A Contemporary Aristotelian–Thomistic Perspective on the Evolutionary View of Reality and Theistic Evolution
Abstract
:1. Introduction
2. Biological Species
2.1. Hylomorphically–Grounded Essentialist Definition of Species
- (1)
- Biological species is a universal category expressed in and abstracted from concrete living beings that are determined by a particular type of essence;
- (2)
- The latter is constituted by a specific kind of substantial form (SF) which—as a metaphysical principle of actuality—actualizes its correlative metaphysical principle of pure potentiality; that is, primary matter (PM);
- (3)
- Causing thus an organism to be what it is, SF grounds a range of essential and accidental, intrinsic and extrinsic dispositions and properties, characteristic of a given type of living creature;
- (4)
- A provisional list of these dispositions and properties includes particularized kind–specific morphological and physiological developmental programs and a variety of genotypic and phenotypic traits that find their distinctive expression in the historical relationships of organisms that belong to a given species.
2.2. The Revival of Biological Essentialism
2.3. Dynamic Aspect of Hylomorphically–Grounded Biological Essentialism
2.4. Metaphysical and Biological Species Concepts
3. Hylomorphism and Species Transformism
3.1. Disposition of Matter and Levels of Potentiality
3.2. Matter as Striving for Perfection—Scala Naturae
[E]verything capable of being generated has a definite matter from which it comes to be, because there must be a proportion between form and matter. For even though first matter is in potentiality to all forms, it nevertheless receives them in a certain order. For first of all it is in potency to the forms of the elements, and through the intermediary of these, insofar as they are mixed in different proportions, it is in potency to different forms. Hence, not everything can come to be directly from everything else unless perhaps by being resolved into first matter.(In Meta. XII, lect. 2 [§ 2438])
From the fact that matter is known to have a certain substantial mode of existing, matter can be understood to receive accidents by which it is disposed to a higher perfection, so far as it is fittingly disposed to receive that higher perfection.(Q. de an. 9, co.)14
3.3. Metaphysics of Speciation
3.4. Population and Individualistic/Typological Approach
Genes are not ‘disembodied members of populations’ but constituents of organisms, and the fate of the genes is tied to the fate of the organisms whose genes they are. Moreover, the process of adaptive evolution is precisely the process whereby populations come to comprise well–adapted organisms. Knowledge of whether a population has evolved requires knowledge of whether adaptive traits have arisen within individual organisms. For evolution to occur, harmful mutations must be sufficiently rare or ineffectual within individuals, and fitness must be fairly constant across genetically similar individuals. Population thinking is simply not possible without individualistic thinking.
Recent evolutionary developmental biology shows that one cannot understand how natural selection operating over a population of genes can lead to increased and diversified adaptation of organisms unless one understands the role of individual natures (essences) in the process of evolution.
3.5. Levels of Similarity of Adjacent Species
Sometimes, however, the effect has not this aptitude to receive the impression of its cause, in the same way as it exists in the agent: as may be seen clearly in all agents which do not produce an effect of the same species as themselves: thus the heavenly bodies cause the generation of inferior bodies which differ from them in species.19
3.6. The Principle of Proportionate Causation and Evolution
“[T]he begetter is of the same kind as the begotten” (Meta. VII, 8 [1033b 30]). “[W]hatever perfection exists in an effect must be found in the effective cause” (ST I, 4, 2, co.). “[N]o effect exceeds its cause” (ST II–II, 32, 4, obj. 1). “[N]othing acts beyond its species” (Super II Sent. 18, 2, 3). “[T]he order of causes necessarily corresponds to the order of effects, since effects are commensurate with their causes” (SCG II, 15, no. 4). “[E]very agent acts according as it is in act” (SCG II, 6, no. 4). “No effect can be more powerful than its agent cause”(Super II Sent. 18, 2, 3, obj. 3).20
… the only general metaphysical principle that St. Thomas invokes in order to argue for the need for the instrumental contribution of a univocal generator is not the principle of proportionate causality, but instead the principle that a remote created universal cause needs the instrumental contribution of mediating instruments to produce more powerful effects. This principle seems reconcilable with evolution as well—although to articulate this reconciliation would require much further work.
3.7. Teleology and Chance in Evolution
It necessarily follows that chance alone is at the source of every innovation, and of all creation in the biosphere. Pure chance, absolutely free but blind, at the very root of the stupendous edifice of evolution: this central concept of modern biology is no longer one among many other possible or even conceivable hypotheses. It is today the sole conceivable hypothesis, the only one that squares with observed and tested fact. And nothing warrants the supposition—or the hope—that on this score our position is ever likely to be revised.
4. Thomistic School of Theology and Evolution
4.1. Aquinas’s Account of Creation
4.2. Aquinas’s Use of Augustine’s Notion of Rationes Seminales
4.3. From Gradualism to Evolutionism
4.4. Does God Create through Evolution?
4.5. Concurrence of Divine and Created Causes in Evolutionary Transitions
- God is always (and in each case) the ultimate primary cause of (ee3) and (ea2) and the ultimate principal cause of (ee1) and (ee2), as well as of (ea1) of all created entities.
- Creatures can act as secondary causes (dependent on the primary causation of God) of (ee1) and (ee2), as well as (ea1)—with respect to contingent entities other than themselves.55
- Creatures can also act as instrumental causes (dependent on the principal causation of God) of (ee3), as well as (ea2)—with respect to contingent entities other than themselves.
- Proper causes of their offspring’s coming into being (in a most basic and pre–philosophical causal explanation).
- Secondary causes of (ea1), i.e., the instantiation of their offspring’s essence (defined as the eduction of the appropriate SF from the potentiality of PM) and of its (ee1), i.e., coming into existence, as well as its (ee2), i.e., continuing in existence (permanence in time)—the latter by removing causes of corruption and engaging in nurturing their offspring, which is necessary for its survival and growth.
- Instrumental causes of (ea2), i.e., their offspring’s essence (essentia) and (ee3), i.e., its existence (esse) taken as such (per se).
- The proper cause of its origin in the immanent order of causation (in a most basic and pre–philosophical causal explanation), i.e., the agency of the parental organisms belonging to the species S1, within the complex dynamic system of immanent causes, involved in the causally polygenic evolutionary change leading to the coming–to–be of the first exemplar of the species S2.
- The secondary cause of (ea1), understood as the eduction of its proper SF from the potentiality of PM, i.e., the agency of the parental organisms, within the complex system of immanent causal factors, involved in the polygenic process of the instantiation of the first exemplar of the SF of the new species S2 in a given “portion” of a designated mater, which is its principle of individuation.
- The instrumental cause of (ea2), i.e., its essence (essentia), taken as such, defined in terms of the agency of the parental organisms, within the complex system of immanent causes, which is accompanied by the instantiation of the first exemplar of the new species S2 (the actualization of PM by a new kind of SF of the species S2).
- The secondary cause of its (ee1), i.e., coming into existence (esse), defined in terms of the agency of efficient causes (parental organisms acting within the evolutionary matrix of causes), which is accompanied or followed by the coming into existence (esse) of their offspring, which happens to be the first exemplar of the new species S2. If parental organisms engage in nurturing their offspring, which is necessary for its survival and growth, they are also considered secondary causes of (ee2), i.e., their offspring’s continuing existence (permanence in time).
- The instrumental cause of (ee3), i.e., its existence (esse), taken as such, defined in terms of the agency of parental organisms (within the evolutionary matrix of causes), which brings or is followed by an instantiation of the first exemplar of the new species S2.
4.6. Theological Anthropogenesis and Evolution
Scripture … says that “God made man from the dust of the earth, and breathed into his nostrils the breath of life”. This is a plain and direct statement that man’s body … was evolved from preexisting material (symbolized by the term “dust of the earth”), and was therefore [formed] by the operation of secondary laws.
The soul of every individual man is … created … produced by a direct or supernatural act, and, of course, … by such an act the soul of the first man was similarly created.
4.7. Thomistic Version of Theistic Evolution
- TVTE pays attention to natural science and accepts the biological notion of evolution. It carefully follows the research and critical debate concerning the mechanisms of speciation. It also actively engages in the analysis of philosophical aspects and interpretations of the past and current versions of evolutionary theory.
- TVTE is grounded in Aristotle’s and Aquinas’s hylomorphism and ontology of living beings, emphasizing their unity, in reference to the principles of their stability and changeability (see Section 2.1). It also assumes and defends biological essentialism (see Section 2.2).
- TVTE is also grounded in the metaphysical model of evolutionary transitions as delineated in Section 3, with a special emphasis on the categories of the disposition of matter, levels of potentiality, and the notion of matter understood as directed toward perfection. Another crucial aspect of the same model is its application of the notion of the interplay of teleology and chance offered in classical metaphysics (see Section 3.7). (This foundation safeguards TVTE from the pitfalls of materialist reductionism and causal monism.)
- Theologically speaking, TVTE emphasizes, after Aquinas, that the initial act of creation is restricted to the creatio ex nihilo of the most basic physical matter of the elements and keeping the ever–transforming and changing universe in existence (conservatio rerum). Hence, it clearly distinguishes between creation and the processes of the emergence of new things from the already existing secondary matter of the universe.
- TVTE interprets the continual and ongoing processes of micro– and macro–evolution as belonging to the work of adornment (opus ornatus), whose subsequent stages are not limited to the closed and past time interval but extend through the entire history of the universe.
- TVTE acknowledges that the perfection of the universe can grow daily not only with regard to the number of individuals but also with regard to the number of species.
- TVTE assumes that (with the exception of humans) SFs of the first exemplars of new species are educed from the potentiality of PM. It also states that the similarity between parents and their offspring (including offspring belonging to a new species) should not be understood as an absolute, strict, and nonexceptional qualitative identity of their SFs. Rather, it can be defined in terms of a proportional proximity to the SF of the offspring, when compared with the SFs of its parents (see Section 3.5).
- TVTE holds that the origin of species occurs through “production” (productio) from pre–existing matter with ancestry in a process of universal common descent, in which God’s agency concurs with the secondary and instrumental causation of creatures. This proposal is grounded in the reinterpreted version of Augustine’s concept of rationes seminales, which Aquinas introduces in his theology of creation (see Section 4.2, Section 4.3, Section 4.4 and Section 4.5).
- TVTE does not require direct divine intervention in the origin of a new plant or animal species. The exception is the human species, where the first human soul(s) was/were created ex nihilo at the final step of the speciation process, and all subsequent human souls are created ex nihilo at the moment of the conception of each new human being. The first human soul(s) actualized PM properly disposed within evolutionary processes.
- (TVTE remains open–minded in the debate on mono– versus polygenism.)61
5. Conclusions
- The question concerning the amount of pain, suffering, and death in evolutionary processes.66
- The question about mono– and polygenetic views of human speciation, with reference to the notion of original sin and its transmission.67
- The question concerning the confrontation of the classical understanding of the original state of human nature (original justice/righteousness), including the notion of praeternatural gifts (especially impassibility and physical immortality), with the evolutionary view of the origin of the human species.68
- The notion of the human species as the crown and pinnacle of biological evolution in confrontation with the notion of the continuing human evolution, trans– and posthumanism, and the possibility of an emergence of new (higher) intelligent species on Earth or somewhere else in the cosmos.69
Funding
Data Availability Statement
Conflicts of Interest
1 | Among more significant contributors we should mention Mortimer J. Adler, Benedict Ashley, Nicanor Pier Giorgio Austriaco, F. F. Centore, William E. Carroll, Michael Chaberek, John N. Deely, Charles DeKoninck, Joseph Donceel, Ryan Fáinche, Réginald Garrigou–Lagrange, Étienne Gilson, James R. Hofmann, Édouard Hugon, Marie–Dalmace Leroy, Norbert Luyten, Jacques Maritain, Ernan McMullin, Désiré–Joseph Mercier, Antonio Moreno, Raymond J. Nogar, Fran O’Rourke, Edward T. Oakes, R. P. Phillips, Gerard M. Verschuuren, and William Wallace. |
2 | I am thinking here in particular about comments made by Ivan Colagè and Simon Maria Kopf, in their critical response to the book at the promotional event organized in December of 2023 at the Pontifical University of Saint Thomas Aquinas in Rome. I am also grateful for the critical remarks and suggestions shared by both anonymous reviewers of this article. They helped me clarify some of its fundamental assertions. |
3 | The nominalist position in the debate on biological species inspires the definition of units of speciation at the level of populations (less often at the level of individual organisms). In other words, what explains the abundance of living forms is genetic variation and the distribution of traits among organisms within populations. As David Oderberg notes (in reference to Margaret Morrison’s reflection on the importance of the contribution of R. A. Fisher to the development of population genetics [Morrison 2000, pp. 214–24]), “The idea is that individual organisms, and hence their putative essences, play no explanatory role in evolutionary theory. The aim of that theory is to explain biological diversity, but to do this all one needs is an account of the genetic variation in populations, each member of which is unique and not a representative of some essential type. This variation can be encapsulated by general statistical laws that do not refer to the causal powers of individual organisms, so one does not need ‘specific knowledge of the individuals themselves’ in order to understand evolutionary mechanisms”. (Oderberg 2007, p. 207). |
4 | “The species problem is one of the oldest controversies in natural history” (O’Hara 1993, p. 231). It is “one of the thorniest issues in theoretical biology” (Kitcher 2003, p. xii). What indicates the scale of the controversy is certainly the fact that we have around two dozen species concepts in the philosophy of biology and, as claims Ereshefsky, “at least seven well–accepted ones” (Ereshefsky 1998, p. 103). See also (Richards 2008, pp. 161–88) (he defines at least 16 species concepts). |
5 | Genetic dispositions–based essentialism was proposed by Kitts and Kitts (1979) and Rieppel (2010). Dispositional–based essentialism is favored by Wallace (2002) and Austin (2017). Related to it, a developmental programs–based version of biological essentialism was developed by Austin (2017) and Boulter (2012). The mixed approach, defining essences in reference to both genetic and/or phenetic properties and relational/historical aspects of organisms, was developed by Devitt (2023) and Elder (2008). Origin essentialism, introduced by Saul Kripke (1980), is advocated by Elliott Sober (2024, pp. 178–79). I discuss contemporary versions of essentialism in greater length in Tabaczek (2024, pp. 74–81). |
6 | Note that the reference to efficient causes in the causal description of an organism introduces a historical aspect to the hylomorphic variant/aspect of biological essentialism. Yet, as notes Oderberg, “It does not follow from the fact that a substance or species has a certain historical origin that its essence is to have that origin, even if it has its origin necessarily” (Oderberg 2007, p. 101). |
7 | On this interpretation of essentialism, variation, being a result of the action of “interfering forces”, takes an organism away from its “natural stage”, making it thus “the result of imperfect manifestations of the idea implicit in each species” (Mayr 1963, p. 11). Paul Griffiths says variation makes an organism belonging to an intrinsically defined species a “deviation” from an “ideal” (Griffiths 2001, pp. 78–79). Sober finds this view to contrast Darwin’s, for whom “[i]ndividual differences are not the effects of interfering forces confounding the expression of a prototype; rather they are the causes of events that are absolutely central to the history of evolution”. He adds that “the Natural State Model presupposes that there is some phenotype which is the natural one which is independent of a choice of environment” (Sober 1980, pp. 371, 374). Jody Hey brings this line of criticism to its logical conclusion and says: “that variation among organisms is the crucial stuff of changing life and of life’s progress” is thought to be “devastating to essentialism” (Hey 2001, p. 62). |
8 | An expert in Aristotle’s biology, James Lennox, says that “Aristotle’s essentialism is not typological, nor is it in any way ‘anti–evolutionary’. Whatever it is Darwin was up against, it was not Aristotelian essentialism” (Lennox 2001, p. 162). I claim that the typological approach remains plausible when understood in line of the definition of natural kinds provided in the main text (Section 2.1). |
9 | In Tabaczek (2024, pp. 57–91, 170–74) I offer an extended analysis of all major species concepts and distinguish between the categories of metaphysical and biological species, natural kinds, and biblical kinds. |
10 | Commenting on this topic in the Metaphysics, Aristotle states what follows: “Regarding material substance we must not forget that even if all things come from the same first cause or have the same things for their first causes, and if the same matter serves as starting–point for their generation, yet there is a matter proper [i.e., properly disposed] to each, e.g., for phlegm the sweet or the fat, and for bile the bitter, or something else; though perhaps these come from the same original matter” (Meta. VIII, 4 [1044a 15–20]). Aquinas, in turn, comments on this passage thus: “From the things which are said here then it is evident that there is one first matter for all generable and corruptible things, but different proper [i.e., properly disposed] matters for different things” (In Meta. VIII, lect. 4 [§ 1730]). |
11 | One could object that PM cannot be disposed as this would lead to it losing its metaphysical status of pure potentiality. Hence, what can be disposed is only secondary (physical) matter. Still, I claim that the fact that the scope of possible actualizations of PM—when informed by a given SF and AFs—is limited allows us to say (at least analogically) that it is disposed. Especially when we emphasize that it is not disposed as such (per se) but as informed (actualized) by the given SF and a particular set of AFs. Another possible response to this question was proposed by Simon Maria Kopf, who suggests that the “proximate” potentiality of prime matter is nothing other than the disposition of “designated matter”, which through the substance’s AFs is not only extended under determinate dimensions but might also be argued to have determinate dispositions, which can be changed through new AFs. |
12 | Such a notion of potency is, for example, characteristic of the thought of Augustine. In his mature commentary on Genesis, he implements the Stoic notion of rationes seminales (λόγοι σπερματικοὶ, “seed–principles”) and states that “[God] created all [creatures] together … whose visible forms He produces through the ages, working even until now” (De Gen. ad litt. V, 20). He adds that “there is in nature some hidden force by which latent forms are brought into view” (De Gen. ad litt. VI, 16). While providing an important point of reference for the reflection on the philosophical and theological repercussions of the theory of evolution, Augustine’s notion of the actualization of the limited and fixed number of the hidden “latent forms” must be classified as introducing gradualism within a pre–established harmony of the universe rather than anticipating the modern evolutionary theory (the latter was suggested, among others, by St. George Jackson Mivart, John Augustine Zahm, and Henry de Dorlodot—see Tabaczek [2024, pp. 135–37]). To give justice to Augustine, we should acknowledge that apart from the category of rationes seminales, he introduces the notion of unformed matter (materia informis), which he sees as neither actualized matter nor nothingness: “Something midway between form and nothingness” (quiddam inter formam et nihil)” (Conf. XII, 6, 6). Important for the interpretation of the “formless void” in Genesis 1 as a non–temporal absolute potentiality at the initial founding of the world, materia informis becomes for Augustine a principle of mutability: “The mutability of mutable things itself gives them their potential to receive all those forms into which mutable things can be changed. And what is this mutability? … I would call it ‘a nothing–something’ [nihil aliquid] or ‘an–is–that–is–not’ [est non est] if such expressions were allowed” (Conf. XII, 6, 6). However, while this description of materia informis might be seen as resembling Aristotle’s materia prima, we must confront it with a set of passages in which Augustine seems to suggest it is a kind of basic stuff (i.e., secondary matter). In his unfinished commentary on Genesis, he states materia informis is “a kind of mixed–up material [materies erat confuse quaedam] out of which the world … would be fashioned, by the sorting out of its elements and the bestowal on them of shape and form”. (De Gen. ad litt. imp. lib. IV, 11). In Conf. XII, 7 we read it was created ex nihilo in two kinds: spiritual and bodily: “Two realities [duo quaedam], one near to yourself, the other bordering on nothingness”. Similar is his view shared in De Gen. ad litt., where he also speculates about the third, spiritual kind of materia informis—one that gave origin to the first human soul(s). See (Nordlander 2019). |
13 | On another occasion, Aristotle presents us with a similar reflection concerning transitions between various forms of life: “[N]ature passes from lifeless objects to animals in such unbroken sequence, interposing between them beings which live and yet are not animals, that scarcely any difference seems to exist between two neighbouring groups owing to their close proximity” (De part. an. IV, 5 [681a 12–15]). |
14 | See also In De an. II, lect. 7, (§ 315); Q. de pot. 5, 1, co. and ad 5; SCG III, 22, no. 7. |
15 | Consequently, it should be stated that Aquinas’s belief in the “tendency” of properly disposed matter to be actualized (informed)—in a line of consecutive accidental and substantial changes—by various new types of AFs and SFs (including SFs of increasingly higher natural kinds) does not concern only his views on human embryology (see SCG III, 22, no. 7) but can be regarded as a generally binding principle in his metaphysical system. |
16 | Similar metaphysical analysis may be developed with reference to organisms reproducing asexually. |
17 | Some thinkers argue that biological essentialism is not sustainable as it requires clear, nonbridgeable boundaries between species, which—in turn—suggests evolution is saltational and not incremental. I present this argument and respond to it in Tabaczek (2024, pp. 84, 86–88). |
18 | |
19 | Following Aristotle, Aquinas was convinced that the energy of the sun was necessary for substantial changes to occur on Earth. In reference to the example of celestial bodies causing the generation of lower bodies, one can argue that for Aquinas, effects that do not resemble their causes are always ranked ontologically “lower” than their causes, while speciation, as defined above, entails the possibility of originating an organism that is ontologically “higher”; that is, one that has new and metaphysically “more perfect” dispositions in respect to its direct efficient cause. This issue will be addressed in the following section of this article. |
20 | See also Q. de pot. 3, 8, obj. 13; ST I–II, 112, 1; Comp. theo. 1, 93. At the advent of modernity, Descartes upheld this principle (often called a causal adequacy principle). In his “Third Meditation”, he states that “there must be at least as much reality in the efficient and total cause as in the effect of that cause” (Descartes 1984, p. 28). |
21 | The notion of the increased complexity and perfection of things mentioned here is not conceived teleologically. Rather, it simply acknowledges the fact that evolution produces things that can be classified at various levels of structural complexity and are characterized by different sets of dispositional properties. Moreover, speaking about perfection, we should not forget about “a fundamental difference between the metaphysical order of various degrees of perfection of different ‘essences,’ and the biological order of different forms of life which is based on a historical and phenomenological analysis. Metaphysical categories of ‘higher’ and ‘lower’ should not be equated with biological concepts describing organisms as ‘more complex’ and ‘better adapted.’ In other words, ‘more complex’ and ‘better adapted’ do not presuppose a higher perfection of ‘essence.’ Insects, for instance, are certainly not the highest organisms in terms of the metaphysical perfection of their ‘essence,’ but they can be regarded as a culmination of an evolutionary line in terms of adaptation to their environmental niche. That is why, when biology speaks of different species, it does not mean to speak of different ‘essences,’ as it is not interested in levels of ontological perfection” (Tabaczek 2014, p. 60). |
22 | Michael Chaberek claims that an evolutionary framework is incompatible with the thought of Aristotle and Aquinas. In his argumentation, he points to the principles that “no being can convey more act than it possesses”, that “no effect can exceed the power of its cause”, and that “the perfection of the cause cannot be lesser than the perfection of the effect” as incompatible with the evolutionary emergence of novel genera of living things. See Chaberek (2017, p. 48) and Chaberek (2019, p. 56). |
23 | The relevance of the first strategy described here (important for the proper understanding of the medieval formulation and interpretation(s) of PPC) might be limited to a certain form of Thomism. The second strategy is relevant in the context of the contemporary philosophical debate on the causal aspects of evolutionary transitions. Apart from the two strategies delineated in the main text, we may list other approaches to this problem, based on (1) a metaphysical differentiation of types of perfection; (2) the virtual and eminent presence of perfections; and (3) the conservation of the overall perfection of the universe. I discuss them in Tabaczek (2024, pp. 42–55). Another meaningful response to the challenge of PPC and evolution was suggested by Simon Maria Kopf, in reference to the notion of God’s governing primary causation in, with, and through secondary causation executing his providence. If God’s involvement in the agency of secondary causes includes creation, conservation, application, and instrumental causation, a divine application and especially an instrumental use of creaturely powers may explain an increase in the actuality or perfection of the first exemplar(s) of a given new species. I believe this suggestion goes hand in hand with my analysis of yet another possible response to the problem of PPC and evolution offered by Feser, i.e., the eminent presence of higher perfections in causes (see Feser 2014, p. 155): “The idea goes back to the medieval concept of a passive obediential capacity (potentia obedientialis) whereby the nature of a given cause can be ‘elevated’ such that it is capable to give what by nature it does not have. … Hence, the ‘elevation’ of such agents is caused by the supernatural concursus of the First Cause, which enables them to bring about effects of an entirely higher order than those within the ambit of their natural powers” (Tabaczek 2023a, pp. 51–52). |
24 | Paying attention to the same problem of the popular interpretation of the PPC, Peter Coffey states: “The mediaeval scholastics embodied this truth in the formula: Nemo dat quod non habet—a formula which we must not interpret in the more restricted and literal sense of the words giving and having, lest we be met with the obvious objection that it is by no means necessary for a boy to have a black eye himself in order to give one to his neighbour!” (Coffey 1970, p. 60). |
25 | The idea of causal polygeny of events was introduced in the analytic philosophy of biology by John Dupré (1993, pp. 123–24), who, in turn, takes it from genetics, which acknowledges that many genes typically contribute to the production of one trait. Following Dupré, George Molnar (2003, p. 195) notes not only that events are polygenic, but also that causal powers, conversely, are pleiotropic and flexible and can make a contribution to many different effects. |
26 | This view was previously articulated by Luyten (1951), Ashley (1972), and Elders (1984). Interestingly, it finds grounding in Aquinas who, following Avicenna, distinguishes four types of efficient causes, including preparing and perfecting causes (see In Meta. V, lect. 2 [§ 766–69]; In Phys. II, lect. 5 [§ 766–69]). I claim that the former—preparing matter for form (In Meta. V, lect. 2 [§ 767])—can be extended to numerous causal agents contributing to the same complex evolutionary transition, while the latter—causing the ultimate perfection of a thing (In Meta. V, lect. 2 [§ 766])—might be referred to the cause that brings about (directly) the final step of an evolutionary transformation. See also Frost (2022, pp. 192–98). Both Ivan Colagè and Simon Maria Kopf suggest that the contribution of various factors emphasized in the extended evolutionary synthesis requires a closer examination on my side. I find their comment justified and will take it into account in my further reflection on the topic of evolution. |
27 | My extended analysis of teleology and chance in evolution can be found in Tabaczek (2024, pp. 92–126). There I address a number of important issues, including (1) an observation made by Aristotle in Physics and commented on by Aquinas in In Phys., which might be interpreted as a preliminary formulation of the principle of natural selection; (2) a recent argument in the philosophy of biology portraying Darwin as reinventing (Aristotelian) teleology; (3) the debate on teleology among the founding fathers of the twentieth–century evolutionary synthesis; (4) the current status of teleology in philosophy of biology, and (5) the question of whether natural selection should be understood as teleological. |
28 | See Phys. II, 3 (194b 29–195a 2) and Meta. V, lect. 2 (1013a 29–1013b 2). See also Phys. II, 7 (198a 18–20); Meta. I, 2 (983a 30–32). |
29 | See, for instance, De part. an. III, 2 (663b 12–14); IV, 5 (679a 25–30); De gen. an. II, 4 (739b 27–31); III, 4 (755a 17–30). |
30 | Aristotle is careful to note that the final cause is not acting sensu stricto: “The active power is a ‘cause’ in the sense of that from which the process originates: but the end, for the sake of which it takes place, is not ‘active’. (That is why health is not ‘active,’ except metaphorically.) For when the agent is there, the patient becomes something: but when ‘states’ [ἕξεων, hexeōn, dispositions] are there, the patient no longer becomes but already is—and ‘forms’ [εἴδη, eidē] (i.e., ‘ends’) [καὶ τὰ τέλη, kai ta telē] are a kind of ‘state’ [ἕξεις, hexeis]” (De gen. et corr. I, 7 [342b 14–18]). |
31 | In response to the objection that the end—existing upon the completion of the agent’s action—cannot be its cause, Aquinas says that “Although the end be last in the order of execution, yet it is first in the order of the agent’s intention. And it is this way that it is a cause” (ST I–II, 1, 1, ad 1). Concerning natural causes that do not have cognition, Aquinas thinks their “intention” is expressed in their natural inclinations: “to intend … is nothing else than to have a natural inclination to something” (De prin. nat. 19). |
32 | Aquinas has something similar to say in De prin. nat. 19: “we should notice that, although every agent, both natural and voluntary, intends an end, still it does not follow that every agent knows the end or deliberates about the end. To know the end is necessary in those whose actions are not determined, but which may act for opposed ends as, for example, voluntary agents. Therefore it is necessary that these know the end by which they determine their actions. But in natural agents the actions are determined, hence it is not necessary to choose those things which are for the end”. See also Bostock (2006, pp. 48–78), Gotthelf (1976), and Guthrie (1981, pp. 114–18). |
33 | Aquinas’s teaching on final causation follows—for the most part—the position of Aristotle. See In Meta. V, lect. 2 (§ 775); V, 3 (§ 781–82); In Phys. V, lect. 11 (§ 246); De prin. nat. 19, 34–36. |
34 | “No incidental cause can be prior to a cause per se. Spontaneity and chance, therefore, are posterior to intelligence and nature. Hence, however true it may be that the heavens are due to spontaneity, it will still be true that intelligence and nature will be prior causes of this all and of many things in it besides” (Phys. II, 6 [198a 8–13]). |
35 | In his On the Origin of Species, we find Darwin saying: “Mere chance, as we may call it, might cause one variety to differ in some character from its parents, and the offspring of this variety again to differ from its parent in the very same character and in a greater degree; but this alone would never account for so habitual and large an amount of difference as that between varieties of the same species and species of the same genus” (Darwin 1859, p. 111). I think this shows that Darwin was aware of the fact that ontologically real chance events that produce minor variations remain in synergy with the regularity and teleological character of life cycles and the transmission of features between generations. This allows for the accumulation of accidental changes that may lead, in extended periods of time, to speciation. |
36 | I treat this statement as a working definition of theistic evolution. It is commonly known that the theory of evolution was and still is perceived by many as challenging the more literal interpretation of the Bible and the creation story found in Genesis. The more than 160 years that have passed since the publication of Darwin’s book On the Origin of Species (1859) abound in both supportive theological interpretations as well as fierce theologically motivated refutations of his theory. Peters and Hewlett (2003) offer a helpful map of various theological responses to evolutionary theory. Another overview can be found in Fowler and Kuebler (2007). A list of important works related to (1) the historical account of the debate on evolution, (2) a general introduction to the encounter of theology and evolutionary biology, and (3) the debate on the theory of Intelligent Design, can be found in Tabaczek (2024, p. 12n25). |
37 | See ST I, 45, 1–3. Each of the points listed here can be unpacked and further analyzed. I offer such an analysis in Tabaczek (2024, pp. 142–47). My use of the qualification “contingent” in this context refers to the fact that all things created are transient and not necessary. It does not reflect Aquinas’s other use of contingency in the sense of a given thing being not fully determined in its nature to one end. |
38 | See Aquinas’s introduction to ST I, q. 65. Kretzmann notes that this distinction, present also in Super II Sent. 13, 1, 1; 14, 1, 5; 15, 1, 1; 15, 2, 2 and 17, 2, 2, is not fully developed in SCG II, 39–45, where opus distinctionis covers also opus ornatus: “[F]urnishing [opus ornatus] is never even mentioned in SCG II or, for that matter, anywhere else in SCG. So, if ‘distinguishing’ in II.39–45 designates Aquinas’s explanation of the origin of all species … then in SCG ‘distinguishing’ covers also what is carefully separated off as the work of furnishing not only in ST, written after SCG, but also in Aquinas’s earlier Commentary on the Sentences” (Kretzmann 1998, p. 186). |
39 | And even if only earth and water are named, adds Thomas, the author of Gen 1:2 had in mind air and fire as well. The reason he does not mention them is that “the corporeal nature of these would not be so evident as that of earth and water, to the ignorant people” to whom he spoke (see ST I, 66, 1, ad 3 and reply to sc 2 of obj. 3). |
40 | We must remember that in antiquity, many thought plants were not living organisms because they do not move and allocate themselves. Hence, the production of plants in the account of Genesis preceded the actual opus ornatus. |
41 | Aquinas’s distinction between creatio and productio seems to correspond with the distinction between the Hebrew “to create” (bara [בָּרָא]) and “to make” (asah [עָשָׂה]). It is important to acknowledge that Aquinas is not always consistent in his use of these terms. See Tabaczek (2024, pp. 189–90). |
42 | Although Aquinas uses the term rationes seminales explicitly on numerous occasions in his commentary on the Sentences, in other parts of ST, in De veritate, De potentia, and De malo, and in some biblical commentaries, he paradoxically does not use it in his analysis of the works of the six days (ST I, qq. 65–74). At the same time, however, he does refer in these questions directly to the authority of Augustine and his concept of all types of creatures existing in statu potentiae in the earth (the primitive elements) and unfolding at the proper time, contrasting his view with the one held by “other holy writers”. |
43 | ST I, 69, 2, corp.: “In these first days God created all things in their origin or causes, and from this work He subsequently rested. Yet afterwards, by governing His creatures, in the work of propagation, ‘He worketh until now’. Now the production of plants from out the earth is a work of propagation, and therefore they were not produced in act on the third day, but in their causes only”. |
44 | See also Q. de pot. 4, 2, ad 28: “Before the plants were produced causally, nothing was produced, but they were produced together with the heaven and the earth. In like manner the fishes, birds and animals were produced in those six days causally and not actually”. |
45 | “[T]he first members of the species were immediately created by God, such as the first man, the first lion, and so forth” (Super II Sent., 1, 1, 4, co.). See also ST I, 65, 4, co. |
46 | “In its beginning the universe was perfect with regard to its species (quantum ad species)” (Q. de pot. 4, 2, ad 22). |
47 | “To the perfection of the universe there can be added something daily with regard to the number of individuals, not, however, with regard to the number of species”. (ST I, 118, 3, ad 2). |
48 | “The universe in its beginning was perfect (…) as regards nature’s causes from which afterwards other things could be propagated, but not as regards all their effects” (Q. de pot. 3, 10, ad 2). See also Q. de pot. 4, 1, co., Q. de pot. 5, 5, ad 13. |
49 | “[W]ith respect to the beginning of the world something pertains to the substance of faith, namely that the world began to be by creation, and all the saints agree in this. But how and in what order this was done pertains to faith only incidentally insofar as it is treated in scripture, the truth of which the saints save in the different explanations they offer” (Super II Sent. 12, 1, 2, co.). See also Q. de pot. 5, 1, co. |
50 | “[T]he universe can be made better, either through the addition of many parts, that is to say, so that many other species would be created, and that many degrees of goodness that can exist would be complete, since the distance between the highest creature and God is still infinite; and thus God could have made [in this way] the universe better and can still do it” (Super I Sent. 44, 1, 2, co.). See also ST I, 25, 6, ad 3. |
51 | “Species, also, that are new, if any such appear, existed beforehand in various active powers … [i.e., they] existed previously in their causes, in the works of the six days” (ST I, 73, 1, ad 3). |
52 | The view delineated here is shared by a substantial group of theologians coming from different traditions and denominations. It includes the contributors to the 2009 edited volume of the Pontifical Academy of Sciences concerning cosmic and biological evolution, John Paul II, Benedict XVI, Pope Francis, Christoph Schönborn, Denis Alexander, Philip Clayton, Arthur Peacocke, Philip Hefner, Paul Davies, and Robert John Russell. Interestingly, the same view—although not without qualifications—is expressed by some Thomistic philosophers and theologians, including Benedict Ashley, Joseph Donceel, and Nicanor Austriaco. A more detailed presentation of the “creationist” strain of theistic evolution can be found in Tabaczek (2024, pp. 180–87). |
53 | Even if he emphasizes that “The preservation of things by God is a continuation of that action whereby He gives existence” (ST I, 104, 1, ad 4), Aquinas never uses the term “continual creation” (creatio continua), which gained much popularity in a more recent philosophy of religion and creation theology. Fabien Revol (2020) traces its origin back to one of the metaphysical meditations of Francisco Suarez written in 1597, in which he (wrongly) attributes it to Aquinas saying “That is why S. Thomas claims that conservation is, as it were, a continual creation” (Et ideo saepe dicit divus Thomas, conservationem esse quasi continuatam creationem) (Suarez 1861, D. 21, 2, 4 [791]). |
54 | The phrase “as such” (per se) is thought of, in this context, as a way of a more static and synchronic description of the metaphysical categories of esse and essentia. It is contrasted with the complementary dynamic and diachronic side of these metaphysical categories, expressed in terms such as “coming into existence (into being)”, “existence in time”, and “educing (eduction of) SF from the potentiality of PM”. |
55 | Having said that divine conservatio of created things belongs to/is an intrinsic aspect of divine creatio, creaturely secondary causation with respect to (ee2) should be defined in terms of providing conditions for the flourishing, i.e., a proper actualization of dispositions proper to a given natural kind to which the entity/the organism in question belongs. |
56 | See SCG III, 70, no. 8 and ST I, 45, 5, co. Ignacio Silva (2022, pp. 98–102) analyzes Aquinas’s further distinction of the four ways of being the cause of action of something else, introduced in Q. de pot. 3, 7, co. |
57 | This view finds support in In De an. II, lect. 1 (§ 225–226) and SCG II, 72, no. 3. More recently, an anti–dualistic concern with respect to the received notion of anthropogenesis was expressed by Ratzinger: “Can we divide up man in this way between theologians and scientists—the soul for the former, the body for the latter?” (Ratzinger 2011, p. 135). |
58 | This finds confirmation in Aquinas’s general conviction that creation is not miraculous simply because—being ex nihilo—it does not include or presuppose any pre–existing substance or order of nature. Unlike creation, miracles do presuppose and pertain to the order of nature. In other words, they are special ways in which God brings about changes in the created order. As Aquinas notes in ST I, 105, 7, ad 1: “Creation, and the justification of the unrighteous, though done by God alone, are not, properly speaking, miracles, because they are not of a nature to proceed from any other cause; so they do not occur outside the order of nature, since they do not belong to that order”. |
59 | “[W]hen I assert that the human soul has not evolved, I do not claim that there is some empirical gap that we expect to find in natural history” (Madden 2013, p. 273). |
60 | This is an updated version of the list offered in Tabaczek (2024, pp. 167–68). |
61 | This topic is not discussed in the present article. I analyze it in Tabaczek (2024, pp. 244–77). |
62 | My position is inspired by Kretzmann, who states: “Aquinas, of course, had no inkling of any scientific evidence that might prompt an attempt to provide a non–literal interpretation of the biblical account. But the very wording of the first chapter of Genesis, and his idea of the level of sophistication in the audience for whom it was originally intended, led him to join Augustine in taking a remarkably enlightened view of the way to read the story of the six days—a view that would, I think, have equipped Augustine and Aquinas to appreciate judiciously, rather than denounce, scientific accounts of evolution” (Kretzmann 1998, p. 190). |
63 | It is important to notice that the suggested return to the classical categories of hylomorphism, essentialism, and formal and final causation subscribes to a wider revival of Aristotelianism observed in most recent analytic philosophy, particularly in analytic metaphysics. The dynamic aspects of Aristotle’s view of reality—framed within his notion of intertwined categories of potentiality and actuality—are rediscovered in the contemporary metaphysics of dispositions and their manifestations, which also offer an important (dispositional) view of causation that both challenges and contributes to the number of post–Humean notions of causation discussed in analytic metaphysics (see my critical introduction to dispositionalism and dispositional view of causation in Tabaczek 2019a, chp. 5,6, pp. 181–245). Moreover, the recognition of dispositions as “pointing” or being “directed” toward their characteristic manifestations brings back the notion of teleology. Hence, the proponents of dispositionalism talk about “physical” and “natural intentionality”, characteristic of inanimate objects as well as nonsentient, sentient, and conscious forms of living organisms. Finally, an important and heated debate is ongoing with regard to various contemporary analytic notions of hylomorphism. This definitely proves the renewed interest in this crucial conceptual tool of Aristotle, which further translates into the contemporary retrieval of essentialism and the debate over natural kinds (see Tabaczek 2019a, pp. 216–41 and Tabaczek, forthcoming). |
64 | I discuss this issue in greater detail in Tabaczek (2024, pp. 118–23). Leaving aside a complex question concerning the status of general laws in biology (as compared with those formulated in physics and chemistry), my view builds on an important contribution coming from William Stoeger who states: “Although the laws of nature reveal and describe fundamental patterns of behavior and regularities in the world, we cannot consider them the source of those regularities, much less attribute them the physical necessity these regularities seem to manifest. Nor can we ascribe to them an existence independent of the reality whose behavior they describe. Instead I claim that they are imperfect abstract descriptions of physical phenomena, not prescriptions dictating or enforcing behavior. Thus, a Platonic interpretation of these laws is unjustified” (Stoeger 1993, p. 208). Consequently, we must admit that the law (principle) of natural selection reveals and describes the regularity of a greater reproduction success of organisms that are better fitted in their environment. Yet, it does not causally make them to be such or reach reproduction success. It is thus—contrary to what was suggested by Francisco Ayala (see my critical evaluation of his position in Tabaczek 2024, pp. 111–14)—not teleological. |
65 | Alvaro Moreno and Matteo Mossio note that “[E]volutionary mechanisms operate because they are embodied in the complex organization of organisms. Thus, if we look for the roots of the impressive capacity of life to proliferate, to create an enormous variety of forms, to adapt to completely different environments, and particularly, to increase its complexity, we shall focus on individual living entities, namely on organisms, because evolution as an explanatory mechanism actually presupposes the existence of organisms” (Moreno and Mossio 2015, pp. xxi–xxii). Earlier on, in 1979, Francisco J. Varela argued that “evolutionary thought, through its emphasis on diversity, reproduction, and the species in order to explain the dynamics of change, has obscured the necessity of looking at the autonomous nature of living units for the understanding of biological phenomenology” (Varela 1979, p. 5). |
66 | |
67 | As already mentioned, I discuss this debate at length in Tabaczek (2024, pp. 244–77). The conversation on this topic is open and requires further analysis and conceptual work. |
68 | A balanced yet critical evaluation of the traditional approach represented by Karl Rahner (1961a, 1961b) and Piet Schoonenberg (1965, pp. 181–85), has more recently found a response on the side of Roszak (2020) and Vanzini (2023), who strive to defend the classical notion of praeternaturalia in the age of science. Again, the topic requires further analysis and study. |
69 |
References
Primary Sources
Abbreviations and Bibliographical References to the Works of AristotleDe gen. an. ~ De generatione animalium (On the Generation of Animals), translated by Arthur Platt. In The Basic Works of Aristotle, edited by Richard McKeon. New York: The Modern Library, 2001, pp. 665–80.De gen. et corr. ~ De generatione et corruptione (On Generation and Corruption), translated by Harold H. Joachim. In The Basic Works of Aristotle, edited by Richard McKeon. New York: The Modern Library, 2001, pp. 465–531.De part. an. ~ De partibus animalium (On the Parts of Animals), translated by William Ogle. In The Basic Works of Aristotle, edited by Richard McKeon. New York: The Modern Library, 2001, pp. 641–61.Hist. an. ~ Historia animalium (The History of Animals), translated by D’Arcy Wentworth Thompson. In The Complete Works of Aristotle: The Revised Oxford Translation, vol. 1, edited by Jonathan Barnes. Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1984, pp. 774–993.Meta. ~ Metaphysica (Metaphysics), translated by W. D. Ross. In The Basic Works of Aristotle, edited by Richard McKeon. New York: The Modern Library, 2001, pp. 681–926.Meteo. ~ Meteorologica (Meteorology), translated by W. Webster. In The Complete Works of Aristotle: The Revised Oxford Translation, vol. 1, edited by Jonathan Barnes. Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1984, pp. 555–625.Phys. ~ Physica (Physics), translated by R. K Gaye. In The Basic Works of Aristotle, edited by Richard McKeon. New York: The Modern Library, 2001, pp. 213–394.Abbreviations and Bibliographical References to the Works of AquinasComp. theo. ~ Compendium theologiae seu brevis compilation theologiae ad fratrem Raynaldum. In Opera omnia iussu Leonis XIII P. M. edita, Vol. 42. Rome: Editori di San Tommaso, 1979, pp. 83–191. [English translation: Aquinas Compendium of Theology, tr. C. Vollert. St. Louis: B. Herder Book Co., 1947.]De prin. nat. ~ De principiis naturae. Vol. 43 of Opera Omnia iussu Leonis XIII P. M. edita. Rome. Typographia polyglotta, 1976, pp. 39–47. [English translation: The Principles of Nature. In Selected Writings of St. Thomas Aquinas. Edited and translated by Robert P. Goodwin. New York: Bobbs–Merrill, 1965, pp. 7–28.]In De an. ~ In Aristotelis librum De anima commentarium. Vol. 45/1 of Opera Omnia. Rome: Typographia polyglotta, 1984. [English translation: Commentary on Aristotle’s De Anima in the Version of William of Moerbeke and the Commentary of St. Thomas Aquinas. Translated by Kenelm Foster and Silvester Humphries. London: Routledge and Kegan Paul, 1951.]In Meta. ~ In Metaphysicam Aristotelis commentaria. Turin and Rome: Marietti, 1926. [English translation: Commentary on The Metaphysics of Aristotle. 2 vols. Translated by John Rowan. Chicago: Regnery Press, 1961.]In Phys. ~ In octo libros Physicorum Aristotelis expositio. Turin and Rome: Marietti, 1965. [English translation: Commentary on Aristotle’s Physics. Translated by Richard J. Blackwell, Richard J. Spath, and W. Edmund Thirlkel. Notre Dame, Indiana: Dumb Ox Books, 1999.]Q. de an. ~ Quaestio disputata de anima. Edited by J. Robb. Toronto: Pontifical Institute of Medieval Studies, 1968. [English translation: Quaestions on the Soul. Translated by James H. Robb. Milwaukee, Wis.: Marquette University Press, 1984.]Q. de pot. ~ Quaestiones disputatae de potentia Dei. Turin and Rome: Marietti, 1965. [English translation: On the Power of God. Translated by English Dominican Fathers. Westminster, MD: Newman Press, 1952.]Q. de ver. ~ Quaestiones disputatae de veritate. Vol. 22/1–3 of Opera Omnia. Rome: Typographia polyglotta, 1972–1976. [English translation: Truth. 3 vols. Translated by Robert W. Mulligan S.J. et al. Albany, New York: Preserving Christian Publications, 1993.]SCG ~ Summa contra gentiles. 3 vols. Turin and Rome: Marietti, 1961–1967. [English translation: On the Truth of the Catholic Faith: Summa Contra Gentiles. 4 vols. Translated by Anton C. Pegis et al. Garden City, New York: Image Books, 1955–1957.]ST ~ Summa theologiae. Rome: Editiones Paulinae, 1962. [English translation: Summa Theologica. 3 vols. Translated by the Fathers of the English Dominican Province. New York: Benzinger Bros., 1946.]Super Sent. ~ Scriptum super Libros Sententiarum. Edited by S. E. Fretté and P. Maré. Vols. 7–11 of Opera omnia. Paris: Vivès, 1882–1989.Abbreviations and Bibliographical References to the Works of AugustineConf. ~ Confessionum Libri Tredecim. Latin edition: Confessions, vol 1. Introduction and Text, ed. with intro. and comm. by J. J. O’Donnell. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1992. [English translation: The Confessions, Maria Boulding, O.S.B., trans., John E. Rotelle, O.S.A., ed., in The Works of Saint Augustine: A Translation for the Twenty–First Century. New York: New City Press, 1997.]De Gen. ad litt. ~ De Genesi ad literam libri duodecim. In De Genesi ad literam libri duodecim. De Genesi ad literam inperfectus liber. Locutionum in Heptateuchum libri septem (CSEL 28.1.). Crit. ed. J. Zycha. Leipzig1894. [English translation: The Literal Meaning of Genesis. Vol. 1–2. Translated by John Hammond Taylor. New York: Newman Press, 1982.]De Gen. ad litt. imp. lib. ~ De Genesi ad literam inperfectus liber. In De Genesi ad literam libri duodecim. De Genesi ad literam inperfectus liber. Locutionum in Heptateuchum libri septem (CSEL 28.1.). Crit. ed. J. Zycha. Leipzig1894.Secondary Sources
- Artigas, Mariano, Thomas F. Glick, and Rafael A. Martínez. 2006. Negotiating Darwin: The Vatican Confronts Evolution, 1877–1902. Baltimore: JHU Press. [Google Scholar]
- Ashley, Benedict M. 1972. Causality and Evolution. The Thomist 36: 199–230. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Austin, Christopher J. 2017. Aristotelian Essentialism: Essence in the Age of Evolution. Synthese 194: 2539–56. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Balme, David M. 1987. Aristotle’s Biology Was Not Essentialist. In Philosophical Issues in Aristotle’s Biology. Edited by Allan Gotthelf and James G. Lennox. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 287–312. [Google Scholar]
- Bostock, David. 2006. Space, Time, Matter, and Form: Essays on Aristotle’s “Physics”. Oxford: Clarendon Press. [Google Scholar]
- Boulter, Stephen J. 2012. Can Evolutionary Biology Do Without Aristotelian Essentialism? Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplements 70: 83–103. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Carl, Brian T. 2020. Thomas Aquinas on the Proportionate Causes of Living Species. Scientia et Fides 8: 223–48. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Carroll, William E. 2006. At the Mercy of Chance? Evolution and the Catholic Tradition. Revue Des Questions Scientifiques 177: 179–204. [Google Scholar]
- Chaberek, Michael. 2017. Aquinas and Evolution: Why St. Thomas’ Teaching on the Origins Is Incompatible with Evolutionary Theory. Lexington: The Chartwell Press. [Google Scholar]
- Chaberek, Michael. 2019. Classical Metaphysics and Theistic Evolution: Why Are They Incompatible? Studia Gilsoniana 8: 47–81. [Google Scholar]
- Coffey, Peter. 1970. Ontology or the Theory of Being. Gloucester: Peter Smith. [Google Scholar]
- Darwin, Charles. 1859. On the Origin of Species by Means of Natural Selection, or the Preservation of Favoured Races in the Struggle for Life. London: John Murray. [Google Scholar]
- Davison, Andrew. 2023. Astrobiology and Christian Doctrine: Exploring the Implications of Life in the Universe. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Descartes, René. 1984. The Philosophical Writings of Descartes. Translated by John Cottingham, Robert Stoothoff, and Dugald Murdoch. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, vol. 2. [Google Scholar]
- Devitt, Michael. 2023. Biological Essentialism. Oxford: Oxford University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Dodds, Michael J. 2012. Unlocking Divine Action: Contemporary Science and Thomas Aquinas. Washington, DC: Catholic University of America Press. [Google Scholar]
- Donceel, Joseph. 1965. Causality and Evolution: A Survey of Some Neo–Scholastic Theories. New Scholasticism 39: 295–315. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Dumsday, Travis. 2012. Is There Still Hope for a Scholastic Ontology of Biological Species? The Thomist 76: 371–95. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Dupré, John. 1993. The Disorder of Things: Metaphysical Foundations of the Disunity of Science. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Elder, Crawford L. 2008. Biological Species Are Natural Kinds. The Southern Journal of Philosophy 46: 339–62. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Elders, Leo J. 1984. The Philosophical and Religious Background of Charles Darwin’s Theory of Evolution. Doctor Communis 37: 32–67. [Google Scholar]
- Ereshefsky, Marc. 1998. Species Pluralism and Anti–Realism. Philosophy of Science 65: 103–20. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Feser, Edward. 2014. Scholastic Metaphysics: A Contemporary Introduction. Heusenstamm: Editiones Scholasticae. [Google Scholar]
- Fowler, Thomas B., and Daniel Kuebler. 2007. The Evolution Controversy: A Survey of Competing Theories. Grand Rapids: Baker Academic. [Google Scholar]
- Frost, Gloria. 2022. Aquinas on Efficient Causation and Causal Powers. New York: Cambridge University Press. [Google Scholar]
- George, Marie I. 2005. Christianity and Extraterrestrials?: A Catholic Perspective. New York: iUniverse. [Google Scholar]
- Gilson, Étienne. 1984. From Aristotle to Darwin and Back Again: A Journey in Final Causality, Species, and Evolution. Notre Dame: Notre Dame Press. [Google Scholar]
- Gotthelf, Allan. 1976. Aristotle’s Conception of Final Causality. Review of Metaphysics 30: 226–54. [Google Scholar]
- Gouw, Arvin M., Brian Patrick Green, and Ted Peters, eds. 2022. Religious Transhumanism and Its Critics. Lanham: Lexington Books. [Google Scholar]
- Green, Brian Patrick. 2015. Transhumanism and Roman Catholicism: Imagined and Real Tensions. Theology and Science 13: 187–201. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Gregersen, Niels Henrik. 2013. Deep Incarnation and Kenosis: In, With, Under, and As: A Response to Ted Peters. Dialog 52: 251–62. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Griffiths, Paul E. 2001. What Is Innateness? The Monist 85: 70–85. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Guthrie, William K. C. 1981. A History of Greek Philosophy: Volume 6, Aristotle: An Encounter. New York and Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Hey, Jody. 2001. Genes, Categories, and Species: The Evolutionary and Cognitive Cause of the Species Problem. New York: Oxford University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Keltz, Benjamin Kyle. 2020. Thomism and the Problem of Animal Suffering. Eugene: Wipf and Stock. [Google Scholar]
- Kitcher, Philip. 2003. In Mendel’s Mirror: Philosophical Reflections on Biology. Oxford and New York: Oxford University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Kitts, David B., and David J. Kitts. 1979. Biological Species as Natural Kinds. Philosophy of Science 46: 613–22. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Kretzmann, Norman. 1998. The Metaphysics of Creation: Aquinas’s Natural Theology in Summa Contra Gentiles II. Oxford: Clarendon Press. [Google Scholar]
- Kripke, Saul A. 1980. Naming and Necessity. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Lamoureux, Denis O. 2009. Evolutionary Creation: Moving Beyond the Evolution Versus Creation Debate. Christian Higher Education 9: 28–48. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Lennox, James G. 2001. Aristotle’s Philosophy of Biology: Studies in the Origins of Life Science. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Leroy, Marie–Dalmace. 1891. L’évolution Restreinte Aux Espèces Organiques. Paris: Delhomme et Briguet. [Google Scholar]
- Luyten, Norbert A. 1951. The Philosophical Implications of Evolution. The New Scholasticism 25: 290–312. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Luyten, Norbert A. 1954. Evolutionisme En Wijsbegeerte. Tijdschrift Voor Philosophie 16: 3–36. [Google Scholar]
- Madden, James D. 2013. Mind, Matter, and Nature: A Thomistic Proposal for the Philosophy of Mind. Washington, DC: CUA Press. [Google Scholar]
- Maritain, Jacques. 1952. The Range of Reason. New York: Scribner. [Google Scholar]
- Mayr, Ernst. 1963. Populations, Species, and Evolution, An Abridgment of Animal Species and Evolution, Abridged ed. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Mayr, Ernst. 1976. Evolution and the Diversity of Life: Selected Essays. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Mivart, St. George Jackson. 1871. On the Genesis of Species. New York: D. Appleton. [Google Scholar]
- Molnar, George. 2003. Powers: A Study in Metaphysics. Edited by Stephen Mumford. New York: Oxford University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Monod, Jacques. 1970. Chance and Necessity: An Essay on the Natural Philosophy of Modern Biology. Translated by Austryn Wainhouse. New York: Vintage Books. [Google Scholar]
- Moreno, Alvaro, and Matteo Mossio. 2015. Biological Autonomy: A Philosophical and Theoretical Enquiry. Dordrecht: Springer. [Google Scholar]
- Moreno, Antonio. 1973. Some Philosophical Considerations on Biological Evolution. The Thomist 37: 417–54. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Morrison, Margaret. 2000. Unifying Scientific Theories: Physical Concepts and Mathematical Structures. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Nordlander, Andreas. 2019. The Emergence of Soul: Retrieving Augustine’s Potentialism for Contemporary Theological Anthropology. Modern Theology 35: 122–37. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Oderberg, David S. 2007. Real Essentialism. New York: Routledge. [Google Scholar]
- O’Hara, Robert J. 1993. Systematic Generalization, Historical Fate, and the Species Problem. Systematic Biology 42: 231–46. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- O’Rourke, Fran. 2004. Aristotle and the Metaphysics of Evolution. The Review of Metaphysics 58: 3–59. [Google Scholar]
- Peters, Ted, and Martin Hewlett. 2003. Evolution from Creation to New Creation: Conflict, Conversation, and Convergence. Nashville: Abingdon Press. [Google Scholar]
- Peters, Ted, Martinez Hewlett, Joshua M. Moritz, and Robert John Russell, eds. 2018. Astrotheology: Science and Theology Meet Extraterrestrial Life. Eugene: Cascade Books. [Google Scholar]
- Peterson, Daniel J. 2013. The Kenosis of the Father: Affirming God’s Action at the Higher Levels of Nature. Theology and Science 11: 451–54. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Phillips, Richard Percival. 2013. Modern Thomistic Philosophy: An Explanation for Students. Volume 1: The Philosophy of Nature. Heusenstamm: Editiones Scholasticae. First published 1962. [Google Scholar]
- Rahner, Karl. 1961a. On the Theology of Death. Translated by Charles H. Henkey. London: Burns & Oates. [Google Scholar]
- Rahner, Karl. 1961b. The Theological Concept of Concupiscentia. In Theological Investigations, Vol. I: God—Christ—Mary and Grace. Baltimore: Helicon Press, pp. 347–82. [Google Scholar]
- Ratzinger, Joseph Cardinal. 2011. Belief in Creation and the Theory of Evolution. In Dogma and Preaching. San Francisco: Ignatius Press, pp. 131–42. [Google Scholar]
- Revol, Fabien. 2020. The Concept of Continuous Creation Part I: History and Contemporary Use. Zygon 55: 229–50. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Richards, Richard A. 2008. Species and Taxonomy. In The Oxford Handbook of Philosophy of Biology. Edited by Michael Ruse. Oxford and New York: Oxford University Press, pp. 161–88. [Google Scholar]
- Rieppel, Olivier. 2010. New Essentialism in Biology. Philosophy of Science 77: 662–73. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Roszak, Piotr. 2020. Thomas Aquinas on Life in Paradise and Its Anthropological Significance. Archa Verbi 17: 65–88. [Google Scholar]
- Schoonenberg, Piet. 1965. Man and Sin: A Theological View by Piet Schoonenberg. Translated by Joseph Donceel. Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press. [Google Scholar]
- Silva, Ignacio. 2022. Providence and Science in a World of Contingency: Thomas Aquinas’ Metaphysics of Divine Action. New York: Routledge. [Google Scholar]
- Smith, John Maynard, and Eors Szathmary. 2000. The Origins of Life: From the Birth of Life to the Origin of Language. Oxford: Oxford University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Sober, Elliott. 1980. Evolution, Population Thinking and Essentialism. Philosophy of Science 47: 350–83. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Sober, Elliott. 2024. The Philosophy of Evolutionary Theory: Concepts, Inferences, and Probabilities. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Sollereder, Bethany N. 2019. God, Evolution, and Animal Suffering: Theodicy without a Fall. New York: Routledge. [Google Scholar]
- Southgate, Christopher. 2008. The Groaning of Creation: God, Evolution, and the Problem of Evil. Louisville: Westminster John Knox Press. [Google Scholar]
- Stoeger, William R. 1993. Contemporary Physics and the Ontological Status of the Laws of Nature. In Quantum Cosmology and the Laws of Nature: Scientific Perspectives on Divine Action. Edited by Robert J. Russell, Philip Clayton, Kirk Wegter–McNelly and John Polkinghorne. Berkeley: Vatican Observatory & Center for Theology and the Natural Sciences, pp. 207–31. [Google Scholar]
- Suarez, Francisco. 1861. Opera Omnia. Edited by Carolo Berton. Paris: Louis Vivès, vol. 25. [Google Scholar]
- Tabaczek, Mariusz. 2014. An Aristotelian Account of Evolution and the Contemporary Philosophy of Biology. In The 1st Virtual International Conference on the Dialogue between Science and Theology. Dialogo Conf 2014: Cosmology, Life & Anthropology. Edited by Cosmin Tudor Ciocan and Anton Lieskovský. Zilina: Publishing Institution of the University of Zilina, pp. 57–69. [Google Scholar]
- Tabaczek, Mariusz. 2015. Thomistic Response to the Theory of Evolution: Aquinas on Natural Selection and the Perfection of the Universe. Theology and Science 13: 325–44. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Tabaczek, Mariusz. 2019a. Emergence: Towards A New Metaphysics and Philosophy of Science. Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press. [Google Scholar]
- Tabaczek, Mariusz. 2019b. What Do God and Creatures Really Do in an Evolutionary Change? Divine Concurrence and Trans-formism from the Thomistic Perspective. American Catholic Philosophical Quarterly 93: 445–82. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Tabaczek, Mariusz. 2020. The Metaphysics of Evolution: From Aquinas’s Interpretation of Augustine’s Concept of Rationes Seminales to the Contemporary Thomistic Account of Species Transformism. Nova et Vetera 18: 945–72. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Tabaczek, Mariusz. 2022. Does God Create Through Evolution? A Thomistic Perspective. Theology and Science 20: 46–68. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Tabaczek, Mariusz. 2023a. Contemporary Version of the Monogenetic Model of Anthropogenesis: Some Critical Remarks from the Thomistic Perspective. Religions 14: 528. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Tabaczek, Mariusz. 2023b. Human Enhancement, Transhumanism, and Posthumanism: Secular Notion of Transcendence and Its Metaphysical Presuppositions. Angelicum 100: 389–417. [Google Scholar]
- Tabaczek, Mariusz. 2024. Theistic Evolution: A Contemporary Aristotelian–Thomistic Perspective. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Tabaczek, Mariusz. Forthcoming. Contemporary and Classical Versions of Hylomorphism. Paper presented at the 11th International Thomistic Congress at the Angelicum, Rome, Italy, September 19–24.
- Vanzini, Marco. 2023. The Human Condition Before the Fall: Man as the Object of God’s Paternal and Providential Care. Scientia et Fides 11: 213–31. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Varela, Francisco J. 1979. Principles of Biological Autonomy. New York: North Holland. [Google Scholar]
- Wallace, Stan W. 2002. In Defense of Biological Essentialism. Philosophia Christi 4: 29–43. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Walsh, Denis. 2006. Evolutionary Essentialism. The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 57: 425–48. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
Disclaimer/Publisher’s Note: The statements, opinions and data contained in all publications are solely those of the individual author(s) and contributor(s) and not of MDPI and/or the editor(s). MDPI and/or the editor(s) disclaim responsibility for any injury to people or property resulting from any ideas, methods, instructions or products referred to in the content. |
© 2024 by the author. Licensee MDPI, Basel, Switzerland. This article is an open access article distributed under the terms and conditions of the Creative Commons Attribution (CC BY) license (https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/).
Share and Cite
Tabaczek, M. A Contemporary Aristotelian–Thomistic Perspective on the Evolutionary View of Reality and Theistic Evolution. Religions 2024, 15, 524. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel15050524
Tabaczek M. A Contemporary Aristotelian–Thomistic Perspective on the Evolutionary View of Reality and Theistic Evolution. Religions. 2024; 15(5):524. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel15050524
Chicago/Turabian StyleTabaczek, Mariusz. 2024. "A Contemporary Aristotelian–Thomistic Perspective on the Evolutionary View of Reality and Theistic Evolution" Religions 15, no. 5: 524. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel15050524
APA StyleTabaczek, M. (2024). A Contemporary Aristotelian–Thomistic Perspective on the Evolutionary View of Reality and Theistic Evolution. Religions, 15(5), 524. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel15050524