Discounted and Expected Utility from the Probability and Time Trade-Off Model
Abstract
:1. Introduction
2. Literature Review
2.1. Uncertainty as Central Concept. Transformation of Delays into Probability Terms
2.2. Uncertainty is Inherent to Intertemporal Choice. Interpretation of Reward Probability as Waiting Time
2.3. Models to Assess Risky Intertemporal Choices
3. Deriving DU and EU from the Probability and Time Trade-Off Model
3.1. Introduction
- If , then the concept of a discount function in the context of the DU model arises: is a continuous real-valued map defined on , which is strictly increasing in the first component, strictly decreasing in the second component, and satisfies , for every .
- If , then the concept of a discount function in the context of the EU model arises: is a continuous real-valued map defined on , which is strictly increasing in the two components, and satisfies , for every .
- (i)
- is the solution of if, and only if, .
- (ii)
- is the solution of if, and only if, .
3.2. Deriving EU from PTT Model
3.3. Deriving DU from PTT Model
- For , , which is the DU model.
- For , , which is the EU model.
3.4. Deriving PTT from DU or EU Model
- (A)
- Given a DU model, , it can be assumed that all prospects have probability . In this case, we can construct a PTT model which coincides with the DU model when :
- (B)
- Analogously, given an EU model, , it can be understood that all prospects expire at the same instant . In this case, we can construct a PTT model which coincides with the EU model when :Observe that for the sake of generality, neither of the two PTT proposed models are of the form nor pointed out by [1].
- (C)
- Given a DU model, , and an EU model, , if and , respectively, we can construct a PTT model which coincides with both models, at and , respectively:
4. Discussion
- In the seminal paper by Allais [47], the disproportionate preference for present outcomes of the immediacy effect is shown, consequently not only of the intrinsic temptation but the certainty on the payment.
- Keren and Roelofsma [28] analyze the effect of risk on the immediacy effect and the effect of time delay on the certainty effect. They suggest that time distance makes outcomes seem more uncertain by eliminating the certainty advantage of the immediate outcome. Thereof, they reveal that the introduction of uncertainty reduces the importance of time delay (if two certain rewards are transformed to be equally probable (i.e., ), the delayed one is generally preferred). In the same way, time distance decreases the influence of the probability on preferences.
- Chapman and Weber [17] prove that when the delay is introduced to sure outcomes, the certainty effect is almost eliminated just as when uncertainty is added. On the other hand, in a similar way, when explicit risk is introduced to immediate rewards, the immediacy effect is almost eliminated just as if time delay is added. It is necessary to clarify that presently there is no consensus on this topic, while Pennesi [48] confirms that when the immediate payoff becomes uncertain, the immediacy effect disappears, Abdellaoui et al. [35] claim that the immediacy effect persists under risk.
- Epper et al. [31] stress that previous papers, in most cases, determine that there are interaction effects between time and risk, such as risk tolerance increases with delay.
- Andreoni and Sprenger [49] conclude that risk preference is not time preference: “subjects exhibit a preference for certainty when it is available, but behave largely as discounted expected utility maximizers away from certainty”.
- Time interacts with risk preference if, for every , , and ,
- Risk interacts with time preference if, for every , t, , and ,
5. Conclusions
- On the one hand, the DU model has been derived from the PTT model, by taking a specific value of probability. Specifically, we have found that the PTT model is equivalent to the discount function with stochastic time , where is the random variable: “Time period in which the reward x can be delivered, at a discounting level k”.
- Analogously, given a concrete value of time, the EU model can be derived from the PTT model.
- Finally, this paper provides some insights into the construction of a PTT model starting from a DU and an EU model. However, more future research is needed on this topic.
Author Contributions
Funding
Acknowledgments
Conflicts of Interest
Abbreviations
DU | Discounted Utility |
EU | Expected Utility |
DEU | Discounted Expected Utility |
PTT | Probability and Time Trade-Off |
References
- Baucells, M.; Heukamp, F.H. Probability and time trade-off. Manag. Sci. 2012, 58, 831–842. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Green, L.; Myerson, J. A discounting framework for choice with delayed and probabilistic rewards. Psychol. Bull. 2004, 130, 769–792. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed] [Green Version]
- Soares dos Santos, L.; Destefano, N.; Souto Martinez, A. Decision making generalized by a cumulative probability weighting function. Phys. Stat. Mech. Its Appl. 2018, 490, 250–259. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Weber, B.J.; Chapman, G.B. The combined effects of risk and time on choice: Does uncertainty eliminate the immediacy effect? Organ. Behav. Hum. Decis. 2005, 96, 104–118. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Luckman, A.; Donkin, C.; Newell, B.R. Can a single model account for both risky choices and inter-temporal choices? Testing the assumptions underlying models of risky inter-temporal choice. Psychon. Bull. Rev. 2018, 25, 785–792. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Baucells, M.; Heukamp, F.H.; Villasis, A. Risk and time preferences integrated. In Proceedings of the Foundations of Utility and Risk Conference, Rome, Italy, 30 April 2006. [Google Scholar]
- Cruz Rambaud, S.; Sánchez Pérez, A.M. The magnitude and peanuts effects: Searching implications. Front. Appl. Math. Stat. 2018, 4, 36. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
- Samuelson, P.A. A note on measurement of utility. Rev. Econ. Stud. 1937, 4, 155–161. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Von Neumann, J.; Morgenstern, O. Theory of Games and Economic Behavior, 2nd ed.; Princeton University Press: Princeton, NJ, USA, 1947. [Google Scholar]
- Schoemaker, P.J.H. The Expected Utility model: Its variants, purposes, evidence and limitations. J. Econ. Lit. 1982, 20, 529–563. [Google Scholar]
- Coble, K.H.; Lusk, J.L. At the nexus of risk and time preferences: An experimental investigation. J. Risk Uncertain. 2010, 41, 67–79. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Andreoni, J.; Sprenger, C. Risk Preferences Are Not Time Preferences: Discounted Expected Utility with a Disproportionate Preference for Certainty; Working Paper 16348; National Bureau of Economic Research: Cambridge, MA, USA, 2010. [Google Scholar]
- Jamison, D.T. Studies in Individual Choice Behavior; RAND Memorandum No. P-4255; RAND Corporation: Santa Monica, CA, USA, 1970. [Google Scholar]
- Leland, J.; Schneider, M. Risk Preference, Time Preference, and Salience Perception; ESI Working Papers 17-16; ESI: Orange, CA, USA, 2017. [Google Scholar]
- Lanier, J.; Miao, B.; Quah, J.K.H.; Zhong, S. Intertemporal Consumption with Risk: A Revealed Preference Analysis. Available online: http://dx.doi.org/10.2139/ssrn.3168361 (accessed on 28 February 2020).
- Onay, S.; Öncüler, A. Intertemporal choice under timing risk: An experimental approach. J. Risk Uncertain. 2007, 34, 99–121. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Chapman, G.B.; Weber, B.J. Decision biases in intertemporal choice and choice under uncertainty: Testing a common account. Mem. Cogn. 2006, 34, 589–602. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
- Quiggin, J.; Horowitz, J. Time and risk. J. Risk Uncertain. 1995, 10, 37–55. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Prelec, D.; Loewenstein, G. Decision making over time and under uncertainty: A common approach. Manag. Sci. 1991, 37, 770–786. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Green, L.; Myerson, J.; Ostaszewski, P. Amount of reward has opposite effects on the discounting of delayed and probabilistic outcomes. J. Exp. Psychol. Mem. Cogn. 1999, 2, 418–427. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Schneider, M. Dual-Process Utility Theory: A Model of Decisions Under Risk and Over Time; ESI Working Paper; ESI: Orange, CA, USA, 2016. [Google Scholar]
- Gollier, C. The Economics of Risk and Time; MIT Press: Cambridge, MA, USA, 2004. [Google Scholar]
- Rachlin, H.; Raineri, A.; Cross, D. Subjective probability and delay. J. Exp. Anal. Behav. 1991, 55, 233–244. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed] [Green Version]
- Takahashi, T.; Ikeda, K.; Hasegawa, T. A hyperbolic decay of subjective probability of obtaining delayed rewards. Behav. Brain Funct. 2007, 3, 1–11. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed] [Green Version]
- Issler, J.V.; Piqueira, N.S. Estimating relative risk aversion, the discount rate, and the intertemporal elasticity of substitution in consumption for Brazil using three types of utility function. Braz. Rev. Econom. 2000, 20, 201–239. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
- Van Praag, B.M.S.; Booij, A.S. Risk Aversion and the Subjective Time Preference: A Joint Approach; CESifo Working Paper Series 923; CESifo Group: Munich, Germany, 2003. [Google Scholar]
- Anderhub, V.; Güth, W.; Gneezy, U.; Sonsino, D. On the interaction of risk and time preferences: An experimental study. Ger. Econ. Rev. 2001, 2, 239–253. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
- Keren, G.; Roelofsma, P. Immediacy and certainty in intertemporal choice. Organ. Behav. Hum. Decis. Process. 1995, 63, 287–297. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
- Fisher, I. The Theory of Interest; Macmillan: New York, NY, USA, 1930. [Google Scholar]
- Dai, J.; Pachur, T.; Pleskac, T.J.; Hertwig, R. What the future holds and when: A description-experience gap in intertemporal choice. Psychol. Sci. 2019, 30, 1218–1233. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
- Epper, T.; Fehr-Duda, H.; Bruhin, A. Viewing the future through a warped lens: Why uncertainty generates hyperbolic discounting. J. Risk Uncertain. 2011, 43, 169–203. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
- Takahashi, T. A comparison of intertemporal choices for oneself versus someone else based on Tsallis’ statistics. Phys. Stat. Mech. Its Applications 2007, 385, 637–644. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Ericson, K.M.; Laibson, D. Intertemporal choice (No. w25358). In Handbook of Behavioral Economics; Elsevier: Amsterdam, The Netherlands, 2018. [Google Scholar]
- Loewenstein, G.; Prelec, D. Anomalies in intertemporal choice: Evidence and an interpretation. Q. J. Econ. 1992, 107, 573–597. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Abdellaoui, M.; Kemel, E.; Panin, A.; Vieider, F.M. Measuring time and risk preferences in an integrated framework. Games Econ. Behav. 2019, 115, 459–469. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Baucells, M.; Heukamp, F.H. Common ratio using delay. Theory Decis. 2010, 68, 149–158. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Vanderveldt, A.; Green, L.; Myerson, J. Discounting of monetary rewards that are both delayed and probabilistic: Delay and probability combine multiplicatively, not additively. J. Exp. Psychol. Learn. Cogn. 2015, 41, 148–162. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
- Yi, R.; de la Piedad, x.; Bickel, W.K. The combined effects of delay and probability in discounting. Behav. Process. 2006, 73, 149–155. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- DeJarnette, P.; Dillenberger, D.; Gottlieb, D.; Ortoleva, P. Time lotteries, second version (No. 15-026v2). Penn Institute for Economic Research; Department of Economics, University of Pennsylvania: Philadelphia, PA, USA, 2018. [Google Scholar]
- Han, R.; Takahashi, T. Psychophysics of time perception and valuation in temporal discounting of gain and loss. Phys. Stat. Mech. Its Appl. 2012, 391, 6568–6576. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Konstantinidis, E.; Van Ravenzwaaij, D.; Güney, Ş.; Newell, B.R. Now for sure or later with a risk? Modeling risky intertemporal choice as accumulated preference. Decision 2020, 7, 91–120. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
- Caliendo, F.N.; Findley, T.S. Discount functions and self-control problems. Econ. Lett. 2014, 122, 416–419. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Cruz Rambaud, S.; Parra Oller, I.M.; Valls Martínez, M.C. The amount-based deformation of the q-exponential discount function: A joint analysis of delay and magnitude effects. Phys. Stat. Mech. Its Applications 2019, 508, 788–796. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Chew, S.H.; Epstein, L.G. Nonexpected utility preferences in a temporal framework with an application to consumption-savings behaviour. J. Econ. Theory 1990, 50, 54–81. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Halevy, Y. Strotz meets Allais: Diminishing impatience and the certainty effect. Am. Econ. 2008, 98, 1145–1162. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
- Brandstätter, E.; Kühberger, A.; Schneider, F. A cognitive-emotional account of the shape of the probability weighting function. J. Behav. Decis. Mak. 2002, 15, 79–100. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Allais, M. Le comportement de l’homme rationnel devant le risque: Critique des postulats et axiomes de l’école américaine. Econometrica 1953, 21, 503–546. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Pennesi, D. Uncertain discount and hyperbolic preferences. Theory Decis. 2017, 83, 315–336. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Andreoni, J.; Sprenger, C. Risk preferences are not time preferences. Am. Econ. Rev. 2012, 102, 3357–3376. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
Discounted Utility (DU) | Expected Utility (EU) | |
---|---|---|
Pioneer work | Samuelson [8] | Von Neumann and Morgenstern [9] |
Result | The present value of delayed rewards | The expected value of risky rewards |
Formula | ||
Parameters | : utility from the reward at t | : utility from the k-th reward |
t: reward maturity () | : probability of the k-th reward () | |
: discount factor () |
Pioneer work | Jamison [13] |
Result | The value of risky and delayed rewards |
Formula | |
Parameters | V: valuation of consumption in different periods |
t: reward maturity () | |
: discount function | |
: utility of consumption at t () |
© 2020 by the authors. Licensee MDPI, Basel, Switzerland. This article is an open access article distributed under the terms and conditions of the Creative Commons Attribution (CC BY) license (http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/).
Share and Cite
Cruz Rambaud, S.; Sánchez Pérez, A.M. Discounted and Expected Utility from the Probability and Time Trade-Off Model. Mathematics 2020, 8, 601. https://doi.org/10.3390/math8040601
Cruz Rambaud S, Sánchez Pérez AM. Discounted and Expected Utility from the Probability and Time Trade-Off Model. Mathematics. 2020; 8(4):601. https://doi.org/10.3390/math8040601
Chicago/Turabian StyleCruz Rambaud, Salvador, and Ana María Sánchez Pérez. 2020. "Discounted and Expected Utility from the Probability and Time Trade-Off Model" Mathematics 8, no. 4: 601. https://doi.org/10.3390/math8040601
APA StyleCruz Rambaud, S., & Sánchez Pérez, A. M. (2020). Discounted and Expected Utility from the Probability and Time Trade-Off Model. Mathematics, 8(4), 601. https://doi.org/10.3390/math8040601