The One and the Many in Bonaventure Exemplarity Explained
Abstract
:1. Exemplary Ideas and God
1.1. Augustine and Divine Ideas
1.2. Bonaventure and Divine Ideas
- (1)
- If God were to know things by means of an idea, then God would not know through Godself, but through something else17. That would mean that God is dependent on something else in order to know, which is a sign of weakness and imperfection.
- (2)
- An idea is a likeness18, and wherever there is a likeness, there must be a suitability (convenientia) between the two terms of the likeness. But on account of the great distance between God and creatures, either there is no likeness, or it is very small (minima). Therefore, either there is nothing like an idea in God, or it is imperfect; but there can be no imperfection in God, therefore etc.19.
- (3)
- The most noble mode of knowing is to be attributed to God; but it is more noble to know a thing through its essence than through a likeness. Therefore God knows through an essence and not through a likeness20.
- (4)
- Ideas are only necessary for directing and regulating; but only those things that are capable of wandering need direction and regulation. God is not of this sort, therefore God does not require ideas24.
- The first argument considers the ways in which an agent may act, namely by reason, by chance, or by necessity. Chance or necessity as the source of divine agency in the act of knowing are quickly dismissed, and it is not hard to see why: chance would imply imperfection in God, and necessity would imply compulsion. Therefore God acts according to reason. In this article, this seems to mean that God acts on the basis of knowledge. That is to say, the agent must know the effect it is going to produce before that effect exists.Now, everything known is known either through its reality or through a likeness. But nothing exists when God first knows it, for God must know it in order to be able to create it (as was just shown). Therefore things cannot be known through their reality in God. Therefore they must be known according to a likeness26.
- The second argument is based on the logic of signification: If X leads determinately to the knowledge of Y, then X must either have within itself some likeness of Y or be itself the likeness of Y. The protasis of the conditional may be explained as follows: leading determinately is to be opposed to leading accidentally. Therefore, only that which leads to Y by something essential to itself (rather than something accidental) leads determinately to Y. Further to lead to the knowledge of Y requires that X be a likeness of Y, for it is the recognition of an existing likeness that causes one to move mentally from X to Y. Thus, in order to move the mind determinately to knowledge of Y, X must possess an essential likeness to Y.Now, those who look upon God are led to the knowledge of all creatures27. Therefore there must either be some likeness of creatures in God, or God must be this likeness. Further, since these likenesses do not just represent things to others, but also to Godself, they are in God as in a knower. But to represent an object to the mind of a knower by means of a likeness is basically the definition of an idea; therefore there are ideas in God28.
- The third argument is a bit odd. The first step in the argument is that (i) because things are produced by God, they are in God as in their efficient cause, and God is most truly efficient cause. It is this last claim that is difficult to understand: namely, what are we to understand the relationship to be between the fact that things are in God as in their efficient cause and the fact that God is most truly efficient cause? The most likely answer is that we are to understand this as being two ways of expressing the one result: God has produced things, therefore they are in God as in their efficient cause, which is to say that God is most truly efficient cause. The unstated assumption is that in efficient causality effects are in their causes to a significant degree. This claim in itself is not controversial29; it is in effect the guiding intuition behind Augustine’s entire deduction of ideas in God.Next, the argument asserts that (ii) because things are brought to completion by God, God is most truly final cause. This argument appears to parallel the first argument, with the only change being that now we are considering the final cause and not the efficient cause. However, there is an important asymmetry between the two arguments: Bonaventure does not say that things are in God as in their final cause (a claim he did make about efficient causality). This is a reasonable omission: given that final cause is that to which things tend, it would not make sense for things to be contained within that final cause in any straightforward sense. However, the omission does not seem entirely justified given that at the end of the Itinerarium, when the mind reaches at last its final cause (God), it comes to rest in that cause, and so is contained within it. Nevertheless, it is not contained within the final cause from the beginning, and most importantly, not at the time the causation is active, but only once that causal activity is complete. Union is the outcome and not the means of final causality.The argument continues that (iii) in the same way, because things are known and expressed by God, God is most truly exemplar. One might expect the conclusion to be that there must be an exemplar in God; instead, the surprising conclusion is that God must be the exemplar. This argument, presented at this point in the proceedings, is not yet as strong as it will be later; but of all the arguments, it is the most like Bonaventure’s eventual reply, and as such it is anticipating much of the substance of his answer. The missing argument required to get from “God contains an exemplar of all things” to “God is the exemplar of all things” will be elucidated in the response.Finally, the argument claims (iv) that there is no exemplar unless there are ideas of the exemplified things; therefore there must be ideas in God30. This fourth premise, that there is no exemplar unless there are ideas of the exemplified things, amounts to a claim that the exemplified must be in the exemplar in an ideal form. It is presented as being entailed by the definition of the word “exemplar”. Thus, in addition to what is explicitly argued here, we also have a claim about the nature of exemplarity and, ultimately, exemplary causality. It is, Bonaventure implies, much more like efficient causality than it is like final causality.
- (1)
- Whatever God knows, God knows by means of a simple gaze (See note 32).
- (2)
- In all knowledge, there is an assimilation of the knower to the thing known. This similarity is grounded on a likeness of the object known in the mind of the knower.
- (3)
- God has knowledge.
- (4)
- Therefore there must be some such likeness in God (from 2 and 3).
- (5)
- These likenesses must either be caused by the things of which they are the likeness, or not.
- (6)
- In the case of God, they cannot be caused by the objects themselves for many reasons, not least of which is that in that case God would not know by means of a simple gaze, but by multiple likenesses caused by multiple things and received through some process38.
- (7)
- Therefore they must not be caused from outside, but already exist in God (from 5 and 6).
- (8)
- It is more noble to know by means of essence than by a likeness39.
- (9)
- God is most noble.
- (10)
- Therefore in God these likenesses must belong to the category of essence (from 8 and 9).
- (11)
- But the divine essence is simple;40 therefore there cannot be multiple essences in God, nor a division within the essence.
- (12)
- Therefore these ideas cannot be other than the divine essence (from 10 and 11).
- (13)
- But if they were the creaturely essences, it would follow that creatures and the Creator have the same essence, which is absurd ([9], q. 2, resp.).
- (14)
- Therefore they cannot be the essences of things.
2. Exemplary Ideas and Knowledge
2.1. Plurality of Ideas
I call it intrinsic not only because it emerges from within, but also because it has an intrinsic object, an intrinsic principle, and an intrinsic mode. I say it has an intrinsic object because, in the act of knowing, the divine vision does not look at objects outside the divinity itself. Rather, it knows all truth in as far as it gazes upon the divinity itself precisely as truth.([9], qu. 1, resp., p. 78)
2.2. The Influence of the Exemplary Ideas on Cognition
Conflicts of Interest
References
- John F. Wippel. Metaphysical Themes in Thomas Aquinas II. Studies in Philosophy 47; Washington: Catholic University of America Press, 2007, pp. 152–71. [Google Scholar]
- Alexander of Hales, Bernardinus Klumper, and Collegium S. Bonaventurae. Doctoris Irrefragabilis Alexandri de Hales Ordinis Minorum Summa Theological. Florence: Quaracchi, 1924, IaIIae, qu. 7; p. 16. [Google Scholar]
- M. Hurley. “Illumination according to S. Bonaventure.” Gregorianum 32 (1951): 388–404. [Google Scholar]
- Zachary Hayes. “Indeed, for Bonaventure the most properly metaphysical question is that of exemplarity.” In The Hidden Center. New York: Paulist Press, 1981, p. 13. [Google Scholar]
- J. A. Wayne Hellman. Divine and Created Order in Bonaventure’s Theology. Translated by Jay M. Hammond. St. Bonaventure: The Franciscan Institute, 2001, p. 67. [Google Scholar]
- Saint Bonaventure. “Collationes in Hexaemeron.” In Opera Omnia. Quaracchi: Collegium Sancti Bonaventurae, 1891, vol. 5, pp. 327–454. [Google Scholar]
- Leonard J. Bowman. “The Cosmic Exemplarism of St. Bonaventure.” Journal of Religion 55 (1975): 181–98. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Saint Bonaventure. Opera Omnia. Edited by Collegium Sancti Bonaventurae. 10 vols; Quaracchi: Collegium Sancti Bonaventurae, 1882–1902. [Google Scholar]
- Saint Bonaventure. Disputed Questions on the Knowledge of Christ. Translated by Zachary Hayes. St. Bonaventure: Franciscan Institute, 1992. [Google Scholar]
- Joshua Benson. “Structure and Meaning in St. Bonaventure’s Quaestiones Disputatae De Scientia Christi.” Franciscan Studies 62 (2004): 67–90. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Wendy Petersen Boring. “Revising Our Approach to ‘Augustinian Illumination’: A Reconsideration of Bonaventure’s Quaestiones disputatae de scientia Christi IV, Aquinas’ Summa theologiae Ia.84, 1–8, Henry of Ghent’s, Summa quaestionum ordinarum, Q. 2, art. 1, 2.” Franciscan Studies 68 (2010): 39–81. [Google Scholar]
- Saint Augustine. Eighty-Three Different Questions. Translated by David L. Mosher. Washington: Catholic University of America Press, 1982, p. 79. [Google Scholar]
- Saint Augustine. “The Fathers of the Church 78, 79, 88, 90, & 92.” In Tractates on the Gospel of John. Translated by John W. Retting. Washington: Catholic University of America Press, 1995. [Google Scholar]
- Plato. “Phaedrus.” In Plato: Complete Works. Edited by John M. Cooper. Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing Company, 1997, pp. 506–56. [Google Scholar]
- William Preddy. Republic. Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 2013. [Google Scholar]
- Thomas Aquinas. Commentary on the Posterior Analytics of Aristotle. Translated by Fabian R. Larcher. Albany: Magi Books, 1970, p. 189. [Google Scholar]
- Etienne Gilson. The Philosophy of Saint Bonaventure. Translated by Dom Illtyd Trethowan. Patterson: St. Anthony Guild Press, 1965, pp. 132–33. [Google Scholar]
- W. Norris Clarke. “The Problem of the Reality and Multiplicity of Divine Ideas in Christian Neoplatonism.” In Neoplatonism and Christian Thought. Edited by Dominic J. O’Meara. Albany: State University of New York University Press, 1982, p. 123. [Google Scholar]
- Ewert Cousins. Bonaventure and the Coincidence of Opposites. Chicago: Franciscan Herald Press, 1978, p. 116. [Google Scholar]
- Mark G. Henninger. Relations: Medieval Theories 1250–1325. Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1989. [Google Scholar]
- 1For a thorough discussion of this principle in Aquinas and its grounding in Aristotle, see [1].
- 2For one example, cf. Timaeus 29d6 ff., which describes the universe as model on the single Living Thing; another example is Timaeus 41a7–41d4, from which it could be argued that because each creation is less perfect than its maker, and since the unity of the form of the Good is a perfection, the highest unity could only be imaged in a vast multiplicity.
- 3See for example the lengthy discussion in the Summa Halensis ([2], p. 16).
- 4Hurley says: “Exemplarism indeed is in Bonaventure’s thought the open sesame which explains the whole universe.” [3]. Cf. Zachary Hayes: “Indeed, for Bonaventure the most properly metaphysical question is that of exemplarity” [4]. In light of this, care must be taken with J. A. Wayne Hellman’s claim that “…Bonaventure’s doctrine of exemplarism is simply the Christian teaching that all of creation comes forth from the Father and is first expressed in that expression of Himself, namely, the second person who is the Son and the medium” [5]. It is not incorrect to tie exemplarity to the doctrine of creation, as will be shown here; but it is incomplete. We must lean on the second half of the quote from Hellman, that exemplarity will begin in the doctrine of creation, but will reach beyond it into Trinity and Christology. Bonaventure himself, in a famous passage from the Hexaemeron, indicates the importance of exemplarity to his thinking: “Haec est tota nostra metaphysica: de emanatione, de exemplaritate, de consummatione” (Hex. col. 1, no. 17) [6] [“This is our whole metaphysics: concerning emanation, exemplarity, and consummation”]. Leonard Bowman reduces this statement to a primary concern with exemplarity: “These three concepts describe a process in which created beings come forth from God, reflect and express him in their being, and then return to him. They provide therefore the three points which determine the circular economy of exemplarism” [7].
- 5Found in Bonaventure [8]. All translations from the commentary on the Sentences are my own.
- 6Henceforth DQKC.
- 7Joshua Benson rightly observes that DQKC is not a text about the certitude of human knowledge; rather, this only occurs at the midpoint of the disputation as the transition from considering divine knowledge (scientia) to the wisdom of the Incarnate Christ (sapientia) [10].
- 8It might seem that the claim that this is essentially a Platonic problem means that I will be disagreeing with Wendy Peterson Boring, who argues that Bonaventure’s theory of knowledge, especially in this part of DQKC, is actually Aristotelian, in explicit rejection of Platonic epistemology [11]. This is not in fact the case: I am in agreement with Boring’s conclusions in that article. The problem Bonaventure is addressing is, as he has received it, a Platonic one, but his response is Aristotelian (and, indeed, Augustinian) in character.
- 9Augustine says that the words “form,” “species,” or “reasons” might equally be used.
- 10“Now what person, devout and trained in true religion, although he could not yet contemplate these [ideas], would, nonetheless, dare to deny—nay, would not even acknowledge—that all things which are, i.e., that whatever things are fixed in their own order by a certain particular nature so as to exist, are produced by God as their cause? And that by that cause all things which live do live? And that the universal soundness of things and the very order whereby those things which change do repeat with a certain regularity their journeys through time are fixed and governed by the laws of the most high God? This having been established and conceded, who would dare to say that God has created all things without a rational plan? But if one cannot rightly say or believe this, it remains that all things are created on a rational plan, and man not by the same plan as horse, for it is absurd to think this. Therefore individual things are created in accord with reasons unique to them” ([12], pp. 80–81).
- 11“As for these reasons, they must be thought to exist nowhere but in the very mind of the Creator. For it would be sacrilegious to suppose that he was looking at something placed outside himself when he created in accord with it what he did create” ([12], p. 81).
- 12“It is by participation in these that whatever is exists in whatever manner it does exist” [12].
- 13“There is, however, in wisdom itself, in a spiritual way, a certain reason by which the earth was made: this is life” (Tractate 1, no. 17, [78:56]).
- 14Tractate 1, no. 17, [78:55].
- 15This is not an unexpected problem if one begins with Plato’s account. In the Phaedrus (246b ff.) [14], it was the inability to catch sight of something true that caused the fall of the soul into bodiliness; the gods, by contrast, are always safe because their minds are always nourished by the vision of the forms. Wouldn’t it then follow that for God to turn from the contemplation of the highest reality would also entail a turn to imperfection?
- 16Throughout both Sent. and DQKC Bonaventure will use several different terms that are meant to be rough equivalents of idea: similitudines and rationes aeternas are the most common. For the most part, I will simply use “idea” throughout this discussion.
- 17“Dionysius, De divinis nominibus: ‘Cognoscit divinus intellectus, sed ex se ipso et per se ipsum, non secundum ideam singulis se immittens, sed secundum unam excellentiae causam omnia noscens et continens’: ergo Deus singula non cognoscit per ideam” (I Sent. dist. 35, art. un., qu. 1, contra 1) [“Dionysius, Concerning the Divine Names: ‘The divine intellect knows, but from itself and through itself, not applying itself to each thing according to an idea, but knowing and containing all things according to one cause of excellence.’ Therefore God does not know individual things through an idea.”].
- 18That idea is a form of similitudo (“likeness”) is argued in the second argument in favor of the position: “Sed similitudo rei, per quam res cognoscitur et producitur, est idea” (I Sent. dist. 35, art. un., qu. 1, arg. 2) [“But the likeness of a thing through which the thing is known and produces is an idea”]. It is further clarified in the response: “intelligendum, quod idea dicitur similitudo rei cognitae” (I Sent. dist. 35, art. un., qu. 1, resp.). [“it must be understood that an idea is called the likeness of the thing known”].
- 19“Item, ratione videtur: quia idea dicit rationem similitudinis, et similitudo dicit rationem convenientiae; Dei autem ad creaturam, cum sit summa distantia, nulla est convenientia, aut si est, minima est: ergo aut nulla similitudo aut minima. Aut ergo non est idea in Deo, aut si est, secundum rationem imperfectum est; sed nihil imperfectum ponendum est in Deo: ergo etc.” (I Sent. dist. 35, art. un., qu. 1, contra 2) [“Again, it is seen by reason: because idea indicates the notion of likeness, and likeness indicates the notion of suitability; but there is no suitability of God to the creature because there is greatest distance; or if there is suitability, it is minimal. Therefore either there is no likeness or it is minimal. Therefore either there is no idea in God, or if there is, it is imperfect according to reason; but nothing imperfect is to be posited in God, therefore etc.”].
- 20“Item, nobilissimus modus cognitionis est Deo attribuendus; sed cognitio per rei essentiam est nobilior quam per similitudinem rei: ergo Deus cognoscit per essentiam rei, non per similitudinem. Sed idea est similitudo, non essentia rei: et sic etc.” (I Sent. dist. 35, art. un., qu. 1, contra 3) [“Again, the most noble mode of knowing is to be attributed to God; but knowledge through the essence of the thing is more noble than through the likeness of the thing. Therefore God knows through the essence of the thing, not through a likeness. But the idea is a likeness, not the essence of the thing: and thus etc.”].
- 21This is, of course, the conclusion of the allegory of the cave ([15], Book VII, 514a1 ff.).
- 22“At any rate, a person who knows some thing to be must know it through something of that thing, namely, something outside of the essence of the thing or something pertaining to its essence. And he clarifies this with the example of knowing thunder to be, because we perceive a sound in the clouds—which of course pertains to the essence of thunder, albeit not the entire essence, because not every sound in the clouds is thunder—or of knowing a defect, i.e., an eclipse, of the sun or moon to be, because there is a failure of light—although not every failure of light is an eclipse” [16].
- 23“Sed idea est similitudo, non essentia rei” (I Sent. dist. 35, art. un., qu. 1, contra 3).
- 24“Item, idea non est necessaria nisi ad dirigendum in cognoscendo et regulandum in operando; sed nihil indiget dirigente vel regulante, nisi quod potest errare vel deviare. Deus autem nullum horum habet: ergo frustra ponuntur in Deo ideae” (I Sent. dist. 35, art. un., qu. 1, contra 4). [“Again, an idea is only necessary for directing in knowledge and regulating in operation. But nothing needs to be directed or regulated unless it is able to err and deviate. But God has none of those: therefore ideas are posited in God in vain”].
- 25Bonaventure will explicitly avail himself of the Anselmian conception of divinity in many places. For one such example, see Itin. 6.2.
- 26“Omne agens rationabiliter, non a casu vel ex necessitate, praecognoscit rem antequam sit; sed omnis cognoscens habet rem cognitam vel secundum veritatem vel secundum similitudinem; sed res, antequam sint, non possunt haberi a Deo secundum veritatem: ergo secundum similitudinem. Sed similitudo rei, per quam res cognoscitur et producitur, est idea: ergo etc.” (I Sent. dist. 35, art. un., qu. 1, arg. 2) [“Every agent acting rationally and not by chance or necessity foreknows the thing before it exists; but every knower has the thing known either according to truth or according to a likeness. But things are not able to be had by God in truth before they exist: therefore they are had according to a likeness. But a likeness of the thing, through which the thing is known and produced, is an idea. Therefore, etc.”].
- 27Reading “creaturarum” for “creatorum”.
- 28“Item, omne quod determinate ducit in alterum cognoscendum, habet penes se similitudinem cogniti, vel ipsum est eius similitudo; sed speculum aeternum mentes se videntium ducit in cognitionem omnium creat[ura]rum, sicut dicit Augustinus, quod rectius ibi cognoscunt quam alibi: ergo restat quod in eo resident similitudines. Et constat quod sunt in eo sicut in cognoscente, quia non tantum aliis repraesentat, sed sibi; sed haec est tota ratio ideae: ergo, etc.” (I Sent. dist. 35, art. un., qu. 1, arg. 3) [“Again, everything that leads determinately to the knowledge of another thing has within itself a likeness of the thing known, or is itself its likeness. But the eternal mirror leads the minds of the ones looking into it to knowledge of all creatures, as Augustine says, because they know more rightly there than elsewhere. Therefore it remains that likenesses reside in it. And it is clear that they are in it as in a knower, because it not only represents to others, but to itself. But this is the whole definition of an idea. Therefore, etc.”].
- 29A loose theological example would be the idea that all were able to sin in Adam because all were in some way in Adam, who was the cause of all future humans. Aristotle’s examples of efficient causality seem to satisfy the idea that the effect is somehow contained in the cause: An advisor is the cause of an action, a father of a child, a maker of the thing made (Metaphysics V.2, 1013a24 ff.). However, it is not part of the definition of efficient cause, and it seems that he allows for instances that would not be of this sort: the mover causing motion (a species of change), or the fact that the same thing is the cause of contraries, depending on whether it is present or absent (the absence of a steersman, which causes a shipwreck, is Aristotle’s example: a shipwreck is not contained in a steersman nor in his absence in a straightforward way) (Metaphysics V.2, 1013b11–16).
- 30“Item, quia res a Deo producuntur, ideo sunt in Deo tamquam in efficiente, et Deus verissime est efficiens; similiter, quia ab ipso finiuntur, ideo verissime est finis: ergo pari ratione, quia ab ipso cognoscuntur et exprimuntur, per se ipsum Deus verissime est exemplar. Sed exemplar non est, nisi in quo sunt rerum exemplatarum ideae: ergo etc.” (I Sent. dist. 35, art. un., qu. 1, arg. 4) [“Again, because things are produced by God, therefore they are in God as in the one effecting, and God is most truly efficient [cause]; similarly, because they are completed by him, therefore he is most truly end. Therefore, by equal reasoning, because they are known and expressed by him, God is, through his very self, most truly exemplar. But there is not an exemplar unless there is one in whom there are the ideas of the exemplified things. Therefore, etc.”].
- 31“Quidam enim dixerunt, quod Deus non cognoscit secundum rationem ideae, sed secundum rationem causae. Et ponunt simile: sicut si puncta cognosceret suam virtutem, cognosceret lineas et circumferentiam; similiter, si unitas haberet potentiam cognitivam, per quam converteret se super se, cognosceret omnes numeros. Per hunc modum dicunt in Deo esse. Quoniam enim Deus habet virtutem producendi omnia et cognoscit totam suam virtutem, ideo cognoscit omnia. Et hoc dicunt Dionysium sensisse, cum dixit, quod ‘non secundum ideam, sed secundum unam excellentiae causam cognoscit omnia’” (I Sent. dist. 35, art. un., qu. 1, resp.) [“For some say that God does not know according to the logic of an idea, but according to the logic of cause. And they offer a metaphor: just as, if a point were to know its power, it would know lines and the circumference, similarly, if unity were to have cognitive power, through which it were thinking on itself, it would know all numbers. They say that it is like this in God. For because God has the power of producing all things and knows his entire power, therefore he knows all things. And they say that Dionysius thought this, when he said that ‘he knows all things not according to an idea, but according to one cause of excellence’”].
- 32“Primum quidem, quia deus cognoscit non per collationem deveniendi a principio ad principiatum, sed simplici aspectu” (I Sent. dist. 35, art. un., qu. 1, resp.) [“First, indeed, because God does not know by a comparing of what comes from the beginning to what is begun, but by a simple gaze”].
- 33“Rursus, omnis cognoscens ideo distincte producit, quia distincte cognoscit, non e converso: ergo ratio producendi non est ratio cognoscendi” (I Sent. dist. 35, art. un., qu. 1, resp.) [“Again, every knower distinctly produces because he distinctly knows, not the opposite. Therefore the logic of producing is not the logic of knowing”].
- 34“Et iterum, aliqua cognoscit, quae ab ipso non sunt” (I Sent. dist. 35, art. un., qu. 1, resp.) [“And again, he knows some things which are not from him”]. What Bonaventure has in mind here is God’s knowledge of sin. This is discussed to some extent in DQKC, ([9], qu. 1), although that discussion leaves many questions. There is slightly more to be found in I Sent., dist. 38, art. un., qu. 1 and Brev., part 3, chap. 1. A full treatment of the question is outside the scope of the present study; it is sufficient to note that Bonaventure is consistent in maintaining that God is not the cause of evil and yet has knowledge of it, which is enough to defeat the type of knowledge he is arguing against here.
- 35“Ideo est alia positio, et secundum Sanctos, et secundum philosophos, quod Deus cognoscit per ideas et habet in se rationes et similitudines rerum, quas cognoscit, in quibus non tantum ipse cognoscit, sed etiam aspicientes in eum: et has rationes vocat Augustinus ideas et causas primordiales” (I Sent. dist. 35, art. un., qu. 1, resp.) [“Therefore there is another position, both according the Saints and according to philosophers, that God knows through ideas and has the reasons and likenesses of the things that he knows in himself. Not only does he know in these likenesses, but also those gazing into him know by means of them; and Augustine calls these reasons ideas and primordial causes.”].
- 36“omne cognoscens, in quantum huiusmodi, simile est cognoscibili” (I Sent. dist. 35, art. un., qu. 1, resp.) [“Every knower, as such, is similar to the thing known”]. Cf. Etienne Gilson: “It is a resemblance, a sort of copy formed by the intelligence in imitation of the object which it knows, and which is, as it were, its double. This character of resemblance is as rigourously inseparable from knowledge as its character of productivity. All knowledge indeed is, in the strict sense of the term, an assimilation. The act by which an intelligence possesses itself of an object to apprehend its nature implies that this intelligence likens itself to the object, that for the moment it clothes itself with its form, and it is because it can in some way become everything that it can also know everything. It is clear then that, if every act of knowing engenders something, this something can only be a resemblance” [17].
- 37“ergo habet [Deus] eius similitudinem, vel ipse est similitudo” (I Sent. dist. 35, art. un., qu. 1, resp.).
- 38Bonaventure’s express denial of a likeness caused by the object in God says: “dicendum quod est similitudo causata a veritate rei extra, et de hac verum est, quod nunquam ita perfecte exprimit rem, sicut ipsa res, si praesentialiter esset apud animam; et hac similitudine non cognoscit Deus” (I Sent. dist. 35, art. un., qu. 1, ad 3) [“It must be said that there is a likeness caused by the external truth of the thing, and concerning this likeness it is true that it never expresses a thing so perfectly as the thing itself, provided that the thing is presently in the soul. And God does not know by means of this kind of likeness.”] Further, the thing could not cause knowledge of itself before it existed, so God could only know things after they had come to be: “sed omnis cognoscens habet rem cognitam vel secundum veritatem vel secundum similitatem; sed res, antequam sint, non possunt haberi a Deo secundum veritatem: ergo secundum similitudinem” (I Sent. dist. 35, art. un., qu. 1, arg. 2) [“but every knower possesses the thing known either in truth or in likeness. But things, before they exist, are not able to be had by God in truth; therefore in likeness.”].
- 39As previously noted above (p. 4), this premise is borrowed from the third objection. In addition on this point, cf. Hex. col. 12, no. 13: “accidentium substantialiter, quia illae rationes sunt substantia, quae est Deus.” [“[it represents] accidents substantially, since those reasons are substance, which is God.”] [6].
- 40Simplicity (conceived under the concept unity) is very operative in this article, even if it is not thematized. In question 2 we read: “ergo cum Deus sit exemplar, in quo est omnimode status, est ergo in Deus summa unitas” (I Sent. dist. 35, art. un., qu. 2, contra 3) [“therefore since God is the exemplar in which there is complete rest, there is in God the highest unity”]. That omnimode status is important, for where there is motion, there is heterogeneity, there is less perfect and more perfect. This becomes, then, a statement about the fullness and completeness of the exemplar. For Bonaventure, this amounts to an affirmation of the consubstantiality of the Father and the Son. Further, it affirms that the divine essence has been fully expressed in the exemplar, which must then be perfectly simple if it is to reflect the full range of created realia and possibilia.
- 41“Omnes enim rationes exemplares concipiuntur ab aeterno in vulva aeternae sapientiae seu utero” [6].
- 42“Est alia similitudo, quae est ipsa veritas expressiva cogniti et eo similitudo, quo veritas; et haec similitudo melius exprimit rem, quam ipsa res se ipsam exprimat, quia res ipse accipit rationem expressionis ab illa” (I Sent. dist. 35, art. un., qu. 1, ad 3). W. Norris Clarke argues that it is not correct to say that the thing exists more truly in God than in itself, only that it is expressed more truly in God than in itself: “Clearly Thomas Aquinas cannot hold this as a metaphysical doctrine—and not even Bonaventure, if he is to remain consistent with his text quoted above. For if, as I am present in the mind of God, I do not yet possess any slightest trace of my own intrinsic act of esse, in proportion to which alone is measured all my real participation in the perfection of God, then it cannot be literally asserted that I exist, have my true being, in a higher and more perfect state in God’s idea of me than in my own contingent created existence in myself. It is true that my intelligibility, the intelligible content of the divine idea of me, exists in a higher, more perfect way in God than in me; but this is still not my true being, my esse” [18]. But these are not the terms of Bonaventure’s own discussion, who does not speak of real participation being measured in proportion to an intrinsic act of esse, but rather in proportion to expression: “Omnia enim vera sunt et nata sunt se exprimere per expressionem illius summi luminis; quod si cessaret influere, cetera desineret esse vera. Ideo nulla veritas creata est vera per essentiam, sed per participationem” (I Sent. dist. 8, part 1, art. 1, qu. 1, ad 4-7) [“therefore all things are true and were born to express themselves through the expression of that highest light because of which, if it were to cease to flow into them, they would cease to be true. Therefore no created truth is true by essence, but by participation.”] Ewert Cousins directly contradicts Clarke’s claim: “Not only do things exist actually in their divine exemplars, but they have their greatest reality there. Hence we know them most truly when we know them in the divine mind” [19]. At the very least an insistence must be pressed that to speak of intrinsic acts of esse is to invite misinterpretation of the Seraphic Doctor and to have already begun to reinterpret him in light of the Angelic Doctor.
- 43“To gain a better understanding of this question and of the objections, it must be noted that a likeness may be of two different types. The first type is found when two beings participate in a third reality in such a way that we can say ‘a likeness is the same quality present in different beings.’ But there is a likeness in another sense when one being resembles another. And this can be of two types. One is a likeness of imitation. This is seen in the way in which a creature is a likeness of the Creator. Then there is an exemplary likeness. This is found in the way in which the exemplary Idea in the Creator is a likeness of the creature. In both ways, both as imitation and as exemplary Idea, the likeness of which we speak is both expressing and expressive. And it is this sort of likeness that is required for any knowledge of reality” ([9], qu. 2, resp., p. 90).
- 44“Now, there is a knowledge that causes things to be and a knowledge that is caused by things. That knowledge which is caused by things requires a likeness of imitation. Such a likeness is received from outside and therefore involves a sort of composition or addition in the knowing intellect. Hence, it involves some degree of imperfection. But the knowledge which causes things to be requires an exemplary likeness. Such a likeness does not come from outside. Hence, it implies neither composition nor any imperfection, but only absolute perfection. But the divine intellect is the supreme light, the full truth, and pure act. So, as the divine power to produce things is sufficient in itself to produce everything, so the divine light and truth is sufficient in itself to express all things. And since this expression is an intrinsic act, it is eternal. Because an expression is a form of assimilation, the divine intellect—expressing all things eternally in its supreme truth—possesses from eternity the exemplary Ideas of all creatures.” ([9], qu. 2, resp., pp. 90–91).
- 45See Bonaventure, 1 Sent. dist. 26, art. 1, qu. 2, resp.
- 46For an excellent study of the high Scholastic understanding of relations, see [20].
- 47“Therefore, it must be said that the exemplary causes in God are many, not really but only conceptually and by virtue of something found not only in the subject knowing but also in the object known” ([9], qu. 3, resp., p. 106).
- 48Certitude here is not just a matter of feeling certain, but actually coming to necessary conclusions that cannot be wrong.
- 49“The nobility of knowledge requires it, I say, because there can be no certain knowledge except where there is immutability on the part of the object known and infallibility on the part of the knower” ([9], qu. 4, resp., p. 135).
- 50“For a creature is related to God as a vestige, as an image, and as a likeness. In as far as it is a vestige, it is related to God as to its principle. In as far as it is an image, it is related to God as to its object. But in as far as it is a likeness, it is related to God as to an infused gift. And, therefore, every creature that proceeds from God is a vestige. Every creature that knows God is an image. In every creature in whom God dwells, and only such a creature, is a likeness. There are three levels of divine cooperation corresponding to these three degrees of relationship” ([9], qu. 4, resp., pp. 135–36).
- 51“In any work accomplished by a creature in as far as it is a vestige, God cooperates as the creative principle. In any work accomplished by a creature in as far as it is a likeness—such as a work that is meritorious and pleasing to God—God cooperates in the manner of an infused gift. But in a work that proceeds from a creature in as far as it is an image, God cooperates as the moving cause” ([9], qu. 4, resp., p. 136).
- 52“Since certain knowledge pertains to the rational spirit in as far as it is an image of God, it is in this sort of knowledge that the soul attains to the eternal reasons. But because it is never fully conformed to God in this life, it does not attain to the reasons clearly, fully, and distinctly, but only to a greater or lesser degree according to the degree of its conformity to God” ([9], qu. 4, resp., p. 136).
- 53“Since, in the state of innocence, the image existed without the deformity of guilt but did not yet have the full deiformity of glory, it attained to them ‘in part’ but not ‘obscurely.’ In the state of fallen nature, the image is both deformed and lacking in deiformity. Therefore, it attains to them ‘in part’ and ‘obscurely.’ In the state of glory it lacks every deformity and it possesses its full conformity to God. Here, therefore, it attains to them in their fullness and clarity” ([9], qu. 4, resp., p. 136). Cf. ([17], p. 403). The introduction of deiformity, a favorite concept for Bonaventure, signals that, like Augustine, the conceptuality is becoming increasingly participatory. At this point in this text, it is merely mentioned and not expounded upon, but it will play an ever larger role in the remaining questions of DQKC.
- 54“Haec est tota nostra metaphysica: de emanatione, de exemplaritate, de consummatione” (Hex. col. 1, no. 17) [6] [“This is our whole metaphysics: concerning emanation, exemplarity, and consummation”].
© 2016 by the author; licensee MDPI, Basel, Switzerland. This article is an open access article distributed under the terms and conditions of the Creative Commons Attribution (CC-BY) license (http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/).
Share and Cite
Johnson, J. The One and the Many in Bonaventure Exemplarity Explained. Religions 2016, 7, 144. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel7120144
Johnson J. The One and the Many in Bonaventure Exemplarity Explained. Religions. 2016; 7(12):144. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel7120144
Chicago/Turabian StyleJohnson, Junius. 2016. "The One and the Many in Bonaventure Exemplarity Explained" Religions 7, no. 12: 144. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel7120144
APA StyleJohnson, J. (2016). The One and the Many in Bonaventure Exemplarity Explained. Religions, 7(12), 144. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel7120144