1. Introduction
Bargaining sets, cores, and competitive equilibria are important solutions for economies and games. In 1954, Arrow and Debreu [
1] established the celebrated existence theorem of competitive (Walrasian) equilibria in finite exchange economies and some special finite production economies under a set of assumptions. Since then, the existence of competitive equilibrium for different economies under various assumptions has been studied extensively in the literature, including those for finite economies by Bewley [
2], Mas-Colell [
3], and Podczeck and Yannelis [
4], and those for continuum economies by Aumann [
5], Hildenbrand [
6], and Sondermann [
7].
While competitive equilibrium outcomes are in the core, in general, the core is larger than the set of equilibrium allocations in a finite economy. The question of the relationship of the core of an economy to the set of competitive equilibrium allocations originates with Edgeworth’s conjecture that, if an economy were replicated, the core of an economy would shrink to the set of competitive equilibrium allocations. In 1963, Debreu and Scarf [
8] gave a rigorous treatment of Edgeworth’s conjecture. Aumann [
9] proved a remarkable result that the core and the set of competitive allocations coincide in an exchange economy with a continuum (infinite many) of traders under some standard assumptions, and Rustichini and Yannelis [
10] extended Aumann’s result to the setting where the commodity space is an ordered separable Banach space. In 1989, Mas-Colell [
11] extended Aumann’s result by proving the following well-known fact: The bargaining set and the set of competitive allocations coincide in an exchange economy with a continuum of traders under some standard assumptions. This result is extended to coalition production economies with a continuum of traders and finite-dimensional Euclidean commodity spaces by Liu and Zhang [
12].
For a finite economy, it is well-known that the set of competitive allocations could be a strict subset of the core which can also be a strict subset of the bargaining set. In 1979, Aubin [
13] introduced the notion of fuzzy core (see also [
14,
15]) for an exchange economy by using fuzzy coalitions which allow agents to participate in a coalition with any level between 0 and 100 percentage, and proved that the fuzzy core and the set of competitive equilibrium allocations coincide in a finite exchange economy. Using Aubin’s veto mechanism [
16] through fuzzy coalitions, Herv
s-Est
vez and Moreno-Garc
a [
17] and Liu [
18] proved that the fuzzy (Aubin) bargaining set coincides with the set of competitive allocations in a finite economy with a finite-dimensional Euclidean commodity space under standard assumptions.
In this paper, we establish the equivalence of the fuzzy core, the fuzzy bargaining set, and the set of competitive allocations in a finite coalition production economy with an infinite-dimensional commodity space under some standard assumptions. We first derive a continuous equivalence theorem and then discretize it to obtain the desired equivalence in finite economies. Our equivalence theorem is built on a general model—coalition production economies with separable Banach spaces as commodity spaces and thus includes many of the corresponding existing equivalence theorems in the literature. Studying the equivalence of the set of competitive allocations, the fuzzy core, and the fuzzy bargaining set is useful as the existence of any of them implies the existence of the others if they are equivalent, and Liu [
19] established the non-emptiness (existence) of the fuzzy core in a finite production economy with infinite-dimensional commodity space.
We conclude this section with the following remark: Equilibrium analysis in the infinite-dimensional setting differs in important ways from equilibrium analysis in the finite dimensional setting as noted by Zame [
20]. For example, while Aumann proved that the core and the set of competitive allocations coincide in exchange economies with a continuum of traders and a finite-dimensional Euclidean commodity space, Podczeck [
21] and Tourky and Yannelis [
22] showed that the core and the set of competitive allocations are not equivalent in an atomless exchange economy with a continuum of traders and a non-separable Banach space as commodity space.
2. The Equivalence between the Set of Competitive Allocations and the Bargaining Set in a Continuum Economy
A Banach space is a complete normed vector space and note that a separable Banach space is a locally convex Hausdorff space. Given a Banach space , its dual is the set of continuous linear functionals . Throughout this paper, we shall let be a separable Banach space such that the positive cone is closed and convex and has an interior point. We assume that is equipped with a reflexive, transitive, anti-symmetric order relation ≤ such that (1) if and , then (2) if and , then (3) implies . By , we mean that and . We define the positive cone and the dual cone of to be .
The following concepts for continuum coalition production economies with infinite dimensional commodity spaces are natural extensions of those corresponding concepts for continuum economies with finite-dimensional commodity space
(see [
6,
9,
12]). For a continuum economy, the set of agents is the closed interval
, denoted by
T, such that
forms an atomless measure space, where
is Lebesgue measure. Let
be a measurable consumption correspondence, where
is interpreted as the consumption set of agent
. We use
to denote the set of all coalitions which are all nonnull Lebesgue measurable subsets of
T, all integrals are Bochner integrals (see [
10] for the definition) taken with respect to Lebesgue measure
, and we use notation
instead of
for convenience.
A
coalition production economy with a continuum of agents and an infinite-dimensional commodity space is
where each
is the production set of the firm (coalition)
with
being the total production set,
is player
t’s endowment vector which is Bochner integrable, and
is the profit distribution function for the total production set
Y such that
and
is continuous with respect to
p, where each agent
t receives profit share
from the total profit
at production
and price vector
p.
Definition 1. A (feasible) allocation
(or “trade") for a continuum economy is a Bochner integrable assignment for which An allocation blocks an allocation via a coalition S if for each and Definition 2. The core of a production economy with a continuum of agents is the set of all (feasible) allocations that are not blocked via any nonnull coalition.
For a continuum coalition production economy, the following assumptions are standard.
(II.1) For every , is convex and closed containing 0, weakly compact, integrably bounded, and is Bochner integrable.
(II.2) Desirability (o f the commodities): implies .
(II.3) Continuity (o f the commodities): For each , the sets and are open (relative to ) for a.e. .
(II.4) Measurability: If and are assignments, then the set is Lebesgue measurable in T.
(II.5) is irreflexive and transitive for all .
We remark here that assumptions (II.2)–(II.5) are standard assumptions as in Aumann [
9], and assumption (II.1) similar to that in [
23].
For convenience, denote
by
. The following concept of competitive equilibrium for a continuum production economy is given in [
6,
12], with commodity space being a separable Banach space and the price system being the unit ball
which is compact with respect to weak
topology on
by the well-known Banach—Alaoglu Theorem.
Definition 3. A competitive equilibrium (Walrasian equilibrium) of a continuum economy consists of a price system , a feasible allocation , and a production such that
(i) ;
(ii) and for any coalition , ;
(iii) for almost every (a.e.) trader t, is maximal with respect to in t’s that is, for almost every ,
We make the following assumptions on the production sets and price systems:
(P.1) is a closed, convex, and weakly compact subset of containing 0 and for each .
(P.2) For each
and any coalition
,
(P.3) The wealth map is joint continuous (i.e., continuous with respect to and ).
Remark 1. We remark that assumption (P.2) holds for a coalition production economy with a continuum of agents satisfying that is a closed convex cone of with vertex 0 for each : In fact, we must have for any and for any price vector . Otherwise, if for some , then for any as the production set is a convex cone and the profit approaches positive infinity as c approaches the positive infinity, which is impossible. For each , since , it follows that for any . Thus, assumption (P.2) holds.
The next fact for a coalition production economy with a continuum of agents and an infinite-dimensional commodity space can be proved easily similar to Theorem 2.3 in [
24].
Lemma 1. Any competitive allocation belongs to the core in a coalition production economy with a continuum of agents and an infinite-dimensional commodity space.
The following concepts of objections, counterobjections, and bargaining sets are natural extensions of the corresponding concepts for exchange economies given by Mas-Colell [
11].
Definition 4. An objection to the allocation is a pair , where and is an allocation such that
(a)
(b) for a.e. and .
Definition 5. Let be an objection to the allocation . A counterobjection to is a pair , where and is an allocation such that
(a)
(b) ,
(c) for a.e. and for a.e. .
Definition 6. An objection is said to be justified if there is no counterobjection to it. The bargaining set of the economy is the set of all allocations which have no justified objection.
Clearly, the core of the economy
is contained in the bargaining set
. In 1989, Mas-Colell [
11] proved that following well-known result.
Theorem 1 (Mas-Colell, 1989). For an exchange economy with a continuum of traders and a commodity space satisfying assumptions (II.1)–(II.4), the bargaining set coincides with the set of competitive allocations.
The following theorem generalizes Theorem 1 in two main aspects: exchange economies are extended to coalition production economies and commodity spaces are extended from Euclidean spaces to separable Banach spaces.
Theorem 2. Let be a coalition production economy with a continuum of agents and commodity space , where is an ordered separable Banach space. If satisfies assumptions (II.1)–(II.5) and (P.1)–(P.3), then its bargaining set coincides with its set of competitive allocations.
We postpone the proof for Theorem 2 to
Section 4.
3. Fuzzy Cores, Fuzzy Bargaining Sets, and Competitive Equilibria of Finite Economies
Throughout this paper, we let be an ordered separable Banach space such that the positive cone is closed convex and has an interior point. In this section, we will establish the equivalence of the set of competitive allocations, the fuzzy core, and the fuzzy bargaining set in a finite coalition production economy with infinite-dimensional commodity space.
We first recall the following concept of a finite coalition production economy and some necessary preliminaries from the literature. For simplicity, we assume that the preference orderings are representable by real valued concave continuous utility functions
, which can be used to approximate rather general preference relations according to Section 4.6 in Debreu [
25]. Let
be the set of
n agents and denote by
the set of all nonempty subsets (coalitions) of
N.
A
coalition production economy with
n agents is
which consists of a collection of the commodity space
, agents’ characteristics
, and coalitions’ production sets
. The triple
is agent
i’s characteristics as a consumer:
is his consumption set,
is his utility function, and
is his endowment vector. The set
is the production set of the firm (coalition)
S for which every agent
works and
consists of all production plans that can be achieved through a joint action by the members of
S. We use
for the total production possibility set of the economy. For convenience, we simply call
an economy.
An exchange economy is a special coalition production economy with for all .
For each
, the set
of
S-allocations is
The set of all (feasible) allocations of the economy
is
which is assumed to be nonempty and compact.
We make the following assumptions on consumption sets, utility functions, and the sets of allocations:
(A.1) For every agent , is a closed convex subset of containing 0 and (where stands for the interior of A).
(A.2) Desirability (o f the commodities): implies .
(A.3) For each
,
is continuous and strongly convex (i.e., for all
and
such that
and
, and for all
with
,
(A.4) The set of all (feasible) allocations is nonempty and compact.
Note that, for each , if and only if , and implies that .
Definition 7. By a price (or price system ), we shall mean a continuous linear functional (see (3)), and we denote the value of p at the vector x by .
One can think as the profit at price p and production x and view the map as the wealth map.
We make the following assumption on the production sets and the wealth map:
(P.1) is a closed convex cone with the vertex at the origin in and for each .
(P.2) The wealth map is joint continuous (i.e., continuous with respect to and ).
Note that assumption (P.1) implies the following common assumptions: (1)
for all
(exchange economy, see [
9,
11,
26]); (2)
Y is a closed convex cone with vertex at the origin and
for each
(see [
8]).
Remark 2. Similar to the remarked by [8], under assumption (P.1), we have for any , any and for any price vector provided . For otherwise, if for some , then for any as the production set is a convex cone and the profit approaches the positive infinity as c approaches to the positive infinity, which is impossible. For each , since , it follows that for any . The following concept of competitive equilibrium for an economy satisfying assumption (P.1) is a natural extension of the corresponding concept given in [
8,
18].
Definition 8. For an allocation and a price vector , the couple is a competitive equilibrium
of an economy if the profit is maximized on Y and for each , satisfies the preferences of the i-th consumer under the constraint that is, for each , We say that an allocation
in a coalition production economy
is blocked by a coalition
S if there is an attainable
S-allocation
such that
for all
with at least one of the inequalities being strict (see [
8]). The
core of an economy
is the set of all attainable allocations that cannot be blocked by any coalition. Recall from Aubin [
16] that a fuzzy coalition is a vector
with
for each
(where
is the participation level of agent
i). A crisp coalition
corresponds to a special fuzzy coalition
with
if
and
if
. The following fuzzy core concept is a refinement of the core for an economy (see Florenzano [
14]).
Definition 9. The fuzzy core of an economy is the set of all allocations which can not be blocked by any fuzzy coalition, where an allocation is blocked by a fuzzy coalition s, which means that there exists such that with , and for each with at least one of the inequalities being strict.
Clearly, the fuzzy core
is a subset of the core
in an economy
. The next standard fact is given in [
18] for coalition production economies with Euclidean commodity spaces, which works exactly the same for Banach spaces as commodity spaces.
Lemma 2. For an economy satisfying assumptions (A.2), (A.3), and (P.1), any competitive allocation of is in the fuzzy core of .
In 1989, Mas-Colell [
11] introduced the (Mas-Colell) bargaining set for exchange economies. Motivated by Aubin’s veto mechanism [
16], Herv
s-Est
vez and Moreno-Garc
a [
17] and Liu [
18] gave the following fuzzy extension of the corresponding concept for economies with Euclidean commodity spaces, which is stated in the setting of Banach spaces here.
Definition 10. A fuzzy objection to an allocation is a pair , where and is defined on S, for which there exist for each , such that
(a)
(b) for each with at least one of these inequalities being strict.
Definition 11. Let be a fuzzy objection to an allocation . A fuzzy counterobjection to is a pair , where and is defined on Q, for which there exist for each , such that
(a)
(b) for each and for each .
Definition 12. A fuzzy objection is said to be justified if there is no fuzzy counterobjection to it. The fuzzy (Aubin) bargaining set of an economy is the set of all allocations which have no justified Aubin objection.
When restricted to the crisp case, that is, for all and for all , we obtain the (Mas-Colell) bargaining set for the economy . Clearly, the fuzzy bargaining set is a subset of the bargaining set in an economy .
Note that it follows from the definitions that, in an economy , the core is a subset of the bargaining set and the fuzzy core is a subset of the fuzzy bargaining set . The fuzzy core of an economy can be viewed as a refinement to the core of the economy by allowing agents to cooperate at a different participation level (from 0 percent to 100 percent), thereby with more blocking power, the fuzzy bargaining set does the same to the bargaining set for an economy.
Given a finite economy
with
n agents satisfying assumption (P.1), we construct a special continuum economy
with
n types of distinct agents as follows: We divide the set
of agents into
n subintervals
for
and
, where all agents in
are identical to agent
i in the economy
, that is,
where
and
for all
; for any
and
,
if and only if
; for each coalition
(where
is the set of all measurable subsets of
T), define
, where
(thus,
) with
being Lebesgue measure and
for any
and any
.
For each allocation
, define the step function
by
Then,
is an allocation in
. In fact,
implies that
. By assumption (P.1),
which implies that
is an allocation in
by (4).
To prove our main theorem, we need the following lemma which is the Lemma together with its remark by Garc
a-Cutr
n and Herv
s-Beloso [
26].
Lemma 3 (Garc
a-Cutr
n and Herv
s-Beloso, [
26]).
Let ⪰ be a convex and continuous preference relation and be a Banach space. If has positive measure, is an integrable function and is such that (or ) for all , then In the next theorem, an allocation
in
yields an allocation
in
with
for
; and an allocation
in
gives rise to an allocation
in
with
for all
and
. The following proof is motivated by the proof of Theorem 1 from [
26].
Theorem 3. Let be a finite economy satisfying assumptions (A.3) and (P.1). Then, is a competitive equilibrium for if and only if is a competitive equilibrium for .
Proof. Let
is a competitive equilibrium for
. Then, we have
in
defined by
for all
and
. Since
Y is a cone by assumption (P.1),
implies
and so
is an allocation in
. By Remark 1, we have
. Moreover, we have
, and
implies
for each
. It follows that, for each
and for all
,
and
implies
, where
for all
, and so
Thus,
is a competitive equilibrium for
.
Conversely, let
be a competitive equilibrium for
. Then,
satisfies
for
. Since
Y is a cone by assumption (P.1),
implies that
Thus,
is an allocation for
. Since
by Remark 2,
. Thus, the profit is maximized on
Y at
for the economy
.
Next, we show that each
is in the budget set
. Since
is in the budget set
for all
, we have for each
,
and
To show that
is a competitive equilibrium for
, it suffices to show that, for
,
implies
. Let
and define
by setting
for all
. We claim that there exists
such that
. Suppose, otherwise, that
for all
. By assumption (A.3) and Lemma 3, we have
which implies
by the construction of
, contradicting
. Thus, the claim holds. Since
is a competitive equilibrium for
,
implies that
. Since
and
, it follows that
. Thus,
is a competitive equilibrium for
. □
It is well-known that, in a finite exchange economy, which is a special production economy with
for all
, the set of competitive allocations could be a proper subset of the core which can also be a proper subset of the bargaining set. Here, we will prove the following equivalence between the set of competitive allocations and the fuzzy bargaining set in a finite coalition production economy with infinite-dimensional commodity space which generalizes the equivalence theorems in [
17,
18]. The proof is similar to the proof of Theorem 4.5 in [
18], with major difficulties and complications caused by infinite-dimensional commodity spaces involved, much of the difficulties occurred in the proof of Theorem 2 given in
Section 4.
Theorem 4. Let be a finite economy satisfying assumptions (A.1)–(A.4), (P.1), and (P.2). Then, the set of competitive allocations and the fuzzy bargaining set coincide in .
Proof. First, by Remarks 1 and 2, it is easy to check that the assumptions (A.1)–(A.4), (P.1) and (P.2) in Theorem 4 imply assumptions (II.1)–(II.5) and (P.1)–(P.3) in Theorem 2. By Lemma 2 and the fact that the fuzzy core is a subset of the fuzzy bargaining set , we conclude that the set of competitive allocations of is a subset of the fuzzy bargaining set .
Similar to the proof of Theorem 4.5 in [
18], applying Lemma 3 and Theorems 2 and 3, one can show that the fuzzy bargaining set
is a subset of the set of competitive allocations of
. □
Since the set of competitive allocations is a subset of the fuzzy core which is a subset of the fuzzy bargaining set, Theorem 4 implies the next equivalence theorem immediately.
Theorem 5. Let be a finite economy satisfying assumptions (A.1)–(A.4), (P.1), and (P.2). Then, the set of competitive allocations and the fuzzy core coincide in .
Proof. By Lemma 2, the set of competitive allocations is a subset of the fuzzy core in . Recall that the fuzzy core is a subset of the fuzzy bargaining set in . It follows from Theorem 4 that we must have the set of competitive allocations, the fuzzy core, and the fuzzy bargaining set coincide in . □
The following example provides an economy which satisfies the assumptions in Theorems 4 and 5.
Example 1. Let be the exchange economy: , , , for any , for all and for all . Then, it is easy to check that satisfies assumptions (A.1)–(A.4), (P.1), and (P.2). Thus, Theorems 4 and 5 can be applied here.
4. Cores, Bargaining Sets, Competitive Allocations in Continuum Economies
In this section, we will prove Theorem 2 along the same line as the proof of Theorem 1 by Mas-Colell [
11] through competitive objections defined below, using an approach similar to the proof of the extension of Theorem 1 to continuum coalition production economies with finite-dimensional Euclidean commodity space
given in [
12]. Note that there are significant differences due to important structural differences between finite-dimensional Euclidean space
and infinite-dimensional Banach spaces.
Definition 13. The objection to the allocation is if there is a price system such that for a.e. :
(i) for satisfying , , with strict inequality if ;
(ii) for satisfying , , with strict inequality if .
Lemma 4. For a coalition production economy with a continuum of agents and commodity space satisfying assumptions (H.1), (II.1)–(II.5) and (P.1), every competitive objection to an allocation is justified.
Proof. Let
be the price vector associated with the competitive objection
. Then, we have
Suppose there is a counterobjection
to
. Then, there exists
such that
,
for a.e.
, and
for a.e.
.
By the definition of competitive objection, we have
It follows from Definition 9 (ii), (6) and (7) that
However, by (5), we have
a contradiction. Therefore, the objection
is justified. □
The next theorem is Theorem 6.2 in [
27].
Theorem 6 (Yannelis, 1991). Let be a finite atomless measure space, be a Banach space and be a correspondence. Then, is convex.
The following extension of Fatou’s lemma is Theorem 3.1 from [
28], where
is the set of the weak limit superior points of the sequence
of subsets in a Banach space
:
Theorem 7 (Yannelis, 1988).
Let be a complete finite atomless measure space and be a separable Banach space. Let ( be a sequence of nonempty closed valued correspondences such that for all n (, for all , where is an integrably bounded, weakly compact, nonempty, convex valued correspondence. Moreover, suppose that is closed and convex valued. Then, The next theorem extends the corresponding result by Aumann [
29] from Euclidean spaces to Banach spaces.
Theorem 8. Let be a complete finite separable measure space and be a separable Banach space. Let be a nonempty, closed, integrably bounded, weakly compact, convex valued correspondence having a measurable graph such that for each , is upper semicontinuous. Then, is upper semicontinuous.
Proof. To show that is upper semicontinuous, by the Closed Graph Theorem, we need to show that, if with all and with all , then . Since is closed, weakly compact, and convex valued, it can be proved that is closed and convex valued. It follows from Theorem 7 that , which implies that there exists a subsequence with all such that for a.e. . Since and is upper semicontinuous, we have . Thus, is upper semicontinuous. □
Note that a separable Banach space
is a complete metric space, and the following fact is Aumann’s Measurable Selection Theorem in [
16].
Theorem 9 (Aumann’s Measurable Selection Theorem, 1969). If is a complete finite measure space, has a measurable graph, and is separable, then F has a measurable selection. Moreover, if F is also integrably bounded, it admits a Bochner integrable selection.
The following remark is Remark 1 from [
23].
Remark 3. Let be a Banach space and u be an interior element of . Then, for any nonzero , .
The proof of the next lemma is along the same line as in [
12,
30], with major difficulties caused by infinite-dimensional Banach space. Recall that a well-known theorem by James [
31] states: A closed and bounded convex subset
C of a Banach space
is weakly compact if and only if every continuous linear functional defined on
attains its maximum value over
C, where weakly compact means compact with respect to the weak topology in a Banach space. The integral of a correspondence
F is defined by
The next lemma extends Lemma 3.9 in [
12] with a much more complicated proof.
Lemma 5. Let be a coalition production economy with a continuum of agents and commodity space satisfying assumptions (H.1), (II.1)–(II.5) and (P.1)–(P.3). If is an allocation which is not competitive in , then there is a competitive objection to .
Proof. Assume that is an allocation which is not competitive. We will construct a competitive objection to .
For convenience, we will use a continuous and quasi-concave function
to represent the preference relation
(it is a well-known fact that real valued continuous and quasi-concave utility functions can be used to approximate rather general preference relations arbitrarily closely). Recall that the budget set for agent
at each
(see (3)) is
Then, it is easy to see that the budget set
is closed. It follows that
is weakly compact for each
as
is weakly compact and
. By James’s Theorem, the continuous function
attains maximum on
for each
and every
. For all
and all
, define
Then, it is easy to see that
is convex and closed, and
is nonempty by James’s Theorem [
31] for any
and
. Thus,
is weakly compact. Since
is integrably bounded by assumption (II.1),
is integrably bounded. By Theorem 9, there exists a Bochner integrable selection
.
For each
, define
Then,
is closed and weakly compact as
is closed and weakly compact for each
and each
. Moreover, since
is integrable by assumption (II.1) and
has a Bochner integrable selection
, a Bochner integrable function in
exists.
Let
and
Then,
. By the measurability assumption (II.4), both
S and
are Lebesgue
-measurable. Since
is not competitive, we have
which implies
. We claim that, for any
,
In fact, suppose that, for
,
By the continuity assumption (II.3) and the fact that
is linear continuous, there exists
such that
and
which implies that
, contradicting the fact
. Thus, (9) holds.
Since
is weakly compact by assumption (P.1
), it follows from James’s Theorem [
31] that, for each
, there exists
such that
. For each
, let
and define
Then,
is nonempty for every
as there exists a Bochner integrable function in
and
. Since
is closed and
is jointly continuous by assumption (P.3
), it is easy to see that
is closed. Thus,
is closed as
is closed. By Theorem 6,
is convex. Moreover, by a standard argument and using assumption (P.3
), one can check that
is upper semicontinuous. It follows from Theorem 8 that
is upper semicontinuous on
.
We claim that
for any
and any
. Let
. Since
, we have
for each
. It follows that, for any
, there exists Bochner integrable
and
such that
By the definition of
, for any
, we have either
or
, which implies that
for
and
for a.e.
. It follows from assumption (P.2
) that
Thus, the claim holds.
By the Banach extension of the celebrated Gale–Nikaido–Debreu Lemma in Debreu [
25] (5.6, (1) ), there exist
and
such that
. It follows that there exists a Bochner integrable function
for all
and
such that
Recall that
for
. It follows from (10) that
Let
Since
, we have
and so
. It follows from (8) that
We now show that
is a competitive objection. Since
, we have
for all
. Note that
. It follows from (10) that
Moreover, since
for all
,
and so
is an allocation satisfying condition (a) in Definition 10. Since
for all
, it follows from the desirability assumption (II.2) and the definition for
S that
for all
. Together with the fact
(see (8)), we have that
satisfies condition (b) in Definition 10 and so
is an objection.
Now, we claim that, for each
and
,
For otherwise, suppose that
and
. Then, it follows from assumption (II.3) that there exists
such that
and
, contradicting
. Thus, (13) holds. Next, we show that for each
and
,
implies
. Suppose that for some
,
but
. Then,
by (14). Since
is convex containing 0,
implies that
for any
. By assumption (II.3), we can choose
so that
. By (13), we have
. Since
is an interior point of
, by Remark 3,
. Since
by assumption (P.1
),
and so
. It follows that
, a contradiction. Thus,
implies
for each
.
Similarly, we claim that, for any
and
,
In fact, suppose that
but
for some
and
. By the definition of
S,
and
. Thus,
. Since
, by assumptions (II.3) and (P.3
), there exists
such that
and
which implies
. It follows from the definition of
that
, contradicting the fact
. Thus, (4.10) holds. Moreover, similar to the argument in the previous paragraph, we have
implies
for each
. Therefore,
is a competitive objection. □
Proof of Theorem 2. By Lemma 1 and the fact that the core of an economy is contained in its bargaining set , we have that the set of competitive allocations is a subset of the bargaining set . On the other hand, by Lemmas 4 and 5, the bargaining set is contained in the set of competitive allocations of . Thus, the set of competitive allocations coincides with the bargaining set in economy . □
Since, for a continuum coalition production economy , the set of competitive equilibria is contained in its core by Lemma 2, and the core is contained in its bargaining set, Theorem 2 implies immediately the next fact.
Theorem 10. Let be a coalition production economy with a continuum of agents and commodity space . If satisfies assumptions (II.1)–(II.5) and (P.1)–(P.3), then its core coincides with its set of competitive allocations.
Recall that an exchange economy is a special coalition production economy with
for every coalition
, Theorem 10 implies the following results for exchange economies with a continuum of traders, which implies the corresponding results by Aumann [
9] (for exchange economies with
) and by Rustichini and Yannelis [
10] (for exchange economies with
).
Theorem 11. For an exchange economy with a continuum of traders and commodity space satisfying assumptions (II.1)–(II.5) and (P.3), the core coincides with the set of competitive allocations.
Proof. An exchange economy is a special coalition production economy with for every coalition , which clearly satisfies assumptions (P.1) and (P.2). Theorem 11 follows directly from Theorem 10. □