Violence and Care: Fanon and the Ethics of Care on Harm, Trauma, and Repair
Abstract
:1. Introduction
2. Fanon’s Political Theory in Two Themes
2.1. Theme I: The Social-Political and the Psycho-Affective Realms
Specifically, Fanon argues that the colonial relation and anti-Black racism fundamentally structures the social-political and internal psycho-affective landscapes of all those involved. On the one hand, the very notion of ‘black people’ and ‘white people,’ and the hierarchy between them, is a consequence of colonial relations of power, as Fanon attests repeatedly throughout the text 2. Further, Fanon argues that the psychological outcome of this reproduction of a hierarchy of black and white is an internalized superiority complex by the colonizers and a corresponding internalized inferiority complex by the colonized. The integral relation between these ‘psycho-existential complexes’ and the colonial context are perhaps no better illustrated than in the first substantive chapter of the text, in which Fanon [3] (pp. 2–3) discusses the relationship between colonialism, racism, and language:The white man is locked in his whiteness.The black man in his blackness.We shall endeavour to determine the tendencies of this double narcissism and the motivations behind it.
The problem we shall tackle in this chapter is as follows: the more the Black Antillean assimilates the French language, the whiter he gets—i.e., the closer he comes to becoming a true human being. […] A man who possesses a language possesses as an indirect consequence the world expressed and implied by this language.All colonized people—in other words, people in whom an inferiority complex has taken root, whose local cultural originality has been committed to the grave—position themselves in relation to the civilizing language: i.e., the metropolitan culture. The more the colonized has assimilated the cultural values of the metropolis, the more he will have escaped the bush. The more he rejects the bush, the whiter he will become.
This brief passage is telling. The fact that the European is ‘surprised’ to hear such ‘good French’ reveals their superiority complex: in a colonial world, they have internalized their superiority, and language is one of the markers of this superiority. To hear, then, “a black man speaking correctly” is surprising in that it ruptures this psychic structuring principle (itself co-constituted by the colonial social-political context) of superiority. Simultaneously, the exasperation experienced by the black man upon encountering this surprise is tied to the ways in which the exchange foregrounds his ‘inferiority’. “To speak a language is to appropriate its world and culture” [3] (p. 21). When one encounters surprise at the sheer fact that one could appropriate a world and culture that is demarcated as superior to one’s own, one is reminded of said demarcation, of the reality that within such a system, one is constructed and positioned as inferior.The fact is that the European has a set idea of the black man, and there is nothing more exasperating than to hear: ‘How long have you lived in France? You speak such good French?’ […] There is nothing more sensational than a black man speaking correctly, for he is appropriating the white world.
The problem of colonialism involves, more precisely, ongoing attempts “to decipher the changing scale (measure, judgment) of a problem, event, identity, or action as it comes to be represented or framed in the shifting ratios and relations that exist between the realms of political and psycho-affective experience” [9] (p. xxxvii). Colonialism can only be assessed, and the behaviours of both colonizers and colonized can only be grasped, by foregrounding the ways in which the social-political realm and the psycho-affective realm are inextricably intertwined 3.The problem of colonization, therefore, comprises not only the intersection of historical and objective conditions but also man’s attitudes toward these conditions.[3] (p. 65)
2.2. Theme II: Violence
More simply, as Fanon [2] (p. 46) writes, “It is understandable how in such an atmosphere [i.e., colonial relations of domination] everyday life becomes impossible”.There is, first of all, the fact that the colonized person, […] perceives life not as a flowering or a development of an essential productiveness, but as a permanent struggle against an omnipresent death. This ever-menacing death is experienced as endemic famine, unemployment, a high death rate, an inferiority complex and the absence of any hope for the future.All this gnawing at the existence of the colonized tends to make of life something resembling an incomplete death.
While the violence of the colonized is necessarily a violence that responds to the violence of colonialism, and as such, it is inherently a reactive violence, it also must be a violence that recognizes “itself as the source of a new world, a new order” [6] (p. 96). Reflection, questioning, and understanding the conditions which give rise to the necessity of this violent release is of crucial import for Fanon’s vision of how this violence can lead to liberation. In their awareness of how things are—of the violence inflicted upon them, of the unjustness of their circumstance—the colonized are able to “skim over this absurd drama that others have staged” [3] (p. 174) and build a different world. The reflexive colonized subject will be able to direct meaningfully their violence toward the disruption and destruction of the social-political structure. Another passage from Black Skin, White Masks [3] (p. 80, emphasis in original) helps to demonstrate this point:It is through self-consciousness and renunciation, through a permanent tension of his freedom, that man can create the ideal conditions of existence for a human world.
In other words, the black man should no longer have to be faced with the dilemma ‘whiten or perish,’ but must become aware of the possibility of existence; in still other words, if society creates difficulties for him because of his colour, if I see in his dreams the expression of an unconscious desire to change colour, my objective will not be to dissuade him by advising him to ‘keep his distance’; on the contrary, once his motives have been identified, my objective will be to enable him to choose action (or passivity) with respect to the real source of the conflict, i.e., the social structure.
The violence of shattering a social-political structure, like colonialism, is undeniable. It will be a reordering of the world, and the opening up of productive possibilities for new worlds. When revolutionary violence is “purposeful, intentional, and oriented toward world-making” [8], “violence can be embodied in a creative way” [6] (p. 96) and it becomes associated with world making and creative genius that cannot yet be known [10]. Through this final phase of violence comes decolonization and horizons of possibility for a world without colonial oppression. This world is a future-oriented world, a world of freedom.Decolonization, which sets out to change the order of the world, is clearly an agenda for total disorder.
2.3. Themes I and II: The Productive Harmony of Violence, Context, and Subject
At the individual level, violence is a cleansing force. It rids the colonized of their inferiority complex, of their passive and despairing attitude. It emboldens them and restores their self-confidence.
2.4. An Accidental: ‘Colonial War and Mental Disorders’
Today the all-out national war of liberation waged by the Algerian people for seven years has become a breeding ground for mental disorders. […]These disorders last for months, wage a massive attack on the ego, and almost invariably leave behind a vulnerability virtually visible to the naked eye. In all evidence the future of these patients is compromised.[2] (pp. 182–4)
What these cases suggest is that the use of violence did not liberate those who fought against colonial relations, like this resistance fighter. Instead, violence ensnared these fighters in a cycle of violence, trauma, and harm. This chapter, I suggest, thereby disrupts many of Fanon’s political theoretical claims: “The idea that using violence may be a way to escape being in violence is countered by case after case in which people remain trapped in the violence they have inflicted and suffered” [6] (p. 98). Or, as Fanon [2] (p. 185) writes, “Our actions never cease to haunt us”.In a certain African country, independent for some years now, we had the opportunity of treating a patriot and former resistance fighter. The man, in his thirties, would come and ask us for advice and help, since he was afflicted with insomnia together with anxiety attacks and obsession with suicide around a certain date of the year. The critical date corresponded to the day he had been ordered to place a bomb somewhere. Ten people had perished during the attack.The circumstances surrounding the symptoms are interesting for several reasons. Several months after his country had gained independence he had made the acquaintance of nationals from the former colonizing nation. They became friends. These men and women welcomed the newly acquired independence and unhesitatingly paid tribute to the courage of the patriots in the national liberation struggle. The militant was then overcome by a kind of vertigo. He anxiously asked himself whether among the victims of his bomb there might have been individuals similar to his new acquaintances. It was true the bombed café was known to be the haunt of notorious racists, but nothing could stop any passerby from entering and having a drink. From that day on the man tried to avoid thinking of past events. But paradoxically a few days before the critical date the first symptoms would break out. They have been a regular occurrence ever since. [2] (pp. 184–5)
3. The Ethics of Care: Violence, Trauma, and Repair
3.1. A Critical, Political Ethics of Care
For this reason, the ethics of care must be a critical and political theory [14]. If moral subjects and moral knowledges are constituted in and by unique webs of social relations, a care ethical orientation to morality means that we must pay attention to how and why subjects and knowledges emerge in and through these unique relations, and especially to how power permeates all of this, shaping our needs, desires, and visions for living well. We must interrogate these relations critically, and seek to understand how they come to constitute what counts as morality as such and how they shape our moral understandings, our “moral forms of life” [18] (p. 105). Further, this is a collective task of mutual exchange, in which we listen and attempt to respond well to others so as to better meet their needs.This is not an abstract ethics about the application of rules, but a phenomenology of moral life which recognizes that addressing moral problems involves, first, an understanding of identities, relationships, and contexts, and second, a degree of social coordination and co-operation in order to try to answer questions and disputes about who cares for whom, and about how responsibilities will be discharged.[17] (p. 31)
Again, given our relational and therefore vulnerable being (in that we are vulnerable as finite, material, and embodied beings, and in that we are vulnerable to the social relations that constitute our subjectivities), care ethics orients us to the ongoing task of fostering relations that support life, that allow for repair, and that respond to needs and desires. At the same time, care ethics’ recognition of the multiplicity of moral selves and moral forms of life (a recognition which stems from its relational social ontology) means that what, exactly, is a need, and correspondingly, the content of ‘care’, cannot be taken for granted. As I have argued, alongside scholars like Kirsten Cloyes [20], care must be agonized. Different versions of care, heterogeneous understandings of needs, and divergent desires and interests must be deliberated on, and they will sometimes be at odds. A key moral task involves attempting to understand needs and forms of care that may be very different from our own, so that we may humbly and reflexively consider and adjudicate amongst competing visions of care. As Margaret Urban Walker [18] (p. 7) writes, “the justification of the moral understandings that are woven through a particular lifeway rests on the goods to be found in living it”. Care ethics, as an approach to moral thinking which prioritizes the good to be found in living any form of life, does not rely on universal principles to make moral claims and justifications. Instead, it “recasts moral deliberation as the difficult and messy task of attempting to decentre one’s own judgement (never fully possible) in an attempt to know the other (never fully possible) in an ongoing and iterative way” [14] (p. 143) so as to undertake the often “tough” [21] (p. 99) and pain-staking work of building and repairing relations that allow all to live as well as is reasonably possible [4] (p. 40) given our vulnerable embodiment and relational subjectivity.This ‘organizing trajectory’ is, to be sure, only thinly normative; how to be attentive and respond to a plurality of situated needs and heterogenous vulnerable moral selves cannot be predetermined or prescribed, only gleaned through tentative, and sometimes agonistic, practices of care which are continually assessed and revised. Nonetheless, what is of moral value from an ethics of care perspective is care, and the substance of moral practices is found in the ways in which we attempt, often through many iterations, to live well, to respond to needs, and to minimize harm and suffering.
3.2. Reconceiving Violence and Care: A Relational Approach
This maternal practice is very much in line with the ethics of care, which, as outlined above, is premised on a relational social ontology (and thus foregrounds our inescapable vulnerability) and a commitment to responding to this vulnerability with care. It is also because of this orientation that Ruddick has largely been read as a pacifist. Nurturing life, again, seems to be fundamentally at odds with violence. Yet, Frazer and Hutchings [7] (p. 116) suggest that Ruddick’s work is better conceived of along the lines of “non-violent peacemaking”. This difference may seem small, but it is salient. Like care ethics, Ruddick’s relational ethics suggests that all ethical dilemmas and moral quandaries must be examined critically in the context in which they emerge. This includes issues related to violence, and even the meaning of violence itself. As Frazer and Hutchings [7] (p. 119) write,Maternal practice begins with a double vision—seeing the fact of biological vulnerability as socially significant and as demanding care. […] To be committed to meeting children’s demand for preservation does not require enthusiasm or even love; it simply means to see vulnerability and to respond to it with care rather than abuse, indifference, or flight.
From the standpoint of maternal thinking [and, as I argue here, the ethics of care], a reliance on violence contradicts the immanent meaning of the practice of mothering [or care more broadly] and reproduces subjectivities for whom others are ‘killable’. Violence figures in [Ruddick’s] work as something that cuts, breaks or freezes the possibility of constructive relationships between those in conflict, both interpersonally and collectively. Non-violence by contrast preserves, maintains and creates constructive relationships between those in conflict, interpersonally and collectively.What follows from this is that a feminist peacemaker cannot make conclusive judgements relating to whether a particular set of strategies and tactics are either violent or non-violent outside of a holistic understanding of the conflict at issue. Further, an appreciation of the importance of position in relation to the means by which political struggles are being fought is needed.
An example of the former situation would be where systems of power, like colonial relations, make it difficult for some to meet their needs—often without the use of any direct force or violence. An example of the latter might very well be the type of violent revolution that Fanon envisions—a form of inflicting pain and injury so as to create ‘non-violence,’ meaning relations in which all, and particularly the least powerful, can flourish. From this point of view, care ethics, I suggest, is not necessarily opposed to Fanon’s violence; moreover, care ethics could perhaps help us assess Fanon’s claim about the efficacy of violence in specific contexts.stresses how the meaning of violence is not given simply by the infliction of pain and injury but also by the relations of power into which inflictions of pain and injury are introduced. [… This] opens up the possibility that some contexts that are apparently free of pain and injury may actually be violent, and some contexts in which pain and injury are inflicted may be non-violent, or at least not incompatible with non-violence.[7] (p. 120)
3.3. From Trauma and Towards Repair
Funding
Acknowledgments
Conflicts of Interest
Please note that I am relying on English translations of Fanon’s work in this article. | |
It is worth noting that Fanon is not reductionist in this sense; he also gives weight to the ways in which familial relations and interpersonal relations (which are, undeniably, also shaped by the social-political realm) can have serious effects on the individual’s psyche. In other words, Fanon does not locate all neurosis as coming from the colonial system, although his goal is to trace the many ways in which this system does fundamentally shape people’s psycho-affective landscapes. See, in particular, chapter 3 of Black Skin, White Masks [3]. | |
There are notable exceptions. Virginia Held [29] tackles the question of care ethics and violence directly, although in a way that is distinct from what has been argued here. For instance, while I have argued that a care ethics approach to understanding violence would entail investigating what practices constitute violence or non-violence within specific contexts, Held [29] (p. 126) spends less time interrogating these nuances and instead asserts that “violence damages and destroys what care labours to create”. Fiona Robinson’s [30] exploration of care ethics and human security is another important exception. Robinson expands notions of human security from a care ethics lens to reconsider what should count as ‘human security;’ in so doing, she implicitly expands on notions of violence, which are often conceived of narrowly and in terms of direct bodily harm within the international relations literature. |
References
- Fanon, F. A Dying Colonialism; Chevalier, H., Translator; Grove Press: New York, NY, USA, 1965. [Google Scholar]
- Fanon, F. The Wretched of the Earth; Philcox, R., Translator; Grove Press: New York, NY, USA, 2004. [Google Scholar]
- Fanon, F. Black Skins, White Masks; Philcox, R., Translator; Grove Press: New York, NY, USA, 2008. [Google Scholar]
- Fisher, B.; Tronto, J. Toward a Feminist Theory of Caring. In Circles of Care: Work and Identity in Women’s Lives; Abel, E.K., Nelson, M.K., Eds.; State University of New York Press: Albany, NY, USA, 1990; pp. 35–62. [Google Scholar]
- Ferrarese, E. Vulnerability: A Concept with Which to Undo the World as It Is? Crit. Horiz. A J. Philos. Soc. Theory 2016, 17, 149–159. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Frazer, E.; Hutchings, K. Revisiting Ruddick: Feminism, Pacifism and Non-violence. J. Int. Political Theory 2013, 10, 109–124. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Frazer, E. On Politics and Violence: Arendt Contra Fanon. Contemp. Political Theory 2008, 7, 90–108. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Drabinski, J. Frantz Fanon. In The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy; Zalta, E.N., Ed.; The Metaphysics Research Lab: Stanford, CA, USA, 2019; Available online: https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2019/entries/frantz-fanon (accessed on 15 March 2022).
- Bhaba, H. Foreword: Framing Fanon. In The Wretched of the Earth; Fanon, F., Author; Philcox, R., Translator; Grove Press: New York, NY, USA, 2004; pp. VII–XLI. [Google Scholar]
- Frazer, E.; Hutchings, K. Argument and Rhetoric in the Justification of Political Violence. Eur. J. Political Theory 2007, 6, 180–199. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Sartre, J.-P. Preface. In The Wretched of the Earth; Fanon, F., Author; Philcox, R., Translator; Grove Press: New York, NY, USA, 2004; pp. VII–XLI. [Google Scholar]
- Hamington, M. The Care Ethics Moment: International Innovations. Int. J. Care Caring 2018, 2, 309–318. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Sevenhujsen, S. Citizenship and the Ethics of Care: Feminist Considerations on Justice, Morality, and Politics; Routledge: London, UK, 1998. [Google Scholar]
- FitzGerald, M. Care and the Pluriverse: Rethinking Global Ethics; Bristol University Press: Bristol, UK, 2022. [Google Scholar]
- Hekman, S. Moral Voices, Moral Selves: Carol Gilligan and Feminist Moral Theory; The Pennsylvania State University Press: University Park, PA, USA, 1995. [Google Scholar]
- Robinson, F. Resisting Hierarchies through Relationality in the Ethics of Care. Int. J. Care Caring 2019, 4, 11–23. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Robinson, F. Globalizing Care: Ethics, Feminist Theory, and International Relations; Westview Press: Boulder, CO, USA, 1999. [Google Scholar]
- Walker, M.U. Moral Understandings: A Feminist Study in Ethics, 2nd ed.; Routledge: New York, NY, USA, 2007. [Google Scholar]
- Hamington, M. Politics is Not a Game: The Radical Potential of Care. In Care Ethics and Political Theory; Engster, D., Hamington, M., Eds.; Oxford University Press: Oxford, UK, 2015; pp. 272–292. [Google Scholar]
- Cloyes, K. Agonizing Care: Care Ethics, Agonistic Feminism and a Political Theory of Care. Nurs. Inq. 2002, 9, 203–214. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed]
- Noddings, N. Caring: A Feminine Approach to Ethics and Moral Education, 2nd ed.; University of California Press: Berkeley, CA, USA, 2003. [Google Scholar]
- Ruddick, S. Maternal Thinking: Towards a Politics of Peace; Beacon Press: Boston, MA, USA, 1989. [Google Scholar]
- Card, C. Gender and Moral Luck. In Justice and Care: Essential Readings in Feminist Ethics; Held, V., Ed.; Westview Press: Boulder, CO, USA, 1995; pp. 79–98. [Google Scholar]
- Clement, G. Care, Autonomy, and Justice: Feminism and The Ethic of Care; Routledge: New York, NY, USA, 1996. [Google Scholar]
- FitzGerald, M. Reimagining Government with the Ethics of Care: A Department of Care. Ethics Soc. Welf. 2020, 14, 248–265. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Tronto, J. Caring Democracy: Markets, Equality, and Justice; New York University Press: New York, NY, USA, 2013. [Google Scholar]
- Ghandeharian, S.; FitzGerald, M. COVID-19, the Trauma of the Real, and the Political Import of Vulnerability. Int. J. Care Caring 2022, 6, 33–47. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Harris, C.P. (Caring for) the World that Must be Undone. Contemp. Political Theory 2021, 20, 890–925. [Google Scholar]
- Held, V. Can the Ethics of Care Handle Violence? Ethics Soc. Welf. 2010, 4, 115–129. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Robinson, F. The Ethics of Care: A Feminist Approach to Human Security; Temple University Press: Philadelphia, PA, USA, 2011. [Google Scholar]
- Gibson, N.; Beneduce, R. (Eds.) Frantz Fanon, Psychiatry and Politics; Rowman & Littlefield: Lanham, MD, USA, 2017. [Google Scholar]
- Turner, L.; Neville, H. (Eds.) Frantz Fanon’s Psychotherapeutic Approaches to Clinical Work: Practicing Internationally with Marginalized Communities; Routledge: New York, NY, USA, 2019. [Google Scholar]
- Paré, É. A Theory of Actionality: Fanon, Racial Injuries and Existentialist Phenomenology. In Proceedings of the 2022 Canadian Political Science Association Annual Conference, Online, 30 May–3 June 2022. [Google Scholar]
Publisher’s Note: MDPI stays neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations. |
© 2022 by the author. Licensee MDPI, Basel, Switzerland. This article is an open access article distributed under the terms and conditions of the Creative Commons Attribution (CC BY) license (https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/).
Share and Cite
FitzGerald, M. Violence and Care: Fanon and the Ethics of Care on Harm, Trauma, and Repair. Philosophies 2022, 7, 64. https://doi.org/10.3390/philosophies7030064
FitzGerald M. Violence and Care: Fanon and the Ethics of Care on Harm, Trauma, and Repair. Philosophies. 2022; 7(3):64. https://doi.org/10.3390/philosophies7030064
Chicago/Turabian StyleFitzGerald, Maggie. 2022. "Violence and Care: Fanon and the Ethics of Care on Harm, Trauma, and Repair" Philosophies 7, no. 3: 64. https://doi.org/10.3390/philosophies7030064
APA StyleFitzGerald, M. (2022). Violence and Care: Fanon and the Ethics of Care on Harm, Trauma, and Repair. Philosophies, 7(3), 64. https://doi.org/10.3390/philosophies7030064