-ḥikam. Edited by Bālī Khalīfa al-Ṣūfiyāwī. Cairo: Al-Maṭbaʿa al-Ẓāhira. [Google Scholar]
- Qayṣarī, Dāwūd, ed. 1955. Sharḥ Fuṣūṣ al-ḥikam. Tehran: Sharika Intishārāt ‘Ilmi wa Farhangī. [Google Scholar]
- Qūnawī, ṣadr al-Dīn, ed. 2013. Al-Fukūk fī asrār Mustanadāt Ḥikam al-Fuṣūṣ. Beirut: Kitāb Nāshirūn. [Google Scholar]
- Rizvi, Sajjad. 2006. The Existential Breath of al-raḥmān and the Munificent Grace of al-raḥīm: The Tafsīr Sūrat al-Fātiḥa of Jāmī and the School of Ibn ʿArabī. Journal of Qur’anic Studies 8: 58–87. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Rustom, Mohammed. 2005. Dāwūd al-Qayṣarī: Notes on His Life, Influence and Reflections on the Muḥammadan Reality. Journal of the Muhyiddin Ibn ‘Arabi Society 38: 51–64. [Google Scholar]
- Sands, Kristin Zahra. 2006. Ṣūfī Commentaries of the Qur’an in Classical Islam. Abingdon: Routledge. [Google Scholar]
- Sells, Michael. 1988. ‘Ibn ʿArabī’s Polished Mirror: Perspective Shift and Meaning Event’. Studia Islamica 67: 121–49. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Stade, Robert. 1970. Ninety-Nine Names of God in Islam. Ibadan: Daystar Press. [Google Scholar]
- Stern, Gustav. 1931. Meaning and Change of Meaning: With Special Reference to the English Language. Bloomington: Indiana University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Thom, Paul. 2008. Logic and metaphysics in Avicenna’s modal syllogistic. In The Unity of Science in the Arabic Tradition: Science, Logic, Epistemology and their Interactions. Edited by Shahid Rahman, Tony Street and Hassan Tahiri. New York: Springer, pp. 361–76. [Google Scholar]
- Todd, Richard. 2014. The Sufi Doctrine of Man: Ṣadr al-Dīn al-Qūnawī’s Metaphysical Anthropology. Leiden: Brill. [Google Scholar]
- Wippel, John. 2000. The Metaphysical Thought of Thomas Aquinas: From Finite Being to Uncreated Being. Washington, DC: The Catholic University of America Press. [Google Scholar]
- Zamakhsharī, Abu’l-Qāsim, ed. 1987. Al-Kashshāf ‘an ḥaqā’iq Ghawāmiḍ al-Tanzīl. Beirut: Dār al-Kitāb al-‘Arabī. [Google Scholar]
Disclaimer/Publisher’s Note: The statements, opinions and data contained in all publications are solely those of the individual author(s) and contributor(s) and not of MDPI and/or the editor(s). MDPI and/or the editor(s) disclaim responsibility for any injury to people or property resulting from any ideas, methods, instructions or products referred to in the content. |
© 2023 by the authors. Licensee MDPI, Basel, Switzerland. This article is an open access article distributed under the terms and conditions of the Creative Commons Attribution (CC BY) license (https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/).
Share and Cite
Lala, I.; Alwazzan, R. Necessary Existence and Necessary Mercy: Ibn ‘Arabī’s Reformulation of Ibn Sīnā’s Ontological Proof. Religions 2023, 14, 1016. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel14081016
Lala I, Alwazzan R. Necessary Existence and Necessary Mercy: Ibn ‘Arabī’s Reformulation of Ibn Sīnā’s Ontological Proof. Religions. 2023; 14(8):1016. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel14081016
Chicago/Turabian StyleLala, Ismail, and Reham Alwazzan. 2023. "Necessary Existence and Necessary Mercy: Ibn ‘Arabī’s Reformulation of Ibn Sīnā’s Ontological Proof" Religions 14, no. 8: 1016. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel14081016
APA StyleLala, I., & Alwazzan, R. (2023). Necessary Existence and Necessary Mercy: Ibn ‘Arabī’s Reformulation of Ibn Sīnā’s Ontological Proof. Religions, 14(8), 1016. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel14081016