Armchair Evaluative Knowledge and Sentimental Perceptualism
Abstract
:1. Introduction
2. Sentimental Perceptualism and the Armchair
“In experiencing indignation at the harsh punishment of the toddler, it seems to you that the punishment is in fact unjust: your occurrent emotional state puts forward your indignation’s content as correct. This is in analogy to the content of a sense perception. In perceiving that the cat is on the mat, it seems to you that the cat is actually there.” [21] (p. 377)
3. Deepening the Challenge for Sentimental Perceptualism
4. Overcoming Two Problems at Once
4.1. The Content Challenge
“Compare the question of how your greenish perceptual experiences get to be about green, rather than about some other thing, such as orange or square. There is great disagreement in the theory of content determination about just how this happens. But there is widespread agreement that it doesn’t happen simply by magic. Your perceptual state has to somehow latch on to green.” [14] (pp. 127–128)
4.2. How to Answer the Content Challenge
“Organisms like bacteria, amoebae, paramecia, worms, molluscs, clams are differentially sensitive to various attributes in the physical environment. They discriminate those attributes. Their sensory capacities carry information. They function to respond in certain ways, given this information…These sensory capacities are not perceptual.” [47] (p. 315)
He later continues:
“Where there is perception, there is sensory information registration. That is, where there is perception, there is functional, causally based, usually high statistical correlation, between a type of state impacted by surface stimulation (and that encodes surface stimulation), on one hand, and a type of stimulation, on the other.” [47] (p. 317)
4.3. Answering the Content Challenge
4.3.1. Causation and Covariation
4.3.2. Biological Function
“In experiencing indignation at the harsh punishment of the toddler, it seems to you that the punishment is in fact unjust: your occurrent emotional state puts forward your indignation’s content as correct. This is in analogy to the content of a sense perception. In perceiving that the cat is on the mat, it seems to you that the cat is actually there.” [21] (p. 377)
“Very roughly, the phenomenology of feeling sad about something, which involves negative affect, experientially represents that that something is of disvalue.” [82] (p. 46)
“The person in an emotional state, like the person describing what he sees, largely describes the part of the world that, in her emotion, she is attending to. She says, “The dirty bastard took me for all I had” or “This is a wonderful day!” or “He’s always gazing at other women with that famished look”…Just as the person who is reporting on his visual impressions most often tells you what he sees, the person reporting on his emotions most often tells you how the world appears to him.” [7] (pp. 72–73)
4.4. Extending the Story to Offline Affect and Answering the Armchair Challenge
Psychologists as diverse as Laurence Kohlberg and Jonathan Haidt have taken this innate structure to be wholly, or at least in large part, affective.56“[T]here must be an irreducible core set of initial, evolved, architecture-derived content-specific valuation assignment procedures, or the system could not get started. The debate cannot sensibly be over the necessary existence of this core set. The real debate is over how large the core set must be, and what the proper computational description of these valuation procedures and their associated motivational circuitry is.” [88] (p. 317)
5. Conclusions
Funding
Institutional Review Board Statement
Informed Consent Statement
Data Availability Statement
Acknowledgments
Conflicts of Interest
1 | Sentimental perceptualism became especially prominent in 17th–18th century Great Britain, due especially to the influence of the Third Earl of Shaftesbury [1] and Francis Hutcheson [2]. The view was further developed in the 19th and early 20th centuries by Franz Brentano [3] and Alexius Meinong [4]. For contemporary proponents, see, among others, Mark Johnston [5], Graham Oddie [6], Robert Roberts [7], and Christine Tappolet [8]. Notably, some theorists prefer to think of desires and emotions as responses to perceptual-like feelings of value rather than as perceptual-like themselves [9,10]. Theorists drawn to this model should feel free to translate my arguments accordingly. |
2 | Williamson [11] questions the importance of the distinction between a priori and a posteriori knowledge. Nothing that I argue here, however, requires any assumptions about the nature or significance of this distinction. Instead, the real challenge for sentimental perceptualists is to explain the way in which we seem to be able to acquire evaluative knowledge by mere reflection, and in a way that preserves the perceptualist ambitions of the theory, however that knowledge is ultimately classified. |
3 | See Tropman [13] on ‘appearance intuitionism’ and ‘rationalist intuitionism’, both of which ground evaluative knowledge in the intellect (rather than affect) and thus count as rationalist on my taxonomy. |
4 | On how best to think about basic justification—as well as related notions such as non-inferential justification and immediate justification—see [16]. However, as we will see, the armchair challenge is a challenge to capture a certain pretheoretical intuition about evaluative inquiry, not a challenge to show that such knowledge from the armchair counts as basic on some inevitably controversial definition of ‘basic’. |
5 | Perceptualists may allow for many different kinds of value experience, though considerations of simplicity and unity require caution in doing so [17]. |
6 | Not all rationalists are perceptualists, however. Some (e.g., [18]) argue that there’s no need to appeal to intellectual experiences to explain evaluative knowledge. Instead, evaluative knowledge is grounded in non-experiential understanding of the evaluative propositions that we know. For discussion of this non-perceptualist view, and how it compares to the perceptualist alternative, see [13]. It is also worth noting that Audi has more recently assigned a prominent role to evaluative experiences of various sorts [19]. |
7 | There is a distinction between those who maintain that affective experiences have evaluative content and those who still treat such experiences as evaluative but locate the evaluation outside the content (e.g., [15,22]). Although proponents of the latter view agree that affect involves an evaluation, their picture is not compatible with sentimental perceptualism as defined here. Still, proponents of this cousin of sentimental perceptualism face the armchair challenge, if they want their theory to be provide a basis for evaluative knowledge, and so they may (in principle) find aspects of the solution I offer congenial. |
8 | Interestingly, the example of the politician indicates that evaluative inquiry is often an impure mix of armchair and non-armchair inquiry. Suppose that I have a strong reason to vote for the politician and that it would be good if the politician were president. Since the reason is instantiated, a recognition of it would not qualify as armchair inquiry. Learning about this reason might help me to determine whether it would be good if the politician were president. Such impure cases may be less challenging for sentimental perceptualists insofar as the agent has some perceptual-like interaction with a part of the relevant evaluative landscape. In any case, the view that I propose below does not exploit this potential advantage and works even for ‘pure’ cases. |
9 | |
10 | I have in mind imaginings that are analogues of perception as well as of belief; see [26] (p. 734). |
11 | I do not mean to indicate that either McGrath or myself maintains that online experiences are never privileged over offline ones. For example, Alison Jaggar’s discussion of ‘outlaw emotions’ offers one illustration of why lived experience should sometimes take epistemic priority [28]. I briefly flag how my view might begin to accommodate this in n62, though I leave a detailed exploration of this matter to another occasion. See also [27] for important and helpful discussion. |
12 | Such a perceptualist can still maintain that we can acquire analytic evaluative knowledge by mere reflection. Although it often goes without saying, perceptualist theories are meant to explain substantive knowledge [29]. |
13 | I do not take myself to have said anything definitive against an empiricist model according to which our online evaluative experiences are always privileged over our offline experiences. However, in my view, this should be a fallback position in the event that an adequate solution to the armchair challenge cannot be found. |
14 | It has been put to me in conversation that one might hold that, while evaluative reflection does not put us into causal contact with any instantiated evaluative property, it does put us into contact with, say, goodness, wrongness, etc. as such. For many existing sentimental perceptualist theories (e.g., [6]), such a view would generate a peculiar asymmetry between armchair and non-armchair evaluative inquiry–since no sentimental perceptualists believe that it is wrongness, goodness, etc. as such that cause our online affective responses. Moreover, I know of no sentimental perceptualists who have ever tried to defend such an asymmetrical theory (though admittedly they are largely silent about armchair inquiry in general). The sentimental perceptualist theory that I propose maintains as close of a symmetry between armchair and non-armchair inquiry as I think can be expected for those who take the armchair challenge seriously. |
15 | |
16 | |
17 | It is important to be clear that my point here is not that it is epistemically possible from Jacqueline’s perspective that she is wrong (though that may be true). My point is that the full content of Jacqueline’s anger, which includes evaluative content combined with content supplied by other mental states (cf. [22] on the notion of a “cognitive base”), is only contingently true. One reason for this is that there are metaphysically possible worlds in which Sydney uncaringly stomps on her toe but does not wrong her; in those worlds, it will not be true that Sydney wrongs her by uncaringly stomping on her toe. Thanks to an anonymous reviewer for pushing me to clarify this point. |
18 | I am not talking about predictions of how one would feel if something happened. For a sentimental perceptualist, such predictions are at best a highly indirect route to evaluative knowledge. |
19 | Philosophers of mind debate about whether offline affective responses to imaginings and fictions are the same mental state types as their online counterparts [38,39]. I believe my arguments can be adapted to relevant plausible ways in which philosophers have argued that they are not, but I will not be able to explore these matters in depth here. |
20 | For more detail on what sorts of propositions we might come to know through imaginative reflection, see Section 4.4. |
21 | One could insist that an affective response only grounds evaluative knowledge if it is responsive to conditions that necessitate the presence of the relevant evaluative property. I suspect that such a picture will lead to the result that, on a sentimental perceptualist theory, we almost never have evaluative knowledge; in any case, I think that this approach sets the bar on evaluative knowledge too high (see [35]). However, the explanation of armchair knowledge that I offer below could be paired with the idea that affective experiences only ground knowledge if they are responsive to conditions that guarantee the presence of the target evaluative property. |
22 | Kripke famously argues that we can have contingent a priori knowledge that the standard meter stick is one meter long [40], but this does not provide a useful model for sentimental perceptualists. For one, the knowledge in Kripke’s case is grounded in our understanding of ‘meter’, and sentimental perceptualists are not trying to explain semantic evaluative knowledge. For a more detailed discussion about why we should be skeptical about building a value epistemology (cf. [41] (pp. 161–162)). |
23 | I do not mean to suggest that these two approaches are exhaustive. Most notably, I set aside what are sometimes called “short-arm” and “long-arm” functional role theories [45,46]. Versions of the former do not include the external environment as part of the role and generally appeal to inferential roles, specifically. Such views strike me as better suited for explaining the contents of beliefs rather than perceptions. I am moreover persuaded by Mendelovici that these theories struggle more obviously than others in explaining how contents arise in the first place, even if they can explain how we get more complex contents from already existing contents [45] (pp. 72–76). One might (controversially) think that long-arm functionalism can overcome this difficulty, but the most natural way to do so is by appealing to the kinds of relations involved in tracking theories [45] (pp. 76–79). What I say below will thus be relevant to theorists drawn to this approach. |
24 | My own leanings are increasingly in the direction of phenomenal intentionality as explaining original (underived) intentionality. See especially the considerations outlined in [45] (pp. 79–80, 90–93). |
25 | Kriegel makes this point with respect to what he calls objective and subjective representation, a conceptual contrast that I set aside for the purposes of this paper [43] (p. 162). As Kriegel notes, tracking theories appear suited for targeting objective representation while phenomenal intentionality theories appear suited for targeting subjective representation. |
26 | A phenomenal intentionalist may prefer to say that representation is more precisely of ‘the manifest kind property of being “apple-y” (or perhaps that of playing the apple role)’ [43] (p. 163). |
27 | Mendelovici [45] argues that certain perceptual experiences (e.g., color experiences) always misrepresent and so fail to track what they are about. While Mendelovici’s view merits careful study, I cannot carry out that project here. I assume that our everyday perceptual experiences are not subject to widespread, systematic error. |
28 | |
29 | |
30 | |
31 | |
32 | On this approach, the explanation for why an animal represents the shape and color of some fruit appeals to the fact that the animal’s behavior is counterfactually sensitive to the presence of such fruit; all else equal, it eats all and only fruit of that shape and color. |
33 | Peacocke asks, ‘Is biological function not merely evidentially or epistemically relevant to the determination of content, but constitutively involved as a matter of the very nature of perceptual representation itself?’ [54] (p. 477). The assumption—which seems to me correct–is that biological function is at least evidential. |
34 | A major forerunner to Oddie’s argument is Sturgeon [55]. |
35 | Prinz [56] offers a helpful starting point for similar arguments centering emotions. |
36 | I do not mean to commit to any analysis of causation. It is sufficient for my purposes that commensurateness functions as a useful test for causal relations. |
37 | Oddie is adapting some ideas from Yablo [57] on mental causation. Oddie and Yablo actually use ‘contingent’ rather than ‘dependent’. I tweak their language in order to avoid confusion, since the way in which I use ‘contingent’ elsewhere in this paper is different. |
38 | Following Oddie, I have used counterfactuals to characterize commensurateness. This is a heuristic. The best way to understand commensurateness (as well as causation) is presumably in non-counterfactual terms [6] (p. 195). |
39 | |
40 | A reader might wonder why Oddie’s opponent cannot just construct a disjunction of possible specific ways the natural world could have been so that the disjunction includes all and only the specific ways the world could have been sufficient to produce the desire. The claim would then be that the desire is dependent on this disjunctive property. Oddie is aware of this objection, and his reply is that the grotesque disjunction would not really be a property and so cannot be a cause. This is a reasonable response to the objection, I believe. However, note that even if it is not, it does not immediately follow that values (e.g., reasons) cannot be causes if the long disjunction is just another way of picking out the reason. |
41 | |
42 | One may worry that the relation of being a reason is not really adequate to the desire, since we can imagine versions of the case in which the hiker’s situation favors helping but not in a way that leads to the desire. Strictly speaking, we should speak of reasons within a certain range. However, this is not a surprising qualification. An object’s squareness can cause a visual representation as of its being square, but of course, strictly speaking, what we normally mean is squareness within a certain range (the square object needs to be within a certain size range, for example). |
43 | According to Prinz, some emotions which are blends of basic emotions were selected for, too [53] (p. 76). For example, contempt, which he takes to be a blend of anger and disgust, may be such a case. In fact, some evolutionary psychologists maintain that all emotion types are suspeptible to evolutionary explanation [63] (pp. 45–47). |
44 | This passage is quoted from Jessica Tracy and Daniel Randles’ overview of the contributions to a special issue of Emotion Review on basic emotions [64]. As they observe, each contributor accepts this way of thinking about basic affect and also agrees that such affect exists [65,66,67,68]. For some philosophers who accept a similar thesis, see [37,53,69]. By contrast, social constructivists deny that emotions are rooted in such affect programs (e.g., [70]). However, this would not entail that more primitive, pre-emotional forms of affect are not rooted in the sorts of affect programs others see as the biological basis of emotions (cf. [5]). In any case, social constructivist approaches to emotion face what appear to me to be severe difficulties [71]. |
45 | Artiga [74] makes this point in a reply to Street [75]. The reply is really a very simple one. The core of the response is simply to point out the typical kinds of descriptions which are offered by psychologists, cognitive neuroscientists, and biologists for how perceptual capacities evolve (e.g., Comer and Leung’s description of how cockroaches came to sense predators [76]). |
46 | |
47 | The appropriate sort of action will vary depending on the nature of V. |
48 | Street’s main target is non-naturalist moral realism, which includes commitments to moral value’s irreducibility and causal inefficacy [75] (p. 111). She only briefly considers the extent to which her arguments extend to a view on which value properties are causally efficacious. Thus nothing that I say here responds to the core of Street’s widely cited paper. |
49 | |
50 | See [79,80]. For philosophers who use similar language, see [56,81]. Many psychologists believe that emotions involve appraisals, which are defined as representations of how something or other bears on well-being, paradigmatically the well-being of the appraiser. In the case of basic emotions, the appraisals have the function of responding to some class of considerations that bear on well-being. |
51 | |
52 | |
53 | Of course, an opponent might predict that the science will not turn out as the sentimental perceptualist hopes. One complication is that showing this to be the case would seem to require making certain normative assumptions about what is or is not valuable (see [85]). |
54 | This assumption is natural in light of the way in which we ordinarily talk about offline affect. We do not have two different classes of affect terms, for example. However, even if offline analogues of online affect are a subtly different attitude, it does not follow that the present project is undermined. It would depend on the details of why they are treated as different attitudes. See also n19 above. |
55 | Marcus’ understanding of innateness is also adopted by Haidt and Joseph [87], among others. |
56 | Haidt and Joseph compare their own view to that of Kohlberg (as well as Piaget before him) [87] (p. 374). |
57 | In earlier work with Hichem Naar, we briefly raise and explore the intersection of (what I refer to here) as the content and armchair challenges [62] (pp. 3090–3094). The overarching aim of that paper was to address a different problem for sentimental perceptualism (roughly, about how affect could offer perceptual-like access to value insofar as affect responds to other mental states). The present paper takes on the armchair and content challenges in focused and systematic fashion; furthermore, while much of what I say is in the spirit of the earlier remarks, some shifts (as indicated above) have emerged in my thinking. |
58 | For a detailed exploration of how imagination represents its content, see [89] (pp. 184–194). |
59 | On the idea of perceptual experiences representing their contents as real, see [89]. |
60 | See Naar [90] for detailed references. Naar ultimately thinks that treating fittingness as accuracy is misguided. I also note that I have myself proposed that sentimental perceptualists should think of fittingness as accuracy, which is why I previously rejected the sort of suggestion favored here about the content of affect in response to imaginings [62] (p. 3091). |
61 | I defend this view in greater length elsewhere [91]. |
62 | The proposal here may allow for a principled explanation of why lived experience can sometimes have epistemic priority over detached evaluative reflection (cf. [28,92]). In the former case, there is the possibility of changing affective tendencies through causal interaction with value. For reasons of space, I am unable to further explore this line of thought here. See also n11 above. |
63 |
References
- Cooper, A.A. An Inquiry Concerning Virtue, or Merit (selections). In British Moralists 1650–1800: Hobbes-Gay; Raphael, D.D., Ed.; Hackett: Indianapolis, IN, USA, 1991; pp. 169–188. [Google Scholar]
- Hutcheson, F. An Inquiry Concerning the Original of Our Ideas of Virtue or Moral Good (selections). In British Moralists 1650–1800: Hobbes-Gay; Raphael, D.D., Ed.; Hackett: Indianapolis, IN, USA, 1991; pp. 261–299. [Google Scholar]
- Brentano, F. The Origins of Our Knowledge of Right and Wrong; Chisholm, R.; Schneewind, E., Translators; Routledge: London, UK, 1969. [Google Scholar]
- Meinong, A. On Emotional Presentation; Kalsi, S.M., Translator; Northwestern University Press: Evanston, IL, USA, 1972. [Google Scholar]
- Johnston, M. The authority of affect. Philos. Phenomenol. Res. 2001, 63, 181–214. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Oddie, G. Value, Reality, and Desire; Oxford University Press: New York, NY, USA, 2005. [Google Scholar]
- Roberts, R. Emotions in the Moral Life; Cambridge University Press: New York, NY, USA, 2013. [Google Scholar]
- Tappolet, C. Emotions, Values, and Agency; Oxford University Press: New York, NY, USA, 2016. [Google Scholar]
- Müller, J.M. Perceptualism and the epistemology of normative reasons. Synthese 2020, 199, 3557–3586. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Naar, H. Emotion: More like action than perception. Erkenntnis 2022, 87, 2715–2744. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Williamson, T. How deep is the distinction between a priori and a posteriori knowledge? In The A Priori in Philosophy; Casullo, A., Thurow, J.C., Eds.; Oxford University Press: New York, NY, USA, 2013; pp. 291–312. [Google Scholar]
- Huemer, M. Ethical Intuitionism; Palgrave MacMillan: New York, NY, USA, 2005. [Google Scholar]
- Tropman, E. Varieties of moral intuitionism. J. Value Inq. 2014, 48, 177–194. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Schroeder, M. How does the good appear to us? Soc. Theory Pract. 2008, 34, 119–130. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Schafer, K. Perception and the rational force of desire. J. Philos. 2013, 110, 258–281. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Cowan, R. Clarifying ethical intuitionism. Eur. J. Philos. 2015, 23, 1097–1116. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
- Väyrynen, P. Doubts about moral perception. In Evaluative Perception; Bergqvist, A., Cowan, R., Eds.; Oxford University Press: New York, NY, USA, 2018; pp. 109–128. [Google Scholar]
- Audi, R. Moderate intuitionism and the epistemology of moral judgment. Ethical Theory Moral Pract. 1998, 1, 15–44. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Audi, R. Moral Perception; Princeton University Press: Princeton, NJ, USA, 2013. [Google Scholar]
- McBrayer, J. A limited defense of moral perception. Philos. Stud. 2010, 149, 305–320. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Döring, S. Seeing what to do: Affective perception and rational motivation. Dialectica 2007, 69, 363–394. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Deonna, J.; Teroni, F. The Emotions: A Philosophical Introduction; Routledge: New York, NY, USA, 2012. [Google Scholar]
- Foot, P. The problem of abortion and the doctrine of double effect. Oxf. Rev. 1967, 5, 5–15. [Google Scholar]
- Kind, A. Imagining under constraints. In Knowledge Through Imagination; Kind, A., Kung, P., Eds.; Oxford University Press: New York, NY, USA, 2016; pp. 145–159. [Google Scholar]
- Williamson, T. Knowing by imagining. In Knowledge Through Imagination; Kind, A., Kung, P., Eds.; Oxford University Press: New York, NY, USA, 2016; pp. 113–123. [Google Scholar]
- Arcangeli, M. Interacting with emotions: Imagination and supposition. Philos. Q. 2017, 67, 730–750. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- McGrath, S. Moral knowledge and experience. In Oxford Studies in Metaethics 6; Schafer-Landau, R., Ed.; Oxford University Press: New York, NY, USA, 2011; pp. 107–127. [Google Scholar]
- Jaggar, A. Love and knowledge: Emotion in feminist epistemology. Inquiry 1989, 32, 151–176. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Milona, M. On the epistemological significance of value perception. In Evaluative Perception: Aesthetic, Ethical, and Normative; Bergqvist, A., Cowan, R., Eds.; Oxford University Press: New York, NY, USA, 2018; pp. 200–218. [Google Scholar]
- Armstrong, D. Belief, Truth, and Knowledge; Cambridge University Press: New York, NY, USA, 1973. [Google Scholar]
- Lewis, D. On the Plurality of Worlds; Basil Blackwell: Malden, MA, USA, 1986. [Google Scholar]
- Bengson, J. Grasping the third realm. In Oxford Studies in Epistemology 5; Tamar Szabo Gendler, T., Hawthorne, J., Eds.; Oxford University Press: New York, NY, USA, 2015; pp. 1–38. [Google Scholar]
- Väyrynen, P. Some good and bad news for ethical intuitionism. Philos. Q. 2008, 58, 489–511. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
- Milona, M. Intellect versus affect: Finding leverage in an old debate. Philos. Stud. 2017, 174, 2251–2276. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Lord, E. How to learn about aesthetics and morality through acquaintance and deference. In Oxford Studies in Metaethics 13; Shafer-Landau, R., Ed.; Oxford University Press: New York, NY, USA, 2018; pp. 71–97. [Google Scholar]
- Ellsworth, P. Levels of thought and levels of emotion. In The Nature of Emotion; Ekman, P., Davidson, R., Eds.; Oxford University Press: New York, NY, USA, 1994; pp. 192–196. [Google Scholar]
- Brady, M. Emotional Insight: The Epistemic Role of Emotional Experience; Oxford University Press: New York, NY, USA, 2013. [Google Scholar]
- Doggett, T.; Egan, A. How we feel about terrible, non-existent Mafiosi. Philos. Phenomenol. Res. 2012, 84, 277–306. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Mitchell, J. Two irreducible classes of emotional experiences: Affective imaginings and affective perceptions. Eur. J. Philos. 2022, 30, 307–325. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Kripke, S. Naming and Necessity; Harvard University Press: Cambridge, MA, USA, 1980. [Google Scholar]
- McKeever, S.; Ridge, M. Principled Ethics: Generalism as a Regulative Ideal; Oxford University Press: New York, NY, USA, 2006. [Google Scholar]
- Tenenbaum, S. Appearances of the Good: An Essay on the Nature of Practical Reason; Cambridge University Press: New York, NY, USA, 2007. [Google Scholar]
- Kriegel, U. Two notions of mental representation. In Current Controversies in Philosophy of Mind; Kriegel, U., Ed.; Routledge: New York, NY, USA, 2013; pp. 161–179. [Google Scholar]
- Mendelovici, A.; Bourget, D. Naturalizing intentionality: Tracking theories versus phenomenal intentionality theories. Philos. Compass 2014, 9, 325–337. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
- Mendelovici, A. The Phenomenal Basis of Intentionality; Oxford University Press: New York, NY, USA, 2018. [Google Scholar]
- Harman, G. (Non-solipsistic) conceptual role semantics. In New Directions in Semantics; Lepore, E., Ed.; Academic Press: London, UK, 1987; pp. 55–81. [Google Scholar]
- Burge, T. The Origins of Objectivity; Oxford University Press: New York, NY, USA, 2010. [Google Scholar]
- Dretske, F. Naturalizing the Mind; Cambridge University Press: New York, NY, USA, 1995. [Google Scholar]
- Neander, K. Teleological theories of mental content. In The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy; Zalta, E.N., Ed.; Spring 2012 Edition; Available online: http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2012/entries/content-teleological/ (accessed on 4 June 2023).
- Neander, K. Toward an informational teleosemantics. In Millikan and Her Critics; Kingsbury, J., Ryder, D., Williford, K., Eds.; Blackwell: Malden, MA, USA, 2013; pp. 21–40. [Google Scholar]
- Millikan, R. Language, Thought and Other Biological Categories; MIT Press: Cambridge, MA, USA, 1984. [Google Scholar]
- Papineau, D. Representation and explanation. Philos. Sci. 1984, 51, 550–572. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Prinz, J. The Emotional Construction of Morals; Oxford University Press: New York, NY, USA, 2007. [Google Scholar]
- Peacocke, C. Perception, biology, action, and knowledge. Philos. Phenomenol. Res. 2014, 88, 477–484. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Sturgeon, N. Moral explanations. In Morality, Reason and Truth; Copp, D., Zimmerman, D., Eds.; Rowman and Allenheld: Totowa, NJ, USA, 1985; pp. 49–78. [Google Scholar]
- Prinz, J. Gut Reactions: A Perceptual Theory of Emotions; Oxford University Press: New York, NY, USA, 2004. [Google Scholar]
- Yablo, S. Mental causation. Philos. Rev. 1992, 101, 245–280. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Milona, M.; Schroeder, M. Desiring under the proper guise. In Oxford Studies in Metaethics 14; Shafer-Landau, R., Ed.; Oxford University Press: New York, NY, USA, 2019; pp. 121–143. [Google Scholar]
- Scanlon, T.M. What We Owe to Each Other; Harvard University Press: Cambridge, MA, USA, 1998. [Google Scholar]
- Gregory, A. Desire as Belief: A Study of Desire, Motivation, and Rationality; Oxford University Press: New York, NY, USA, 2021. [Google Scholar]
- Wedgwood, R. Sensing values. Philos. Phenomenol. Res. 2001, 63, 215–223. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Milona, M.; Naar, H. Sentimental perceptualism and the challenge from cognitive bases. Philos. Stud. 2020, 177, 3071–3096. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Tappolet, C. Philosophy of Emotion: A Contemporary Introduction; Routledge: New York, NY, USA, 2022. [Google Scholar]
- Tracy, J.; Randles, D. Four models of basic emotions: A review of Ekman and Cordaro, Izard, Levenson, and Panksepp and Watt. Emot. Rev. 2011, 3, 397–405. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
- Ekman, P.; Cordaro, D. What is meant by calling emotions basic. Emot. Rev. 2011, 3, 364–370. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Izard, C.E. Forms and functions of emotions: Matters of emotion–cognition interactions. Emot. Rev. 2011, 3, 371–378. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Levenson, R. Basic emotion questions. Emot. Rev. 2011, 3, 379–386. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Panksepp, J.; Watt, D. What is basic about basic emotions? Lasting lessons from affective neuroscience. Emot. Rev. 2011, 3, 387–396. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- D’Arms, J.; Jacobson, D. The significance of recalcitrant emotion (or, anti-quasijudgmentalism). In Philosophy and the Emotions; Hatzimoysis, A., Ed.; Cambridge University Press: Cambridge, UK, 2003; pp. 127–146. [Google Scholar]
- Barrett, L.F. How Emotions Are Made: The Secret Life of the Brain; Houghton Mifflin Harcourt: New York, NY, USA, 2017. [Google Scholar]
- Kurth, C. Are emotions psychological constructions? Philos. Sci. 2019, 86, 1127–1238. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
- Blackburn, S. How to be an ethical antirealist. Midwest Stud. Philos. 1988, 12, 361–375. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Nesse, R. Evolutionary explanations of emotions. Hum. Nat. 1990, 1, 261–289. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed] [Green Version]
- Artiga, M. Rescuing tracking theories of morality. Philos. Stud. 2015, 172, 3357–3374. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Street, S. A Darwinian dilemma for realist theories of value. Philos. Stud. 2006, 127, 109–166. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Comer, C.; Leung, V. The vigilance of the hunted: Mechanosensoryvisual integration in insect prey. In Complex Worlds from Simpler Nervous Systems; Prete, F.R., Ed.; MIT Press: Cambridge, MA, USA, 2004; pp. 313–334. [Google Scholar]
- James, S. The caveman’s conscience: Evolution and moral realism. Australas. J. Philos. 2009, 82, 215–233. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Cowan, R. Cognitive penetrability and ethical perception. Rev. Philos. Psychol. 2015, 6, 665–682. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
- Scherer, K. Appraisal considered as a process of multilevel sequential checking. In Appraisal Processes in Emotion: Theory, Methods, and Research; Scherer, K., Schorr, A., Johnstone, T., Eds.; Oxford University Press: New York, NY, USA, 2001; pp. 92–120. [Google Scholar]
- Lazarus, R. Appraisal: The minimal cognitive prerequisites of emotion. In What Is an Emotion? Classic and Contemporary Readings, 2nd ed.; Solomon, R., Ed.; Oxford University Press: New York, NY, USA, 2003. [Google Scholar]
- Price, C. Emotion; Polity Press: Malden, MA, USA, 2015. [Google Scholar]
- Montague, M. Evaluative phenomenology. In Emotion and Value; Roeser, S., Todd, C., Eds.; Oxford University Press: New York, NY, USA, 2014; pp. 32–51. [Google Scholar]
- Dokic, J.; Lemaire, S. Are emotions perceptions of value? Can. J. Philos. 2013, 43, 227–247. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Milona, M. The attitudinalist challenge to perceptualism about emotion. Dialectica, forthcoming.
- Vavova, K. Debunking evolutionary debunking. In Oxford Studies in Metaethics 9; Shafer-Landau, R., Ed.; Oxford University Press: New York, NY, USA, 2014; pp. 76–101. [Google Scholar]
- Marcus, G. The Birth of The Mind: How a Tiny Number of Genes Creates the Complexities of Human Thought; Basic Books: New York, NY, USA, 2004. [Google Scholar]
- Haidt, J.; Joseph, C. The moral mind: How five sets of innate intuitions guide the development of many culture-specific virtues, and perhaps even modules. In The Innate Mind, Vol. 3: Foundations and the Future; Carruthers, P., Laurence, S., Stich, S., Eds.; Oxford University Press: New York, NY, USA, 2007; pp. 367–392. [Google Scholar]
- Cosmides, L.; Tooby, J.; Barrett, H.C. Resolving the debate on innate ideas: Learnability constraints and the evolved interpenetration of motivational and conceptual functions. In The Innate Mind: Structure and Contents; Carruthers, P., Laurence, S., Stich, S., Eds.; Oxford University Press: New York, NY, USA, 2005; pp. 305–337. [Google Scholar]
- Kriegel, U. Varieties of Consciousness; Oxford University Press: New York, NY, USA, 2015. [Google Scholar]
- Naar, H. The fittingness of emotion. Synthese 2021, 199, 13601–13619. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Milona, M. Reasons for perceptualism about emotion. Unpublished manuscript.
- Nathan, U. Moral emotions and unnamed wrongs: Revisiting epistemic injustice. Ergo 2023, 9, 755–781. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
Disclaimer/Publisher’s Note: The statements, opinions and data contained in all publications are solely those of the individual author(s) and contributor(s) and not of MDPI and/or the editor(s). MDPI and/or the editor(s) disclaim responsibility for any injury to people or property resulting from any ideas, methods, instructions or products referred to in the content. |
© 2023 by the author. Licensee MDPI, Basel, Switzerland. This article is an open access article distributed under the terms and conditions of the Creative Commons Attribution (CC BY) license (https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/).
Share and Cite
Milona, M. Armchair Evaluative Knowledge and Sentimental Perceptualism. Philosophies 2023, 8, 51. https://doi.org/10.3390/philosophies8030051
Milona M. Armchair Evaluative Knowledge and Sentimental Perceptualism. Philosophies. 2023; 8(3):51. https://doi.org/10.3390/philosophies8030051
Chicago/Turabian StyleMilona, Michael. 2023. "Armchair Evaluative Knowledge and Sentimental Perceptualism" Philosophies 8, no. 3: 51. https://doi.org/10.3390/philosophies8030051
APA StyleMilona, M. (2023). Armchair Evaluative Knowledge and Sentimental Perceptualism. Philosophies, 8(3), 51. https://doi.org/10.3390/philosophies8030051