Positive Psychology and Philosophy-as-Usual: An Unhappy Match?
Abstract
:1. Introduction
1.1. Background
We well recognize that positive psychology is not a new idea. It has many distinguished ancestors, and we make no claim of originality. However, these ancestors somehow failed to attract a cumulative, empirical body of research to ground their ideas.[1] (p. 13)
reading philosophy and dabbling in history and religion did not provide satisfying answers to that question. I found the ideas in these texts to be too subjective, to be dependent on faith or to be dubious assumptions; they lacked the clear-eyed skepticism and the slow cumulative growth that I associated with science.[1] (p. 7)
1.2. The Present Work
2. Conceptual Rigour through Philosophy-as-Usual?
2.1. Example 1: “Flow” and the Concordance Thesis
2.1.1. Background
The virtuous person, like the expert in a practical skill, responds dynamically to challenges, but this is, we may think, experienced in action as a selfless kind of flow.[17] (p. 33)
virtuous activity, as opposed to merely self-controlled activity, is pleasant, not in involving extra feelings but in being unimpeded by contrary impulses, and in harmony with all of the person’s thoughts and feelings. In the virtuous, virtuous activity can be thought of as an example of “flow” because it is an unforced expression of the person’s reasoning and feelings, in harmony with the rest of her character and structured system of goals.[17] (p. 30)
flow experiences occur when individuals engage in complex and challenging activities that test one’s capacities [...] cognitive engagement is crucial, as part of the enjoyment lies in the exercise of her intellect—in the problem-solving,[19] (p. 96)
most of the virtuous activities that Aristotle sees as flourishing–constituting are pretty dull and uninspiring in themselves [and] not likely to produce flow,[6] (p. 546)
2.1.2. Disambiguating “Flow”
researchers seem to equalize the precondition of flow [...] with the experience itself [...] Because the association between the preconditions of flow and the experience itself is definitely not deterministic [...] this is problematic. [… A] measure of skills–demands balance should not be used (or interpreted) as a measure of the flow experience per se.
- The experience of autotelic (intrinsically motivated) behaviour;
- Optimal experience, which in turn has several definitions including
- A ‘complex and positive state characterized by deep involvement and absorption, supporting personal growth, well-being and optimal functioning in daily life’ [31] (p. 3), and
- The experience “where action becomes automatic and conscious thought seems to meld together with the action itself” [32] (p. 95);
- The experience of total involvement in what one is doing [33];
- Skill–demand balance (e.g., [35]).
Aristotle famously expresses this as the difference between the virtuous and the merely “encratic” or continent person, who acts in the same way as the virtuous, but is not yet virtuous, because acting virtuously comes up against his feelings and attachments.[18] (p. 67)
2.1.3. Concept Clarification Failure
2.2. Example 2: “Objective Wellbeing”
Subjectivity can refer to somewhat differing things. A view can emphasise the importance for the well-being of positive feeling states such as happiness—someone has high well-being to the extent that they feel happy. Or, subjectivity can be characterised as the extent to which people define their own well-being in whatever way they choose, as opposed to having others define it by reference to external standards. These two aspects can be combined if it is assumed that when people are left to define their own well-being subjectively, experienced happiness is central to that definition.[39] (p. 1075)
It is almost de rigueur to invoke Wittgenstein as an example of an unhappy flourisher. His famous last words, ‘Tell them that I’ve had a wonderful life’ [...] are typically taken to mean that he considered himself to have flourished in life [...] However, by all accounts, he was a grumpy and miserable person with a serious happiness deficit.
2.3. Example 3: “Normativity”
2.4. Example 4: “Eudaimonia”
3. Philosophy outside Its Proper Bounds
3.1. Kraut’s Oyster versus Nagel’s Bat
asks us to compare two lives: the first he calls “oyster-like” because it has “very little consciousness and a very little excess of pleasure over pain”; the second is that of a human being. His striking thesis is that a sufficiently longer oyster-like life is better than any shorter human life, no matter how wonderful the goods in the human life are.(p. 2)
I will refer to the other creature in this comparison as “McTaggart’s oyster” (not just oyster-like). To simplify matters further, I will assume that this oyster feels no pain and only the mildest of pleasures as it takes in nourishment.(p. 2)
We can have some notion of [the oyster’s] inner life: it takes in nourishment and (we are assuming) it seeks more of the same because it has a pleasant sensation when it eats. We know through introspection what it is like to get pleasure from the taste of something. We can imagine what it is like to have nothing but that as one’s form of consciousness, and can compare that kind of life to the much larger form of consciousness we are lucky enough to have, with respect to how good they are.[58] (p. 23)
3.2. Relevance to Positive Psychology
4. Discussion
Philosophy could be characterized with only a bit of irony as what is left if you begin with the sum total of human thought and subtract those areas in which clear progress has been made. Matters are even less encouraging when it comes to philosophical ethics. The history of ethics looks like a story of progress only if its main texts are read in reverse chronological order.[64] (p. 1)
5. Could the Match Turn Happy?
5.1. Absolving Aristotle
that it is not profitable for us at present to do moral philosophy [...] the concepts of obligation, and duty—moral obligation and moral duty, that is to say—and of what is morally right and wrong, and of the moral sense of “ought”, ought to be jettisoned.(p. 1)
If someone professes to be expounding Aristotle and talks in a modern fashion about “moral” such-and-such he must be very imperceptive if he does not constantly feel like someone whose jaws have somehow got out of alignment: the teeth don’t come together in a proper bite.
5.2. The Value of Returning to the Source(s)
5.3. A Dao (道 “Way”) Forward for Positive Psychology
5.3.1. ZhuangZi: The Sage in Flow
the idea of flow in positive psychology focuses on two key factors, namely, skills and goals. Zhuangzi’s flow, however, accentuates more the idea of forgetfulness, or to be more exactly, the forgetfulness of both self and the goal.
5.3.2. Harmony and Flexibility
5.3.3. Way-Making
Funding
Data Availability Statement
Conflicts of Interest
1 | The claim that humanistic psychology was deficient in terms of rigorous science was disputed and later partly retracted, see [2] (p. 18). However that may be, this dispute is irrelevant for the present work as the latter is concerned with the relationship between philosophy and the scientific study of wellbeing in positive psychology. |
2 | I use this term for lack of a better one. What I find problematic in philosophy does not neatly line up with the popular analytic versus European distinction. The phrase is chosen in parallel with “business as usual”, which is a way of saying that things continue as normal. Of course, this can be a positive thing (e.g., being able to keep things going without interruption during times of crisis) or negative (e.g., insufficient flexibility to adopt to changing circumstances). I leave it to the reader to determine in which respects and to what extend philosophy-as-usual is to be seen positively, negatively, or neutral. |
3 | It is provided as an appendix since I am painfully aware of the brevity of my discussion. Nevertheless, I felt a work related to positive psychology should at least sketch a positive outlook; a fuller treatment has to await another occasion. |
4 | And possibly also for the psychology of judgement and decision making, see the last section of this paper. |
5 | Adkins [15] (p. 297): “aretê denoted and commends “excellence”, not “virtue”“; Urmson [16] (p. 30): “aretê: excellence or goodness of any kind. [...] aretê is commonly translated virtue, a transliteration of the Latin virtus, but neither aretê nor virtus means virtue, except in such archaising expressions as “the virtues of the internal combustion engine”. |
6 | Aristotle seems to see this the same way, see EN 1177b31-1178a4. |
7 | These appeared after the first draft of the present manuscript was written. |
8 | All italics in quotes are in the original, unless otherwise indicated. |
9 | An invention that seems to have come only after the development of complex societies [42] |
10 | I.e., appealing to a pessimistic induction on ethical theories analogous to the pessimistic induction in the philosophy of science. |
11 | For example, in the famous paper by Hardie [54]. |
12 | The second motivation they provide is the claim that the perception of science as value-free is misconceived—a claim that seems itself misconceived, see the previous subsection. |
13 | This problem seems somewhat similar to that often assigned to life-satisfaction accounts of wellbeing: that lowering expectations makes satisfaction easier to achieve. In fact, here it appears to be more serious, since adaptive expectations often make sense (overly unrealistic expectations tend to be bad for you), whereas lowering one’s potential seems dysfunctional in general. |
14 | I for my part can not even imagine how locusts taste to humans, even though they are being eaten by many. |
15 | About 1,504,000,000,000,000,000,000,000 according to https://www.quora.com/How-much-sand-is-in-Sahara-desert, accessed on 12 May 2022. |
16 | Daniel Dennett’s abbreviation for “Very much more than ASTronomical”, used to refer to “finite but almost unimaginably larger numbers than such merely astronomical quantities as the number of microseconds since the Big Bang times the number of electrons in the visible universe” [59] (ch.6 endnote 36). |
17 | Again this undefined “we.” |
18 | Note that Kraut does not restrict to realistic life spans. E.g., “There is nothing wrong, then, with McTaggart’s idea of a human life that lasts a million years” [58] (p. 228). |
19 | Personally, I find this particularly unfortunate since I do sympathize with much of what Kraut and also Haybron write. There might be something relevant to science in there; but as a scientist, I dislike the prospect of having to double check which of philosophers’ alleged arguments are actually reliable. |
20 | The use of p-values in psychology is controversial, but this does not invalidate the point: the difference is that statisticians have pointed to the intricacies in using p-values for decades but were widely ignored by psychologists (e.g, [65,66]), while philosophy-as-usual sweeps its problems under the rug. |
21 | Admittedly, there have been a number of studies of mindfulness in positive psychology; but see [73,74] for lacunas in this area and for the under-explored complications in the relationship between Buddhism and science. Additionally, parallels between the flow concept and the philosophy of the ZhuangZi have been noted occasionally (e.g., [21] (p. 150f), [75,76]), but not discussed in the context of the relationship between philosophy-as-usual and positive psychology. |
22 | A possible translation of dao [88] (p. 57). |
23 | Which apparently was among the original reasons to develop flow theory, compare the introduction to [20]. |
24 | Examples of optimal experience without action may be provided by meditative absorptions (jhānas), as even the first stages involve intense joy (pīti) and happiness (sukha) without anything that one would ordinarily call an activity. Compare, e.g., [89,90]. Aristotle would seem to agree: EN 1154b 26-28. |
25 | See [96] for a brief introduction and philosophical consequences. |
26 |
References
- Seligman, M.; Csikszentmihalyi, M. Positive psychology. An introduction. Am. Psychol. 2000, 55, 5–14. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed]
- Seligman, M.E. Positive Psychology: A Personal History. Annu. Rev. Clin. Psychol. 2019, 15, 1–23. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed] [Green Version]
- Alexandrova, A. A Philosophy for the Science of Well-Being; Oxford University Press: New York, NY, USA, 2017. [Google Scholar]
- Goodman, F.R.; Disabato, D.J.; Kashdan, T.B.; Kauffman, S.B. Measuring well-being: A comparison of subjective well-being and PERMA. J. Posit. Psychol. 2017, 13, 321–332. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Kashdan, T.B.; Biswas-Diener, R.; King, L.A. Reconsidering happiness: The costs of distinguishing between hedonics and eudaimonia. J. Posit. Psychol. 2008, 3, 219–233. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Kristjánsson, K. The flourishing—Happiness concordance thesis: Some troubling counterexamples. J. Posit. Psychol. 2018, 13, 541–552. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Thorsteinsen, K.; Vittersø, J. Now you see it, now you don’t: Solid and subtle differences between Hedonic and Eudaimonic Wellbeing. J. Posit. Psychol. 2020, 15, 519–530. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Vittersø, J. The Most Important Idea in the World: An Introduction. In Handbook of Eudaimonic Well-Being; Vittersø, J., Ed.; Springer International Publishing: New York, NY, USA, 2016. [Google Scholar]
- Intelisano, S.; Krasko, J.; Luhmann, M. Integrating Philosophical and Psychological Accounts of Happiness and Well-Being. J. Happiness Stud. 2020, 21, 161–200. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
- Overgaard, S.; Gilbert, P.; Burwood, S. An Introduction to Metaphilosophy; Cambridge University Press: Cambridge, UK, 2013. [Google Scholar]
- Nussbaum, M. Who Is the Happy Warrior? Philosophy Poses Questions to Psychology. J. Leg. Stud. 2008, 37, S81–S113. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Quine, W.V. Has philosophy lost contact with people? In Theories and Things; Harvard University Press: Cambridge, MA, USA, 1981. [Google Scholar]
- Dennett, D.C. Intuition Pumps and Other Tools for Thinking; Norton: New York, NY, USA, 2013. [Google Scholar]
- Slote, M. Taiji. Dao 2021, 20, 365–375. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Adkins, A.W. Theoria versus Praxis in the Nicomachean Ethics and the Republic. Class. Philol. 1978, 73, 297–313. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Urmson, J.O. The Greek Philosophical Vocabulary; Duckworth: London, UK, 1990. [Google Scholar]
- Annas, J. The phenomenology of virtue. Phenomenol. Cogn. Sci. 2008, 7, 21–34. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Annas, J. Intelligent Virtue; Oxford University Press: Oxford, UK, 2011. [Google Scholar]
- Besser-Jones, L. The motivational state of the virtuous agent. Philos. Psychol. 2012, 25, 93–108. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Csikszentmihalyi, M. Beyond Boredom and Anxiety: Experiencing Flow in Work and Play; Jossey-Bass: San Francisco, CA, USA, 1975. [Google Scholar]
- Csikszentmihalyi, M. Flow: The Psychology of Optimal Experience; Harper Perennial Modern Classics edition (2008); HarperCollins: New York, NY, USA, 1990. [Google Scholar]
- Csikszentmihalyi, M. Foreword. In Advances in Flow Research; Engeser, S.H., Ed.; Springer: New York, NY, USA, 2012. [Google Scholar]
- Csikszentmihalyi, M. If We Are So Rich, Why Aren’t We Happy? Am. Psychol. 1999, 54, 821–827. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Tse, D.C.K.; Nakamura, J.; Csikszentmihalyi, M. Living well by “flowing” well: The indirect effect of autotelic personality on well-being through flow experience. J. Posit. Psychol. 2021, 16, 310–321. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Moneta, G. On the Measurement and Conceptualization of Flow. In Advances in Flow Research; Engeser, S., Ed.; Springer: New York, NY, USA, 2012. [Google Scholar]
- Kawabata, M.; Mallett, C.J. What is flow? Reconsideration of the state of optimal functioning beyond flow theory. In Routledge International Handbook of Sport Psychology; Schinke, R.J., McGannon, K.R., Smith, B., Eds.; Routledge: Abingdon on Thames, UK, 2016. [Google Scholar]
- Landhäußer, A.; Keller, J. Flow and Its Affective, Cognitive, and Performance-Related Consequences. In Advances in Flow Research; Engeser, S.H., Ed.; Springer: New York, NY, USA, 2012. [Google Scholar]
- Fong, C.J.; Zaleski, D.J.; Leach, J.K. The challenge-skill balance and antecedents of flow: A meta-analytic investigation. J. Posit. Psychol. 2015, 10, 425–446. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Nakamura, J.; Dwight, C.; Shankland, S. Flow: The Experience of Intrinsic Motivation. In The Oxford Handbook of Human Motivation, 2nd ed.; Ryan, R.M., Ed.; Oxford Universty Press: Oxford, UK, 2019. [Google Scholar]
- Csikszentmihalyi, M. Optimal Experience: Psychological Studies of Flow in Consciousness; Cambridge University Press: Cambridge, UK, 1988. [Google Scholar]
- Delle Fave, A.; Bassi, M. Flow and Psychological Selection. In Flow and Psychological Selection; Harmat, L., Ørsted Andersen, F., Ullén, F., Wright, J., Sadlo, G., Eds.; Springer International Publishing: New York, NY, USA, 2016. [Google Scholar]
- Järvilehto, L. Intuition and Flow. In Flow Experience: Empirical Research and Applications; Harmat, L., Ørsted Andersen, F., Ullén, F., Wright, J., Sadlo, G., Eds.; Springer International Publishing: New York, NY, USA, 2016. [Google Scholar]
- Jackson, S. Flowing with mindfulness: Investigating the relationship between flow and mindfulness. In Mindfulness in Positive Psychology: The Science of Meditation and Wellbeing; Ivtzan, I., Lomas, T., Eds.; Routledge: Abingdon on Thames, UK, 2016. [Google Scholar]
- Bassi, M.; Fave, A.D. Flow in the Context of Daily Experience Fluctuation. In Flow Experience: Empirical Research and Applications; Harmat, L., Ørsted Andersen, F., Ullén, F., Wright, J., Sadlo, G., Eds.; Springer International Publishing: New York, NY, USA, 2016. [Google Scholar]
- Baumann, N. Autotelic Personality. In Advances in Flow Research; Engeser, S., Ed.; Springer: New York, NY, USA, 2012. [Google Scholar]
- Ullén, F.; de Manzano, Ö.; Almeida, R.; Magnusson, P.K.; Pedersen, N.L.; Nakamura, J.; Csíkszentmihályi, M.; Madison, G. Proneness for psychological flow in everyday life: Associations with personality and intelligence. Personal. Individ. Differ. 2012, 52, 167–172. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Abuhamdeh, S. Investigating the “Flow” Experience: Key Conceptual and Operational Issues. Front. Psychol. 2020, 11, 158. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Norsworthy, C.; Jackson, B.; Dimmock, J.A. Advancing our understanding of psychological flow: A scoping review of conceptualizations, measurements, and applications. Psychol. Bull. 2021, 147, 806–827. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- MacLeod, A. Well-Being: Objectivism, Subjectivism or Sobjectivism? J. Happiness Stud. 2015, 16, 1073–1089. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Keyes, C.L.M.; Annas, J. Feeling good and functioning well: Distinctive concepts in ancient philosophy and contemporary science. J. Posit. Psychol. 2009, 4, 197–201. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Mattes, J. Reports of the death of value-free science are greatly exaggerated. Rev. Philos. Psychol. 2019, 10, 689–699. Available online: https://doi-org.uaccess.univie.ac.at/10.1007/s13164-018-0426-z (accessed on 12 May 2022). [CrossRef] [Green Version]
- Whitehouse, H.; François, P.; Savage, P.E.; Currie, T.E.; Feeney, K.C.; Cioni, E.; Purcell, R.; Ross, R.M.; Larson, J.; Baines, J.; et al. Complex societies precede moralizing gods throughout world history. Nature 2019, 568, 226–229. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
- Prinzing, M.M. Positive psychology is value-laden—It’s time to embrace it. J. Posit. Psychol. 2021, 16, 289–297. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
- Mullen, B.; Atkins, J.L.; Champion, D.S.; Edwards, C.; Hardy, D.; Story, J.E.; Vanderklok, M. The false consensus effect: A meta-analysis of 115 hypothesis tests. J. Exp. Soc. Psychol. 1985, 21, 262–283. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Ross, L.; Greene, D.; House, P. The “false consensus effect”: An egocentric bias in social perception and attribution processes. J. Exp. Soc. Psychol. 1977, 13, 279–301. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Moeller, H.-G. The Moral Fool: A Case for Amorality; Columbia University Press: New York, NY, USA, 2009. [Google Scholar]
- Peters, U.; Honeycutt, N.; Block, A.D.; Jussim, L. Ideological diversity, hostility, and discrimination in philosophy. Philos. Psychol. 2020, 33, 511–548. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Schwitzgebel, E.; Cushman, F. Expertise in Moral Reasoning? Order Effects on Moral Judgment in Professional Philosophers and Non-Philosophers. Mind Lang. 2012, 27, 135–153. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Schwitzgebel, E.; Cushman, F. Philosophers’ biased judgments persist despite training, expertise and reflection. Cognition 2015, 141, 127–137. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Schwitzgebel, E. Do Ethicists Steal More Books. Philos. Psychol. 2009, 22, 711–725. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Schwitzgebel, E. Are Ethicists Any More Likely To Pay Their Registration Fees At Professional Meetings? Econ. Philos. 2013, 29, 371–380. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
- Schönegger, P.; Wagner, J. The moral behavior of ethics professors: A replication-extension in German-speaking countries. Philos. Psychol. 2019, 32, 532–559. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Fowers, B.J. Aristotle on Eudaimonia: On the Virtue of Returning to the Source. In Handbook of Eudaimonic Well-Being; Vittersø, J., Ed.; Springer: New York, NY, USA, 2016. [Google Scholar]
- Hardie, W.F.R. The Final Good in Aristotle’s Ethics. Philosophy 1965, 40, 277–295. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Smith, T.W. The Audience of the Nicomachean Ethics. J. Politics 2000, 62, 166–186. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Tessitore, A. Reading Aristotle’s Ethics: Virtue, Rhetoric, and Political Philosophy; State University of New York Press: Albany, NY, USA, 1996. [Google Scholar]
- Haybron, D.M. The Philosophical Basis of Eudaimonic Psychology. In Handbook of Eudaimonic Well-Being; Vittersø, J., Ed.; Springer International Publishing: Cham, Switzerland, 2016. [Google Scholar]
- Kraut, R. The Quality of Life: Aristotle Revised; Online; Oxford University Press: Oxford, UK, 2018. [Google Scholar]
- Dennett, D.C. From Bacteria to Bach and Back: The Evolution of Minds; Penguin Books: London, UK, 2018. [Google Scholar]
- Haybron, D.M. The Quality of Life: Aristotle Revised, by Richard Kraut. Mind 2020, 129, 947–956. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Machery, E. Philosophy within Its Proper Bounds; Oxford University Press: Oxford, UK, 2017. [Google Scholar]
- Machery, E. Responses to Herman Cappelen and Jennifer Nado. Philos. Stud. 2022, 179, 329–342. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Machery, E. Response to Alexander and Weinberg, Baz and Deutsch. Analysis 2021, 80, 771–788. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Brewer, T. The Retrieval of Ethics; Oxford University Press: Oxford, UK, 2009. [Google Scholar]
- Cohen, J. The earth is round (p < 0.05). Am. Psychol. 1994, 49, 997–1003. [Google Scholar]
- Wasserstein, R.L.; Lazar, N.A. The ASA Statement on p-Values: Context, Process, and Purpose. Am. Stat. 2016, 70, 129–133. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
- Melnikoff, D.E.; Bargh, J.A. The mythical number two. Trends Cogn. Sci. 2018, 22, 280–293. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Anscombe, G.E.M. Modern Moral Philosophy. Philosophy 1958, 33, 1–19. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Lee, J.H. The Ethical Foundations of Early Daoism: Zhuangzi’s Unique Moral Vision; Palgrave Macmillan: New York, NY, USA, 2014. [Google Scholar]
- Robertson, D. The Philosophy of Cognitive-Behavioural Therapy (CBT): Stoic Philosophy as Rational and Cognitive Psychotherapy; Karnac: London, UK, 2010. [Google Scholar]
- Slingerland Edward, G. Trying Not to Try: The Ancient Art of Effortlessness and the Surprising Power of Spontaneity; Canongate: Edinburgh, UK, 2014. [Google Scholar]
- Zhang, E. Forgetfulness and flow: “Happiness” in Zhuangzi’s Daoism. Sci. Relig. Cult. 2019, 6, 77–84. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Mattes, J. Systematic review and meta-analysis of correlates of FFMQ mindfulness facets. Front. Psychol. 2019, 10, 2684. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed] [Green Version]
- Mattes, J. Are we forgetting sati? Memory and the benefits of mindfulness from a non-Buddhist viewpoint. Mindfulness 2019, 10, 1703–1706. Available online: https://doi-org.uaccess.univie.ac.at/10.1007/s12671-019-01158-y (accessed on 12 May 2022). [CrossRef]
- Barrett, N. Wuwei and Flow: Comparative Reflections on Spirituality, Transcendence, and Skill in the Zhuangzi. Philos. East West 2011, 61, 679–706. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Graham, A.C. Chuang-Tzu: The Inner Chapters; Reprint Edition; Hackett: Indianapolis, IN, USA, 2001. [Google Scholar]
- Daniels, J.D. Uncarved and Unconcerned: Zhuangzian Contentment in an Age of Happiness. Dao 2019, 18, 577–596. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Machek, D. Stoics and Daoists on Freedom as Doing Necessary Things. Philos. East West 2018, 68, 174–200. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Fraser, C. Wandering the Way: A Eudaimonistic Approach to the Zhuāngzǐ. Dao 2014, 13, 541–565. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
- Locke, E.A.; Latham, G.P. The Development of Goal Setting Theory. Motiv. Sci. 2019, 5, 93–105. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Snyder, C.R. Hope Theory: Rainbows in the Mind. Psychol. Inq. 2002, 13, 249–275. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Duckworth, A.L.; Peterson, C.; Matthews, M.D.; Kelly, D.R. Grit: Perseverance and passion for long-term goals. J. Personal. Soc. Psychol. 2007, 92, 1087–1101. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Kuhl, J.; Quirin, M. Seven steps towards freedom and two ways to lose it: Overcoming limitations of intentionality through self-confrontational coping with stress. Soc. Psychol. 2011, 42, 74–84. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Grund, A.; Fries, S.; Rheinberg, F. Know your preferences: Self-regulation as need-congruent goal selection. Rev. Gen. Psychol. 2018, 22, 437–451. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Vallerand, R.J. The Psychology of Passion: A Dualistic Model; Oxford University Press: Oxford, UK, 2015. [Google Scholar]
- Vallerand, R.J.; Blanchard, C.; Mageau, G.A.; Koestner, R.; Ratelle, C.; Léonard, M.; Gagné, M.; Marsolais, J. Les passions de l’âme: On obsessive and harmonious passion. J. Pers. Soc. Psychol. 2003, 85, 756–767. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed] [Green Version]
- Hayes, S.C.; Strosahl, K.D.; Wilson, K.G. Acceptance and Commitment Therapy: The Process and Practice of Mindful Change, 2nd ed.; Guilford Press: New York, NY, USA, 2012. [Google Scholar]
- Ames, R.; Hall, D. Dao De Jing: A Philosophical Translation; Ballantine Books: New York, NY, USA, 2003. [Google Scholar]
- Brahm, A. Mindfulness, Bliss, and Beyond; Wisdom Publications: Boston, MA, USA, 2006. [Google Scholar]
- Bronkhorst, J. Absorption: Human Nature and Buddhist Liberation; University Media: Paris, France, 2012. [Google Scholar]
- Slingerland, E. Effortless Action: Wu-Wei as Conceptual Metaphor and Spiritual Ideal in Early China; Oxford University Press: New York, NY, USA, 2003; ISBN 978-0195314878. [Google Scholar]
- Kahneman, D. Thinking, Fast and Slow; Farrar, Straus and Giroux: New York, NY, USA, 2011. [Google Scholar]
- Evans, J.T.; Stanovich, K.E. Dual-Process theories of higher cognition: Advancing the debate. Perspect. Psychol. Sci. 2013, 8, 223–241. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed]
- Cseh, G.M. Flow in Creativity: A Review of Potential Theoretical Conflict. In Flow Experience: Empirical Research and Applications; Harmat, L., Ørsted Andersen, F., Ullén, F., Wright, J., Sadlo, G., Eds.; Springer International Publishing: New York, NY, USA, 2016. [Google Scholar]
- Doyle, C.L. Creative Flow as a Unique Cognitive Process. Front. Psychol. 2017, 8, 1348. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed] [Green Version]
- Mattes, J. ACT and Greek philosophy: What if your chosen valued-direction is ataraxia (undisturbedness, equanimity)? In Proceedings of the ACBS Virtual World Conference, Online, 24–27 June 2021. [Google Scholar]
- Ziporyn, B. Zhuangzi: The Complete Writings; Hackett Publishing Company, Inc.: Indianapolis, IN, USA, 2020. [Google Scholar]
- Stanovich, K. Rationality and the Reflective Mind; Oxford University Press: Oxford, UK, 2010. [Google Scholar]
- Gendlin, E.T. Experiencing and the Creation of Meaning: A Philosophical and Psychological Approach to the Subjective; Northwestern University Press: Evanston, IL, USA, 1997. [Google Scholar]
- Evans, J.S.B. Reflections on reflection: The nature and function of Type 2 processes in dual-process theories of reasoning. Think. Reason. 2019, 25, 383–415. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Neys, W.D. On Dual- and Single-Process Models of Thinking. Perspect. Psychol. Sci. 2021, 16, 1412–1427. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Baumann, N.; Kazén, M.; Quirin, M.; Koole, S.L. Why People Do the Things They Do: Building on Julius Kuhl’s Contributions to the Psychology of Motivation and Volition; Hogrefe: Göttingen, Germany, 2018. [Google Scholar]
- Kuhl, J. Motivation und Persönlichkeit: Interaktionen Psychischer Systeme; Hogrefe: Göttingen, Germany, 2001. [Google Scholar]
- Kuhl, J.; Kazén, M.; Quirin, M. La teoría de la interacción de sistemas de la personalidad (The Theory of Personality Systems Interactions (PSI)). Rev. Mex. De Psicol. 2014, 31, 90–99. [Google Scholar]
- Kuhl, J.; Baumann, N. Personality systems interactions (PSI theory): Toward a dynamic integration of personality theories. In The Handbook of Personality Dynamics and Processes; Rauthmann, J.F., Ed.; Academic Press: Cambridge, MA, USA, 2021; Chapter 27; pp. 709–730. [Google Scholar]
Publisher’s Note: MDPI stays neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations. |
© 2022 by the author. Licensee MDPI, Basel, Switzerland. This article is an open access article distributed under the terms and conditions of the Creative Commons Attribution (CC BY) license (https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/).
Share and Cite
Mattes, J. Positive Psychology and Philosophy-as-Usual: An Unhappy Match? Philosophies 2022, 7, 52. https://doi.org/10.3390/philosophies7030052
Mattes J. Positive Psychology and Philosophy-as-Usual: An Unhappy Match? Philosophies. 2022; 7(3):52. https://doi.org/10.3390/philosophies7030052
Chicago/Turabian StyleMattes, Josef. 2022. "Positive Psychology and Philosophy-as-Usual: An Unhappy Match?" Philosophies 7, no. 3: 52. https://doi.org/10.3390/philosophies7030052
APA StyleMattes, J. (2022). Positive Psychology and Philosophy-as-Usual: An Unhappy Match? Philosophies, 7(3), 52. https://doi.org/10.3390/philosophies7030052