1. Motivation of the Paper
In [
1], it is showed that for convex and coherent risk measures defined on a rearrangement invariant and solid space, i.e., for every random variables
X and
Y with the same distribution
implies
and
, the domain must actually be a subset of
, written
, and the corresponding representation need no completeness assumption, in contrast to the continuity requirement for positive linear functionals employed in the Namioka-Klee theorem for ordered linear spaces. The motivation of [
1] was inspired by the consideration of financial positions having an infinite mean, such as those modeled by Pareto-distributed random variables whose density has a tail index less than one (namely heavy-tailed random variables), which showed up in coping with operational risk, see [
2]. Motivated by the above, we provide standing-alone structure theorems for convex and coherent risk measures that are not direct consequences of known results using neither topological structure for the dual spaces nor continuity from above for the risk measures involved.
In fact, another source of inspiration for using this approach stems from [
3], where in establishing a one-to-one correspondence among the partial ordering of
(interpreted, from the decision theory perspective, as a preference relation), sets of acceptable positions, valuation bounds (actually good-deal bounds), coherent risk measures, and price systems, the authors assert that differently from typical works on arbitrage theory that use topological structures such as closeness and compactness with associated strong separation, it is possible to restate the theory in a purely algebraic manner. In particular, they noticed that a linear pricing functional should lie in the algebraic dual
of
, so in the light of their unified approach to valuation and risk measurement, it seems reasonable to attack the representation problem for monetary risk measures by conceiving cones
containing
as their
internal point. The latter should be interpreted as a
benchmark position that can be different from the usual risk-free one given by a zero-coupon bond, and
also contains the nonnegative financial positions, and its convex structure typically induces the partial ordering on
. Moreover, acceptability of a position
can be understood as the minimal amount of capital
, for
, such that
. We can also think of
e as a risk-free bank account in which a liquid amount of money
m is reserved to make the position acceptable; see [
4,
5] for the case of uncertainty affecting
e, that can lead to cash subadditivity). This leads us to propose an entirely algebraic dual representation of both convex and coherent risk measures defined on ordered linear spaces, where, in the spirit of [Th.2] in [
3], we use a linear functional interpreted as a pricing functional without worrying about its continuity. To obtain a dual representation in the general framework of ordered linear spaces, we resort to Edelheit’s separation theorem, see [
6]. We used it in order to extend the Fenchel-Moreau theorem for conjugate representation of convex functions
, namely its Fenchel-Legendre transform. It turns out that the notion of internal points of cones is crucial for this hyperplane separation theorem to apply. Armed with these algebraic tools, we obtain the dual representation of monetary risk measures with respect to the algebraic dual space
of all the financial positions in
, which is different from the topological dual
.
In our Theorems 2 and 3, the domain of
is indeed a general Riesz space
with a partial order induced by some cone with a non-empty quasi-interior. On the other hand, we are aware of the relevant special case
. In [
7], the authors showed that this is the right ambient space for representing law-invariant convex risk measures provided the underlying probability space is standard; see also [
8] for the extension to atomless probability spaces, which is actually a supplementary note to [
9]. We must care that the topological (or even norm) interior of the positive cone
is empty, and since topological interior points are internal points, there is no sufficient condition to guarantee the direct determination of such latter points. We solve this problem by using the notion of quasi-interior points, since any of such points is also an internal point of the positive cone
, see [
10]. Our contribution to the theory of financial risk measures is in the direction of a convex duality theory without topology: we do not need the underlying spaces to be topological; we do not require continuity of the linear functionals involved in the dual-robust representation of convex/coherent risk measures; we do not impose any axiom concerning continuity of the risk measures ourselves, in part to recover an order-type continuity in the special case
. This enables us to extend previous results on partially ordered linear spaces towards weak separation of convex sets by functional without further requiring any topological assumption. Since some recent literature has investigated the relationship between risk measures and performance measures, we also employ our algebraic framework to extend the notions of coherent acceptability indices and quasi-concave acceptability indices of performance; see [
4,
11,
12] and the references therein.
The paper is organized as follows:
Section 2 sets out some definitions and preliminary results to be used in the sequel.
Section 3 contains our first result concerning the dual representation of coherent risk measures on partially ordered linear spaces.
Section 4 is on our second result concerning the dual representation of convex (not necessarily coherent) risk measures on partially ordered linear spaces.
Section 5 provides an application of our convex duality theory to the case of financial position with finite mean, discussing some issues concerning interior and internal points and introduces the special ‘order continuity’ of the corresponding convex risk measures. In
Section 6, a further application of our algebraic framework is presented: acceptability indices based on either coherent risk measures or convex risk measures on partially ordered linear spaces are treated.
Section 7 contains some concluding remarks.
2. Preliminaries
Given a vector space
containing financial positions, including the constant ones,
denote the algebraic dual of
, which is the vector space of all linear functionals (real-valued) on
, then
is called the
polar wedge of
. For
, a vector
is an internal point of
if given some
, there exists a real number
such that
for any
with
. Recall that, assuming convexity, the set of internal points is convex; see, for example, [Th.1, Ch.4] in [
13] or [Th.0.2.1] in [
14]. In fact, internal and interior points coincide for convex sets in topological vector spaces; see, for example, [Lemma 1.4] in [
15] in the case of normed spaces. It is worth noting that in finite-dimensional spaces (the Euclidean ones), all locally convex topologies are equivalent, then internal and interior points coincide; see [Th.5.60] in [
16]. We let
be partially ordered by
i.e., the partial order is induced by a cone
. In the case
, the partial ordering is reflexive, antisymmetric, transitive, and compatible with the linear structure of
:
- (i)
for any ;
- (ii)
If and , then ;
- (iii)
If and , then ;
- (iv)
If , then for any ;
- (v)
If , then , for any .
The set
is a positive cone provided that
satisfies properties (i) together with (iii) to (v); by adding antisymmetry (ii), it is also pointed. The following statement provides separation of convex sets in (ordered) linear spaces; see [Th.0.2.4] in [
14].
Theorem 1 (Eidelheit’s Separation Theorem).
Suppose that are convex subsets of such that and . Then there is a non-zero functional f of , such that Theorem 1 was established in [
6]. This is the separating hyperplane theorem we mainly used in our representation results. Equivalently, there exists some
such that
if
and
if
, or in short
and
, which is weak separation. Observe that the same statement is [Th.3.8] in [
17]. Compare also with [Th.5.6.1] in [
16]. A convex subset
of a cone
is a
base if for any
there exists some real number
, depending on
X, such that
. If
, the set
is a base of
. The solid subspace generated by
is defined as
, where
. If
is a normed linear space and
is dense in
, then
X is called quasi-interior point. For more details about partially ordered linear spaces, see [
14].
The properties of coherent/convex risk measures and acceptance sets are established in [
18,
19] or [
20], respectively, see also [Ch.4] in [
21]. For the sake of completeness, we list the relevant properties of risk measures. We interpret
as profit and loss from the holding of a portfolio over a fixed time horizon (negative values are losses). Then, a mapping
is a
monetary risk measure if:
it is decreasing monotone, i.e., every such that implies ;
it is cash additive, i.e., for every we have , where is an internal point of the cone of acceptable positions.
The internal point
e can be interpreted as a proxy for the riskless bond, or in the terminology of [
3] relatively secure cash stream. If, in addition,
is
(first degree) positive homogeneous, for all and,
subadditive, , for all ,
then it is a coherent risk measure, which is also a convex mapping. On the other hand, is a convex risk measure if satisfies decreasing monotonicity, cash additivity, and
convexity, for any and for all .
Clearly,
convex is not necessarily coherent. Subadditivity becomes additivity for comonotone
; see [Sec.4.7] in [
21].
3. Coherent Risk Measures on Ordered Linear Spaces
The dual representation of risk measures on a partially ordered linear space
of financial positions can be traced back to [
18] and then [
22], in the case
. The underlying probability space is assumed to be complete and atomless. We keep this assumption for the rest of the paper. We start with a restatement of the classical construction of a cash additive risk measure, given an acceptance set
of financial positions. Recall that
is only assumed to be a partially ordered linear space, and
is the algebraic dual of
, and
is the polar wedge of
.
Theorem 2. A coherent risk measure , whose acceptance set is the cone , such that and e is an internal point of , admits the following dual representation:where . Proof. Let , i.e., X is acceptable. Thus, from cash additivity with respect to e. Then for any . Hence, and . Applying again cash additivity with respect to e, for any . Since and are both convex sets, from Eidelheit’s separation theorem, we have , hence there exists some with and . The latter inequality is especially true for any and . Moreover, this is true for any . This implies that , thus . □
Observe that, equivalently,
. In fact, we have that the mapping
with respect to the cone
and the position
defined as
is a coherent risk measure. The proof can be easily deduced in the current algebraic setting by using cash additivity; see [
22] or [Ch.4] in [
21] for the case
.
4. Convex Risk Measures on Ordered Linear Spaces
In this section, we characterize convex risk measures apart from the representation of coherent risk measures provided in the last section. First, we assume that is a cone of , such that , where as usual is the acceptance set of a convex risk measure satisfying cash additivity with respect to e, which is supposed to be an internal point of .
Theorem 3. Given a cone of acceptable positions, containing e as an internal point, a convex risk measure admits the following dual representation:where , is the polar wedge of the acceptance cone and . We refer to the mapping as a penalty function.
Proof. First, we have that
alike in [Th.5] in [
19]. If
, then
for any
. To show the reverse inequality, we consider
. Thus,
and
for every
. This implies
for any
. From the definition of the penalty function
a, we obtain that
for any
. To show that an equality holds for any
, we suppose that there exists some
such that
This inequality implies there exists some
for which
Hence,
, implying
is not a subset of
. Now,
e is an internal point of
, thus it is also an internal point of
, which is a convex subset of
. The singleton
is also a convex subset of
. The Eidelheit’s separation theorem implies the existence of some
, lying in the algebraic dual
of
, such that
, for every
. Hence
, for any
, where
. Then:
The values of
are positive on
and consequently on
. Then,
, and by normalization, we get
, provided that
. Now, assuming that there exists some
R such that
, where
, we have that
, for any
, and if
, the above separation inequality is violated. Hence, such an
R does not exist. By the separation argument with
, we obtain
which is a contradiction since
. Hence,
which is again a contradiction for any
, as a consequence of the assumption on the existence of
. Eventually, the dual representation is valid for any
, and the proof is complete. □
Incidentally, applying Theorem 3, we get another interesting result. Recall that any real-valued convex function f on a convex subset of a linear space may be defined on the whole by setting it to on . Thus, if the effective domain is nonempty and f nowhere takes the value , then it is called proper.
Theorem 4 (Fenchel-Moreau Type).
Let be a partially ordered linear space. Define a mapping being proper convex, the level set being convex and containing a cone , the vector being an internal point of . Then f admits the following representation:where and the penalty term a are defined as in Theorem 3. Proof. Follows from Theorem 3. □
Theorem 4 is an algebraic version of the classical Fenchel-Moreau theorem for the dual representation of convex risk measures, where the above domain
should be turned into a locally convex topological ordered linear space with topologically dual
. Moreover, in applying the classical Fenchel-Moreau Theorem to the dual representation of convex risk measures, the well-known extended Namioka theorem is useful; see, for example, [Th.2.2] in [
23]. But in the present paper, we do not require that
be endowed with a locally convex topology; hence, Theorem 4 above is sufficient for the dual characterization of convex risk measures in our algebraic setting and, in addition, does not require any assumption of monotonicity on
. We also notice that our result of the Fenchel-Moreau type provides an extension of [Th.2.4] in [
23] on
spaces without the assumption of
-lower semicontinuity. We end this section by verifying the properties satisfied by the proposed convex risk measure. For the converse of Theorem 3, we have the following proposition, whose proof is omitted.
Proposition 1. A risk measure that admits the representationis a convex risk measure, where is a cone of acceptable positions, containing e as an internal point, is the polar wedge of the acceptance cone , and the penalty function is given by . As in the special cases
for
developed in the literature, coherent and convex risk measures on general ordered linear spaces differ by a penalty function. The financial meaning of the penalty function is that an additional capital loading is needed in order to
secure some financial position
X. Namely, the convex, non-coherent risk measures correspond to more conservative economic capital requirements for any financial position. Nevertheless, a monetary risk measure
defined on a more general ordered linear space
, which is cash additive, decreasing monotone, and convex, is represented as
. Hence, assuming a zero penalty function,
, implies
becomes positively homogeneous and thus a coherent risk measure. To see why this is true, observe that
, for every
, so taking the supremum over the linear functionals
does the job. Moreover, as for the classical Lebesgue spaces, we can show that the addition of positive homogeneity making
coherent would imply
or
. First, we note that by the convexity and the positive homogeneity of
, together with decreasing monotonicity, it follows normalization
. Next, consider those linear functionals
for which
, each
. Evaluating the penalty function over them yields
if and only if
, since obviously
. On the other hand, pick any linear functional
such that
for some
. It follows from the positive homogeneity of
that the mapping
is positive homogeneous. As a byproduct, for those strictly positive real numbers
, we get:
This confirms how the penalty function equals the indicator
ı of the convex subset
where in the current algebraic setting no closeness is required, that is,
if
and
otherwise. It is worth noting that the penalty function is also convex and proper, since
and also
is non-empty. The dual representation of coherent risk measures given by Theorem 2 together with representation (
2) clearly show that we must restrict
to be a subset of
instead. This is due to cash additivity and decreasing monotonicity. Explicitly, picking
entails
implying
, where we used the cash additivity of
. If
then by decreasing monotonicity
, and again picking
yields
, leading to imposing
over all the financial positions
.
Example 1. Assume with algebraic dual and let be the unit order interpreted as a risk-free position. Then, let the set of linear functionals in Theorems 2 and 3 be given by , where as usual are probability measures equivalent to the original , and consider the mapping for any fixed Radon-Nikodým derivatives where together with . Next, remove the -norm topology or the weak topology and instead assume the topology induced by the Ky Fan metricRecall that this metric is not induced by a norm and that it metrizes convergence in probability in the larger space . Recall also how convergence in probability does not imply -convergence. Hence, the dual representation for convex risk measures, or coherent risk measures in the case , still holds thanks to our representation results even if the Radon-Nikodým derivatives in the dual set no longer produce a continuous linear functional . In fact, , but the expectation functional is not α-continuous, but Theorems 2 and 3 do not require any continuity. Example 2. We call incomplete market a subspace which is not or the entire space of financial positions, where denotes its algebraic dual. We want to define coherent and convex risk measures in incomplete markets. Thanks to Theorems 2 and 3 and supposing that e is an internal point of the cone , which is the acceptance set of a risk measure , namely , and that is a cone, we obtain the following:
If ρ is coherent, then , where .
If ρ is convex, then , where , and .
Observe that is a cone, either in the case where ρ is coherent or in the case where ρ is a convex risk measure. In the case of a coherent risk measure, is the acceptance set of ρ. In the case of a convex risk measure, is a cone, which is a subset of the acceptance set . In both of the cases, is an internal point of .
5. Financial Positions as Interior and Internal Points
Referring to the case of financial positions
is mainly based on the insights in [
7] characterized by a one-to-one correspondence between law-invariant convex risk measures on
and
; see also [
8]. Furthermore, the choice
is also supported by empirical evidence underlying the stylized fact that portfolio losses have a finite expectation. On the other hand, there is well-understood empirical evidence that many traded positions have a distribution with fat tails and statistical models for profits and losses such as stable distributions with a suitable (typically greater than one) value of the stability index have a finite mean; see [Ch.3, Sec.1a] in [
24]. See in addition [Ch.3] in [
25] for further details on stylized facts about profits and losses.
Our algebraic approach calls for
considered as a vector lattice or a
Riesz space: The real linear space
is equipped with the usual partial ordering
, for pointwise
-a.s. every scenario
, which in addition has a supremum
for each pair of financial positions. Observe that the partial ordering
is compatible with the algebraic structure of
. Moreover,
for any scenario
and similarly
. Eventually,
. The absolute value
is defined as
. Equivalently, the absolute value in a vector lattice is defined as
, where
and
. This algebraic structure is more general than that of a topological vector lattice, namely
endowed with the norm
, for every position
. In fact, we do not use the Banach lattice feature of
, where the
-norm is also complete. (This norm is monotone with respect to
and entails
as a locally convex-solid space, see [Ch.9] in [
16]). The positive cone of the positions is
. The following negative result is important.
Proposition 2. Assuming is a complete, atomless probability space, then the set of -interior points of is empty.
Proof. Since in this case
is infinite-dimensional, the proof is a consequence of [Th.4.4.4] in [
14]. This is true since
is a well-based cone. □
With the above negative result in mind, we next recall that the order interval
equals the solid subspace generated by
, which is
-dense, then yielding
X as a quasi-interior point. We define the
principal ideal
generated by
X. The former definition requires topological arguments, while the latter is purely algebraic and depends upon the vector lattice structure of
with respect to the pointwise
-a.s. partial order. The following results are remedies to the issue given in Proposition 2.
Proposition 3. Let the dual pair be given. Then, the set of quasi-interior points of is nonempty.
Theorem 5. Any quasi-interior point X of is an internal point of .
Remark 1. Any point in valued strictly positively by a non-zero continuous linear functional in (consider the weak topology ) is a quasi-interior point in , and Proposition 3 yields that the order interval and the principal ideal do coincide for any non-zero .
The two results above are proved in [
10] and are reported here to highlight the importance of using internal points in vector optimization problems as the ones underlying our algebraic robust representation of coherent and convex risk measures.
We close this section with a result on continuity of
when
for
, which is different from the usual strong, weak, or weak
* continuity requirements for convex risk measures; see [Def.3.1] in [
23,
26]. Recall that a sequence
in a Riesz space
is order convergent to a vector
, written
, if there exits another sequence
that is decreasing to the zero vector
for each
, also written
, such that
, written
, and with
for all
.
Theorem 6 (Order Continuity). Let be a convex risk measure, for , and let be a sequence such that in the -a.s. sense for every , where . If , then .
Proof. The sequence
is order-bounded with respect to the partial ordering, which makes
a vector lattice. By [Lemma 8.17] in [
16], we have
for any
f lying in the algebraic dual of
. The convergence is valid for any
as defined in Theorem 3. Hence,
for any
. From the dual representation of a convex risk measure in Theorem 3, we get
since
for any
. □
6. Acceptability Indices on Ordered Linear Spaces
In this section, we provide another representation of acceptability indices of performance using our algebraic framework. First, we consider the following:
Definition 1. A mapping is an acceptability index of performance if it satisfies the following properties.
Quasi-concavity: given a pair and for every such that and one has Monotonicity: for any Scale invariance: for every and
Differently from [
11], we do not use a fourth axiom by calling for the upper semicontinuity of
in the appropriate topology because
is only a partially ordered linear space.
Remark 2. Acceptable positions at level form a convex superlevel setwhich is a natural requirement for any performance measure. Quasi-concavity is equivalent to the convexity of for each : any diversified position performs at least as well as its components. Moreover, is increasing monotone, and Y is at least as acceptable as X, provided that the latter is dominated by the former. By scale invariance, is actually a cone for every ; the level of acceptance remains the same whenever we scale positions.
Now, with a little abuse of notation for each
, we let
be the cone of acceptability for the coherent risk measure
such that
, where
e is an internal point of
. By Theorem 2 we have
with
the latter being the polar wedge of
. Thus, by construction, we have a family of sets of linear functionals
supporting the representation of each coherent risk measure
, with corresponding acceptance set
. Observe that every acceptance set
in (
7) is clearly decreasing in
x. Moreover, if
is increasing in
x, then
is obviously increasing in
x too, by definition (
8), as well as
. In fact, defining
yields
increasing in
x, since
and as usual,
e is an internal point of the cone
. The equivalence of the two definitions of
, in terms of
and in terms of
, now follows from the lemma below, which shows the equivalence
.
Proposition 4. Let be defined as in (9) through an acceptability index . Then, is a coherent risk measure on the ordered linear space , for every . Vice-versa, let be a family of coherent risk measures on the ordered linear space , which is increasing in x. This is an acceptability index of performance (we take ) defined on the same space. Proof. (First part) For the
and
conditions,
is equivalent to
, and
-a.s. together with
do imply
To check decreasing monotonicity of
, take
and pick
such that
-a.s. By increasing monotonicity of
, we have
Thus we deduce
and taking the infimum of both sets, we get
To show cash additivity, for every
and
, we note that
To show positive homogeneity, it suffices to call for the scale invariance of
To check for subadditivity, pick
such that
and
for every
and
By the quasi-concavity of
, for every
, we have
at the same acceptability level
x. Choosing
and using the scale invariance of the acceptability index again entails
Therefore, the scalar
belongs to the set
, and it is greater than or equal to the infimum over the same set, which in turn is just
This inequality holds true for all
and all
belonging to
and to
respectively. As a consequence, taking the infimum with respect to
and then with respect to
, we get
.
(Second part) Let
then by decreasing the monotonicity of
in
x; we have
For any
, we also have
which, together with the monotonicity, entails
for all
As a consequence, we have the set inclusion
and, taking the supremum of both sets, the increasing monotonicity of
is proved. To check quasi-concavity of
, we first choose a pair
such that
and
whenever
By decreasing monotonicity of
, we have
and
for all
This combined with the positive homogeneity of
entails
for every
. Moreover, by subadditivity of
and again for every
, we additionally have
which entails
Eventually, this implies
and quasi-concavity easily follows. The scale invariance of
follows immediately from the positive homogeneity of
. □
With all this in mind, we are ready to state:
Theorem 7. A mapping is an acceptability index of performance if and only if there exists a family of subsets increasing in x withand , where and . The proof of Theorem 7 does not present any serious difficulty with respect to that of the original representation in [Th.1] in [
11], but we provide it for the sake of comparison with our algebraic setting. However, since the special choice
in [Th 1] in [
11] is referred to as a Riesz space, Theorem 7 extends it to general partially ordered linear space.
Proof. (If part) Assuming the mapping
is defined as in (
10), checking it satisfies monotonicity and scale invariance appearing in Definition 1 is trivial. To check for quasi-concavity, pick
with
both
. Assuming
in
we have
both
, for every linear functional
. Since also
, with
, then
.
(Only If part) Let the mapping
be an acceptability index as in Definition 1, and fix
such that
is the convex superlevel set given by (
7), which is decreasing in
x. Now, defining
is equivalent to having
as in (
9). Hence, the mapping
is a coherent risk measure on
, each
. It remains to show the existence of a family
of subsets
increasing in
x, such that the representation
holds. But as showed above,
is coherent, and thanks to Theorem 2, we can let
be the set of linear functionals supporting the representation of
given by (
1), for
. If for such acceptability level
x the superlevel set
given by (
7) is equal to the entire ordered linear space
, then
must be the empty set so that
For the arbitrariness of
x, we get
for every
. Furthermore,
decreases in
x so that
increases in
x, which yields the sets of linear functionals
increase in
x as required. Since Proposition 4 gives
if and only if
, we are done. □
The proof of Theorem 7 can be easily extended to the case of quasi-concave acceptability indices (see Definition 2 below) using an
x-increasing family of convex risk measures
by first recognizing that (
10) can be written
then requiring additionally that
(meaning that a zero position is always acceptable),
for any
, and
for any
, see [Prop.3] in [
27] for the case
where additional continuity properties for both
and
are imposed.
In the special case , for , the order-type continuity of coherent risk measures as stated above, is sufficient to have acceptability indices of performance as upper semicontinuous maps on these spaces for order-bounded sequences of financial positions.
Corollary 1. Let be a mapping given by (10). Assume is a family of coherent risk measures on , increasing in x and continuous in the sense of Theorem 6. Then, for an order-bounded sequence such that . Then . Proof. By Theorem 6 and its proof together with Theorem 7, since by the hypotheses , we have if and only if by linearity, where for a fixed . Assuming , we may pick any real number and get , for every and all linear functionals . This entails and thus , which is upper semicontinuity. □
For coherent risk measures, Definition 1 and Theorem 7 are the adequate framework for performance measurement in the sense of conic finance, see [
28] and the reference therein for a more detailed study of this topic.
When convex, non-coherent risk measures come into play, we need a slightly different definition of an index of performance than Definition 1. Moreover, we need to drop the scale invariance from the minimal properties an acceptability index of performance must satisfy and try to represent it without the direct intervention of some monetary (actually quasi-convex) risk measures, as we did using coherent risk measures in (
10).
Definition 2. A mapping is a quasi-concave acceptability index of performance if it satisfies quasi-concavity and increasing monotonicity.
For such indices of performance, we have the following:
Theorem 8. A quasi-concave acceptability index of performance admits the following ‘min-max’ representation:for every , with , where the risk-free position e is an internal point of the positive cone . Observe that we do not need any acceptability system of positions in Theorem 8.
Proof. The reasoning is the same as in the proof of the topological-version borrowed from [Th.40] in [
12]. Define
, for every
and
. For a fixed position
we obviously have
, and this together with the definition of
imply
It remains to show the reverse inequality and eventually that the infimum can be taken over normalized positive linear functionals
, where
is the positive cone of linear functionals. Beforehand, take
and let
which is a convex superlevel set since
is quasi-concave. Since
, where
is also convex, we can invoke Edelheit’s separation theorem and find some non-zero linear functional
such that
Now, the complement of
, i.e.,
, includes the set of those positions
for which
, for a fixed
, due to the weak separation above. As byproduct:
The above inequalities show that
. Now the infimum can be taken over
, because
as in the proof of [Th.40] in [
12], mainly because
for every linear functional
and
. Eventually, since
we are done. □
Note that Theorem 8 above and its proof are the algebraic version of [Th.40] in [
12], where originally the set
of financial positions is assumed to be a locally convex topological linear space.
Remark 3. The construction of a quasi-concave acceptability index of performance in Theorem 8 is mainly based on the insights of [4]. Relaxing the convexity property, the authors provide a dual representation of quasi-convex risk measures based on acceptability systems, generalizing those considered in [11]. Specifically, any acceptability set posses additional features than convexity and gives rise to a quasi-convex ρ via the association if and only if . A main difference with the acceptability families in [11] is that now is increasing in x. Further, any such set is monotone for a fixed x in the sense of the membership relation and is right-continuous; see [Def 3] in [4]. Quasi-convex risk measures were motivated by the concept of cash-subadditivity in [5] and, in general, by the problem of finding a dual representation of quasi-convex and lower semicontinuous functions; see, for example, [29]. Thus, when is a locally convex topological linear space with dual the robust representation of a quasi-convex, monotone decreasing and a lower semicontinuous risk measure is given (uniquely) by , where and . The supremum is taken over all the normalized nonnegative functionals π. It is worth noting that the function R possesses some interesting properties; see [4]. As said before, Theorem 7 can be given for convex risk measures
, which are also quasi-convex, in order to get the dual representation of quasi-concave acceptability indices like that in Equation (
11). On the other hand, consider the function
where
and
is the set of dual functionals in Theorem 2 for coherent risk measures on partially ordered linear spaces. It is easily seen that
is a monotone increasing and concave (thus quasi-concave) acceptability index, which is by no means scale invariant, and then it cannot be represented via Theorem 7. Observe that the equivalence
if and only if
is violated in this case since the condition
cannot be reduced to
, neither if we take
, for every
, where the indexed sets
of linear functionals are understood as supporting the representation (
10).