1. Introduction
A commutative residuated lattice is defined as an algebra of type satisfying the following conditions: is a lattice; is a commutative monoid with identity e; and , where ≤ is the lattice ordering.
Sometimes, commutative residuated lattices are also called commutative residuated lattice-ordered monoids and abbreviated by CRLs. It is well known that holds if and only if ≤ is compatible with · and for all contains a greatest element (denoted by .
A
CRL is called
idempotent if for all
,
; is called
integral if for all
,
; is called
totally ordered if for all
,
or
; is called
semilinear when it is a subdirect product of totally ordered
CRLs; and is called
conic if for all
,
or
(see [
1,
2,
3,
4]). A semilinear idempotent
CRL is said to be an odd Sugihara monoid if for all
,
. An integral idempotent
CRL is said to be a
Brouwerian algebra if for all
,
. As in [
4], a
CRL is called
semiconic when it is a subdirect product of conic
CRLs.
Ward and Dilworth were the first to study a class of algebra as a generalization of ideal lattices of rings in [
5], which we call commutative residuated lattices.
CRLs play an important role in the study of algebraic logic, as they provide an algebraic semantics for substructural logics (see [
6]). The multitude of different types of
CRLs makes the investigation rather complicated, and at the present moment, large classes of
CRLs lack a structural description. The study of constructions is very important in enhancing our understanding of
CRLs and, as a result, of substructural logics. Hart, Rafter and Tsinakis were the first to study the structure theory of
CRLs in [
7]. In [
8], the authors extend the main results of [
7] to the non-commutative case. More recently, there has been substantial research regarding the structure of some specific classes of
CRLs, see, for example, [
9,
10,
11,
12]. Idempotent
CRLs form an important tool both in algebra and logic (see [
6]). Among them, semiconic ones make a valuable contribution because they include several important algebraic counterparts of substructural logics (see [
13]). Recently, algebra properties for semiconic
CRLs have been given by many authors (see [
1,
2,
4,
6,
14,
15,
16,
17,
18,
19]). In [
20], the authors obtain a structure theorem for semilinear idempotent
CRLs. In this paper, we will study the construction of semiconic idempotent
CRLs. From the semigroup algebraic perspective, idempotent
CRLs are indeed ordered semigroups (for ordered semigroups, see [
21]). The natural partial order plays an important role in the investigation of semigroups (see [
22,
23]). We will make use of the natural partial order to obtain some important properties and then establish a structure theorem of semiconic idempotent
CRLs, which generalizes the main result of [
20].
We proceed as follows: in
Section 2, we present some definitions and facts used in the sequel. In
Section 3, we obtain some properties of semiconic idempotent
CRLs. In
Section 4, we give a structure theorem for semiconic idempotent
CRLs, which generalizes the main result of [
20]. In
Section 5, we prove that the variety of strongly semiconic idempotent
CRLs has the amalgamation property, which generalizes the main result of [
10].
3. Some Properties
To begin with, we obtain some properties of conic idempotent commutative lattice-ordered monoids.
Now let
be a conic idempotent commutative lattice-ordered monoid. Since the monoid reduct of
is an idempotent commutative monoid, we define the
natural partial order on
as follows: for
,
It is clear that is a semilattice. For , [resp. ] means that a and b are incomparable under ≤ [resp. ], and [resp. ] means that [resp. ]. For any , [resp. ] implies either or . Let and if it exists in .
Proposition 1. Let be a conic idempotent commutative lattice-ordered monoid. The following statements are true for :
- (1)
If , then if and only if .
- (2)
If , then if and only if .
- (3)
if and only if .
- (4)
If and , then .
- (5)
If and , then .
Proof. Let be such that . Then, by Lemma 1(3),
This is similar to .
If , then since is conic, or . If , then by , is impossible. Thus, . Similarly, if , then . Conversely, let such that . Suppose that or . Then, since is conic, by Lemma 1(4,5), or , which implies that or , a contradiction. Hence, or . Thus, by (1) and (2), .
Let such that and . Then, by Lemma 1(3), . Let such that and . Then, and , so . Thus, . Since and ,
Let such that and . Then, by Lemma 1(2), . So by (2), and . Let such that and . Then, and , so . Thus, . Therefore, . □
Secondly, we obtain some properties of conic idempotent CRLs.
Proposition 2. Let be a conic idempotent . The following statements are true for :
- (1)
If , then and .
- (2)
If and , then .
- (3)
If , then and .
- (4)
If and , then .
- (5)
If and , then and
Proof. Let such that . Then, , and so . Since by Lemma 2(4), by Lemma 1(5), which implies that Since by Lemma 3(2), , by Proposition 1(3), .
Let such that and . Then, , and so . Suppose that . Then, since by Lemma 3(4), , by Proposition 1(2), , contrary to . Thus,
This is similar to .
This is similar to .
Let such that and . Since , by (1), and Let such that and . Then, and , so by Lemma 2(1). Thus, . Therefore, Because , by Lemma 2(3). Suppose that Then, , so by , . But since , by Lemma 3(4), a contradiction. Thus, . □
Proposition 3 ([2]). Let be a conic idempotent , and let such that . If or , then or Let be a join-semilattice, and let such that for all . is said to be an upper pre-lattice when is not a lattice and is a lattice. Let be a lattice and . is said to be an upper pre-sublattice of if is an upper pre-lattice and there exists such that is a sublattice of . Similarly, we can define the lower pre-lattice and lower pre-sublattice.
Let be a conic idempotent CRL. We define the following sets: , , , , and . For every , let . By Lemma 3(4), for all . Since for all by Proposition 2(1,3) and Lemma 3(4), by Proposition 2(4). It follows that for all . Because and is a chain by Lemma 3(5), is a chain. It is clear that .
We have the following result, which generalizes ([
15] Theorem 3.2).
Theorem 1. Let be a conic idempotent .
- (1)
If , then if and only if .
- (2)
If , then if and only if . In addition, for all .
- (3)
If such that , then .
- (4)
If , then is a sublattice of and is a Brouwerian algebra, where is given by for all .
- (5)
If , then has a greatest element j and is either a sublattice of or an upper pre-sublattice of .
- (6)
If such that , and then .
- (7)
If and such that is an upper pre-sublattice of , then there exists such that in and is a sublattice of with a least element .
- (8)
If satisfies that , then is a sublattice of for all .
- (9)
If and , then .
- (10)
is finitely subdirectly irreducible if and only if is a finitely subdirectly irreducible Brouwerian algebra.
- (11)
is a totally ordered odd Sugihara monoid and subalgebra of , that we call its skeleton.
Proof. We only need to verify the necessity because the sufficiency is clear. Suppose that . Then, there exists such that . Thus, by Lemma 2(6), .
We only need to prove the sufficiency because the necessity is obvious. Suppose that . Since by assumption, by . Let . Then, by Proposition 2(1), . Let such that . Suppose that . If , then by Proposition 2(2), , a contradiction. If , then since , by Proposition 2(4), a contradiction. Consequently, .
It is obvious.
Let and let . Then, , which, together with by Lemmas 2(3) and 3(5), derives that , whence . If or , then or , and so , which implies that . If then by Proposition 2(5), , and so , which implies that . Thus, is a sublattice of . By (1), . Let . Then, . Thus, i is the greatest element of , and so is an integral idempotent commutative lattice-ordered monoid with an identity i. We can claim that for all . To prove this, we consider the following cases:
If , then by Lemma 3(3) and so .
If or , then by Proposition 3, or . So or by Lemma 3(1). Thus, , whence
We define for all . Thus, is a Brouwerian algebra.
Let . By similar arguments as in the proof of , j is the greatest element of and for all , so is a join-semilattice with a greatest element j. Suppose that is not a sublattice of . Then, there exists such that and Hence, and by Lemma 2(3). Let . Suppose that . Then, by Lemma 3(1), which is contrary to . Assume that . Then, by Lemma 2(3), which is contrary to . Thus, for all , Similarly, if such that then for all , It follows that . Therefore, is a sublattice of . Consequently, is an upper pre-sublattice.
Let such that and let , . If , then by , and . Suppose that . Then, , which is contrary to . Thus, by Lemma 3(2), whence . Conversely, if , then and . Suppose that . Then, , which is contrary to . Thus, . Similarly, .
Let and such that is an upper pre-sublattice of . Then, there exists such that and Let . Then, . Since , by . Let such that . Suppose that . Then, by , contrary to . Thus, in . We have . We claim that . Otherwise, if , then since , by (6) and so . It follows that . It is a contradiction. Thus, . Consequently, is a sublattice of with a least element .
Let and . Then, , and so . It follows that is a sublattice of .
Since and , by and . Then, and by Proposition 1(1–2). Suppose that . Then, . Conversely, assume that . We claim that . Otherwise if , then , which is contrary to . Consequently, by Lemma 3(4). By Proposition 2(1,3), and . Suppose that If , then , and so by Proposition 2(2), , which is contrary to . If , then , and so by Proposition 2(4), , which is contrary to . Consequently, .
Suppose that is finitely subdirectly irreducible, then e is join-irreducible in L. Since is a sublattice of , e is join-irreducible in , which implies that is finitely subdirectly irreducible. Conversely, is finitely subdirectly irreducible. Then, e is join-irreducible in . By (6), we have that for all and such that , which implies that e is join-irreducible in Thus, is finitely subdirectly irreducible.
By Lemma 3(5), is a totally ordered set, which implies that is a sublattice of . Let . If , then . If , then . If or , then by Lemma 1(4,5), . Thus, is closed with respect to multiplication. By Lemma 2(7), we have . Consequently, is a subalgebra of . By Lemma 2(6), . It follows that is a totally ordered odd Sugihara monoid. □
Theorem 2. Let be conic idempotent s and be a homomorphism between conic idempotent s.
- (1)
and for all .
- (2)
If such that is an upper pre-sublattice of and , then is an upper pre-sublattice of and there exists such that in and in .
Proof. Let . Then, there exists such that . Since f is a homomorphism, , which implies that . Let and . Then, , and so , which implies that . It follows that .
Since is an upper pre-sublattice of , by Theorem 1(4), and there exists such that . Let . By the proof of Theorem 1(7), in , and so in L. Hence, by Theorem 1(6). It follows that and by Theorem 1(2). We claim that . Otherwise, if , then , and so by Proposition 2(4), , which is contrary to . Thus, . We have and by (1). Suppose that . Then, , and so by Proposition 2(1,3), , which is contrary to . Consequently, . It follows that is an upper pre-sublattice of and by the proof of Theorem 1(7), in . □
4. The Construction Theorem
In this section, we shall show how to construct a conic idempotent and then prove that any conic idempotent is isomorphic to some conic idempotent constructed in this way.
To start with, we introduce some new concepts.
Definition 1. Let be a chain with a greatest element e. Let such that and for every pair such that . Let . Let be a family of pairwise disjoint nonempty posets indexed by J. is called a chain expansion system (abbreviated by -system) if the following conditions hold:
- (CE1)
If , then is a Brouwerian algebra with a greatest element i.
- (CE2)
If , then is either a lattice with a greatest element or an upper pre-lattice with a greatest element .
- (CE3)
If such that is an upper pre-lattice, then there exists such that in I.
Given a -system , put . Define a binary relation ≤ on the set L as follows. Let . in L if one of the following conditions is satisfied:
- (P1)
and .
- (P2)
and .
- (P3)
, and in I.
- (P4)
and .
Lemma 4. is a lattice.
Proof. Firstly, we prove that is a poset. Obviously, ≤ is reflexive. Next, we prove that ≤ is antisymmetric. To see this, let such that and . We consider four cases:
If , then by , and . Since is a poset, .
Suppose and . Then, since and , and , a contradiction. Thus, and is impossible.
By similar arguments as in the previous case, , and is impossible.
Similarly, either or is impossible.
Next, we prove that ≤ is transitive. Let , and be such that and . We consider four cases:
. Then, by , and . Since is a poset, . Thus, by , .
. If and , then , and so by , . If such that in I, then , and so by , . If and , then , and so by , .
. Then, by similar arguments as in the prior case, .
and . If , then and , and so , which implies that by . If and , then by , . If such that , then and in I by . Since is a chain, , and so by , .
We conclude , whence ≤ is transitive.
Finally, we will prove that for all , and exist in L. Let . We consider three cases:
If , then and in L.
If , then and in L.
If , then by the definition of ≤, . If , then since is a Brouwerian algebra, exists in . Let such that . If , then by , and , and so . Thus, by , . If , then since , either and or , which together with , derives that . It follows that in L. Similarly, in L. If , then is either a lattice or a pre-lattice by (CE2). If is a lattice or an upper pre-lattice and exists, then by similar arguments as in the prior case, and in L. If is an upper pre-lattice and does not exist, then by similar arguments in the prior case, in L. By (CE3), there exists such that in I. We claim that in L. Because is the greatest element of by , by . Let such that . Since is an upper pre-lattice and does not exist, , and so by , either or there exists such that and in I, which implies that either or such that . It follows that by . Thus, in L.
□
We define a multiplication ∘ on
L in the following ways: for
,
Lemma 5. is a conic lattice-ordered idempotent commutative monoid with identity e.
Proof. It is clear that and for .
Let . If , then since e is the greatest of I, , which together with e is the greatest element of by , derives that and . If , then , so and . Now, we will show that ∘ satisfies the associative law. Let . We consider the following cases:
If then and whence .
If
and
, then
and
It follows that .
If
then
and
However, .
If , then and whence .
Finally, we show that ≤ is compatible with ∘. Let be such that . We need only to prove that for every . Suppose that . We need to consider the following cases:
If , then by the definition of ∘, and . Since , .
If and , then and . The following subcases need be considered:
If , then , and so by the definition of ∘, and , whence .
If , then by the definition of ∘, and . It follows that .
If and , then by the definition of ∘, and , whence .
If and , then , so by the definition of ∘, and , whence .
If and , then since , in I by . The following subcases need be considered:
If , then by the definition of ∘, and , whence .
If , then by the definition of ∘, and . It follows that .
If , then by the definition of ∘, and , whence . □
We may define a binary operation → on
L in the following way: for
such that
,
We denote by the above .
Theorem 3. is a conic idempotent CRL.
Proof. We need only to prove that for all . Suppose that . We need to consider the following cases:
Case 1 and , or and . We need only to check the following subcases:
If and , then by the definition of ∘, . Let such that . If , then by , . If , then by , and by the definition of ∘, , which, together with , derives that . Thus, , whence .
If and , then by the definition of ∘ and , . Let such that . If , then by , . If , then by the definition of ∘, . Assume that . Then, by the definition of ∘, , so by , which is contrary to . Thus, , which implies that , and so by and .
Case 2 and , or and . We need only to check the following subcases:
If and , then by , and so by the definition of ∘, . Let such that . Suppose that . Then, by , and by the definition of ∘, , which implies that , a contradiction. Suppose that such that . Then, , which implies that , a contradiction. Thus, and , whence
If and , then by the definition of ∘, . Let such that . If , then by . If such that , then , and so by . If such that , then by the definition of ∘, .
Case 3 such that or . Then, by the definition of ∘ and , , which implies that . Let such that . Suppose that or such that . Then, by , and by the definition of ∘, , which implies that , a contradiction. If such that , then by . If such that , then by the definition of ∘, , which implies that , so by . Thus, .
Case 4 and , or and . We need only to check the following subcases:
If and , then by the definition of ∘, . Let such that . If , then by . If , then by the definition of ∘, .
If and , then by the definition of ∘, . Let such that . Suppose that . Then, by the definition of ∘, , a contradiction. If , then by the definition of ∘, , which together with , derives that .
Case 5 and , or and . We need only to check the following subcases:
If and , then by the definition of ∘ and , . Let such that . Suppose that . Then, , a contradiction. If , then by the definition of ∘, , which together with , derives that .
If and , then by the definition of ∘ and , . Let such that . Suppose that . Then, by the definition of ∘, , a contradiction. If , then by the definition of ∘, , which together with , derives that . Thus, , whence . □
Next we shall prove that any conic idempotent CRL is isomorphic to some . Suppose that is a conic idempotent CRL. Let , and . Let . By Proposition 2, for all , , so . If such that , then there exists such that and , so . Thus, .
Lemma 6. is a -system.
Proof. By Theorem 1(1–5,7), is a -system. □
Theorem 4. is equal to .
Proof. For convenience, we denote by the imposed ordering on . We need only to prove that for all and .
We now prove . Let . Assume that . We need to consider three cases:
If , then by Lemma 3(4), and by Theorem 1(6), , which, together with and , derives that by .
If then , which, together with and , derives that by Theorem 1(6). Thus, by , .
If and then by Lemma 3(4), and , so and , whence by ,
Thus,
Suppose that . We need to consider four cases:
If , then by .
If such that , then by Theorem 1(6), .
If such that , then by Theorem 1(6), .
If and , then by Lemma 3(4), and , so .
Thus, whence
It remains to be verified that for all . For this, we need to consider three cases:
If , then by Lemma 1(3), On the other hand, by the definition of ∘ and , , whence .
If then by similar arguments as in (1),
and .
If , then by Lemma 3(4) and by Lemma 2(3), which together with and derives by the definition of ∘. On the other hand, by Proposition 2(3). Hence, .
If , then by Lemma 3(4), and by Theorem 1(4), which, together with and , derives by the definition of Suppose that . Then, , so by Proposition 2(4), , a contradiction. Thus, by Lemma 1(4,5). Hence, .
□
By Theorem 4, we have the following result, which generalizes ([
20] Theorem 20).
Theorem 5. Let be a CRL. The following conditions are equivalent:
- (I)
is a subdirectly irreducible idempotent semiconic CRL.
- (II)
There exists a -system such that
is a nontrivial subdirectly irreducible Brouwerian algebra or , and there exists such that in I;
.
Proof. Let be a subdirectly irreducible semiconic idempotent CRL. Then, since semiconic idempotent CRL is the variety generated by conic idempotent CRLs, is conic. By Theorem 4, , where is a -system. Because is a subdirectly irreducible CRL, the set has a greatest element. Let . If , then , so by Theorem 1(4), is a nontrivial subdirectly irreducible Brouwerian algebra. If , then since , and , so , which implies that . On the other hand, by Proposition 2(1), , so . Thus, , whence by Theorem 1(1).
Conversely, let be a -system such that and . Then, by Theorem 3, is a conic idempotent CRL. If is a nontrivial subdirectly irreducible Brouwerian algebra, then exists, and so , which implies that is a subdirectly irreducible semiconic idempotent CRL. If and there exists such that , then by , , which implies that is a subdirectly irreducible semiconic idempotent CRL. □
5. The Amalgamation Property
In this section, we will use the structure theorem of conic idempotent
CRLs to give some new result about the amalgamation property of the variety of semiconic idempotent
CRLs, which generalizes the main results of [
10].
Let be a class of algebras. A span is a pair of embeddings between algebras . The class K is said to have the amalgamation property if for every span of K, there exists an amalgam and embeddings and such that .
Example 1. Let . We define an order relation on A by , see Figure 1a. We can define a multiplication operation on A by the following: for all ,and for all . Let . We define an order relation on B by , see Figure 1b. We can define a multiplication operation on B by for all and , and for all . Let . We define an order relation on C by , see Figure 1c. We can define a multiplication operation on C by for all and , and for all . We define a division operation on P by for all , where . It is easy to see that and are subdirectly irreducible semiconic idempotent→
CRLs. We define two maps as follows. ; and for . ; , for and . It is clear that and are embeddings of into respectively. We claim that there are no amalgams in where is the class of all conic idempotent CRLs. Suppose that there exists an amalgam and embeddings and such that . Then, and . Hence, by Theorem 2, in . But in . It is a contradiction. We conclude that the span has no amalgam in . An immediate consequence of Example 1 is the following.
Proposition 4. The class of all conic idempotent CRLs and the class of subdirectly irreducible semiconic idempotent CRLs do not have the amalgamation property.
Proof. By Example 1, there exists a span of (subdirectly irreducible) conic idempotent CRLs such that it has no amalgam in the class of all (subdirectly irreducible) conic idempotent CRLs. It follows that the class of all conic idempotent CRLs and the class of subdirectly irreducible semiconic idempotent CRLs do not have the amalgamation property. □
We introduce the following concept.
Definition 2. The variety of strongly semiconic idempotent CRLs consists of the semiconic idempotent CRLs that satisfy
A consequence of Theorem 1 is the following.
Proposition 5. A conic idempotent CRL is a strongly semiconic idempotent CRL if and only if is a lattice for all .
Proof. Let be a conic idempotent CRL. Suppose that is a strongly semiconic idempotent CRL. Then, satisfies Hence, by Theorem 1(4,8), is a sublattice of CRL for all , and so is a lattice for all . Conversely, suppose that is a lattice for all . Let . If , then by Lemma 2(3), , so . Similarly, if , then . If , then by Lemma 3(1), , so . Hence, there exists such that . Since is a lattice, by Theorem 1(4,5), is a sublattice of L. Hence, . Thus, . Consequently, satisfies It follows that is a strongly semiconic idempotent CRL. □
Let be a CRL. A lattice filter F of is called normal if it contains e and it is closed under multiplication. A normal filter F of is said to be prime if it is prime in the usual lattice theoretic sense; that is, whenever , then or Let F and be a normal filter and a congruence of respectively. It is well known that is a congruence of and the upper set of the equivalence class is a normal filter. Moreover, we have the following.
Lemma 7 ([
8]).
The lattice of normal filters of a CRL is isomorphic to its congruence lattice . The isomorphism is given by the mutually inverse maps and . Lemma 8 ([
8]).
Let be a CRL, and let F be a normal filter of . Then, . In what follows, if F is a normal filter of , shall always denote the quotient algebra . Given an element , we write or if there is no confusion for the equivalence class of x in .
Lemma 9. Let be a semiconic CRL, and let F be a normal filter of . Then, the following statements are equivalent:
- (1)
F is prime.
- (2)
For all , whenever , then or .
- (3)
is a finitely subdirectly irreducible conic CRL.
Proof. By specialization.
Suppose that holds, and let . Since is semiconic, . It follows that either or . If , then by Lemma 8, . If , then Thus, is a conic CRL. Let such that . Then, since is conic, , which implies that . Hence, or , which derives that or . Since and . It follows that or . Consequently, is a finitely subdirectly irreducible conic CRL.
Assume that holds, and let such that . Then, . It follows that or or or . Thus, F is prime. □
Lemma 10 ([8]). Let be a residuated lattice and , be finite subsets of the negative cone of with the property that for any i and j. Then, Lemma 11 ([26]). Let be a subclass of variety satisfying the following conditions: - (i)
Every subdirectly irreducible member of is in .
- (ii)
is closed under isomorphisms and subalgebras.
- (iii)
For any algebra and subalgebra of , if and , then there exists such that and .
- (iV)
Every span in has an amalgam in .
Then, has the amalgamation property.
We have the following result, which generalizes [
26] (Theorem 49) in the commutative case.
Theorem 6. Let be a variety of semiconic CRLs, and suppose that the class of finitely subdirectly irreducible conic CRLs in has the amalgamation property. Then, has the amalgamation property.
Proof. It is well known that every subdirectly irreducible semiconic CRL is a finitely subdirectly irreducible conic CRL. It is clear that the class of finitely subdirectly irreducible conic CRLs is closed under isomorphisms and subalgebras. By Lemma 11, we need only to prove that for any , any subalgebra of , and such that is a finitely subdirectly irreducible conic CRL, there is such that and is a finitely subdirectly irreducible conic CRL. Since has the congruence extension property, there is a normal filter F of such that . Let denote the poset under set-inclusion of all set-inclusions of all normal filters of whose intersection with A is P. Since , . By Zorn’s lemma, we have element Q. Next, we shall show that Q is a prime normal filter of . Suppose otherwise, and let be such that but and . Let and be the normal filters of generated by and , respectively. Then, by the maximality of Q, P is a proper subset of the normal filters and of , and so there exist elements , and such that , and . Hence, by Lemma 8, and . Thus, by Lemma 10, . It follows that . Since , the map is an embedding, which together with derives that . Because is a finitely subdirectly irreducible conic CRL, or . Then, by Lemma 8, , or . But , which is a contradiction. Thus, Q is a prime normal filter of , and by Lemma 9, is a finitely subdirectly irreducible conic CRL. The proof of the theorem is complete. □
Lemma 12 ([10]). The class of totally ordered Sugihara monoids has the amalgamation property. The following result is essentially due to Maksimova (see [
27] Chapter 6).
Lemma 13. (Maksimova) The variety of all Brouwerian algebras has the amalgamation property and the class of finitely subdirectly irreducible Brouwerian algebras has the amalgamation property.
Theorem 7. The class of finitely subdirectly irreducible strongly conic idempotent CRLs has the amalgamation property.
Proof. Let be a span of finitely subdirectly irreducible strongly conic idempotent CRLs, assuming, without loss of generality, that and are inclusion maps and that Then, using Theorem 1(11), we also have inclusions between their skeletons and . Since by Theorem 1(11), these skeletons are totally ordered odd Sugihara monoids, Lemma 12 yields an amalgam J for this span that is also a totally ordered odd Sugihara monoid. Moreover, we may assume that . Let and .
Consider
. Recalling that
, clearly
and
. If
, then by Theorem 1(10),
,
and
are finitely subdirectly irreducible Brouwerian algebras, and by Theorem 2,
is a subalgebra of
and
. Hence, by Lemma 13, there exists a finitely subdirectly irreducible Brouwerian algebra
as an amalgam with
. If
, then by Lemma 13, there exists a Brouwerian algebra
as an amalgam with
. If
, then by Proposition 5, each of
and
is a lattice. It is well known that the class of lattices has the amalgamation property. It follows that there exists a lattice
as an amalgam with
. Since
i is the greatest element of
and
, it is also the greatest element of
. Now, for all
and
, let
and
. Let
. By construction,
is a
-system. Thus,
is a conic idempotent
CRL. Since
is a finitely subdirectly irreducible Brouwerian algebra,
is a finitely subdirectly irreducible conic idempotent
CRL. By Proposition 5,
is a strongly finitely subdirectly irreducible conic idempotent
CRL. To show that
is an amalgam of the original span, it suffices to check that
and
are subalgebras of
. Consider
with
. Then,
. If
in
, then
and
, so
and
. If
, then since
is a lattice and
is a sublattice of
,
and
. If
, then since
is a Brouwerian algebra and
is a subalgebra of
,
and
. Thus,
is a sublattice of
. By the definition of
, we have
and
Thus, .
By similar arguments, we have .
The proof that is a subalgebra of is symmetrical. □
Since every variety of commutative residuated lattices has the congruence extension property, by Theorem 6, we have the following result, which generalizes [
10] (Theorem 5.6).
Theorem 8. The variety of strongly semiconic idempotent CRLs has the amalgamation property.