What Attentional Moral Perception Cannot Do but Emotions Can
Abstract
:1. Introduction
Vance and Werner present evidence which, they claim, shows that “most adult human beings” exhibit AMP [1] (p. 518). Furthermore, they argue that this tendency can explain the moral-epistemic abilities that some theorists have hoped moral perception can account for: AMP can explain virtuous agents’ ability to notice morally relevant features that others overlook; it can explain such agents’ ability to accurately represent properties such as suffering, which are morally relevant; and it can explain their ability to carve out certain features as belonging to more-or-less unified “situations” that are candidates for moral assessment. On this basis, Vance and Werner contend that AMP is the psychologically real phenomenon that plays “all the explanatory roles” [1] (p. 501) ascribed to moral perception by some theorists.Attentional Moral Perception (AMP): Humans’ mechanisms of perceptual attention tend to be sensitive to morally relevant properties. Consequently, humans tend to attend to the morally relevant properties they perceive1.
2. What Attentional Moral Perception Can Do
CMP cashes out moral perception along the lines of the kinds of “high-level” perception advocated by some philosophers of mind [7,8,9]. The idea is that our perceptual experiences present us with a wider range of properties than familiar ones such as shape, colour, loudness, and pitch, which are uncontroversially perceptible. For a skilled forester, such-and-such a tree can appear to be a Scots pine; the phenomenal character of her visual experience presents the tree as being a Scots pine. Similarly, according to proponents of CMP, a skilled moral agent can see or hear an action as cruel, in the very literal sense that her perceptual experience presents the action as exhibiting the property of being cruel.Contentful Moral Perception (CMP): “A virtuous agent can represent moral properties as part of the content of her perceptual experience”.[1] (p. 502)
AMP avoids the controversial claim that moral properties such as wrongness or cruelty can show up in perceptual experiences. Instead, Vance and Werner rely on the claim that “moral difference makers” can be “subject to attentional focus in perceptual experience” [1] (p. 507). By “moral difference-makers”, Vance and Werner mean the properties that most theorists call “morally relevant properties”, i.e., not the moral properties themselves but the properties that make a given action wrong or cruel (or right or kind, etc.). Standardly, these will be nonmoral properties present in the situation, such as “someone’s wincing in pain” [1] (p. 509) in a situation where someone’s action is wrong partly due to causing said pain3. Thus, while CMP entails that agents can be perceptually aware of moral properties, AMP requires only that agents can perceptually attend to the nonmoral properties on which those moral properties depend. Vance and Werner wisely remain neutral about which nonmoral properties are the morally relevant ones; whatever the correct account is of what makes an action wrong or makes a person cruel, etc., whether that is the agent’s intentions, the action’s impact on people’s wellbeing, etc., the claim made by AMP is that agents will tend to have their perceptual attention drawn to those properties (insofar as they are accessible to perception).AMP: Humans’ mechanisms of perceptual attention tend to be sensitive to morally relevant properties. Consequently, humans tend to attend to the morally relevant properties they perceive.
3. What Attentional Moral Perception Cannot Do
3.1. Moral Knowledge
3.2. Moral Conversions
By his own account, this experience leads Tolstoy to form a new moral belief at odds with his pre-existing moral beliefs. It is not that the experience enables Tolstoy to fill in the details of formerly abstract moral beliefs; rather, the experience leads him to abandon his former moral beliefs altogether.When I saw the heads being separated from the bodies and heard them thump, one after the next, into the box I understood, and not just with my intellect but with my whole being, that no theories of […] progress could justify this crime. I realized that even if every single person since the day of creation had, according to whatever theory, found this necessary I knew that it was unnecessary and wrong, and therefore that judgments on what is good and necessary must not be based on […] progress, but on the instincts of my own soul.[26] (pp. 12–13)
4. From Perception to Emotion
This understanding of virtuous agents’ sensitivity is in line with historical views such as those of Aristotle [44], Mengzi [45], and Francis Hutcheson [46], as well as some more recent work [47,48,49].Emotional Sensitivity: Virtuous agents tend to respond to morally significant objects with emotions that fit their moral status.
5. Conclusions
Funding
Institutional Review Board Statement
Informed Consent Statement
Data Availability Statement
Conflicts of Interest
1 | Vance and Werner define AMP as follows: “(1) Perceptual, attentional mechanisms tend to be sensitive to moral difference-makers and this sensitivity is reflected in attentional patterns in perceptual experience. (2) Moral cognition is influenced by these attentional patterns such that changing patterns of perceptual attention can change moral judgments and decisions” [1] (p. 507). My gloss is meant to be equivalent to the first part of Vance and Werner’s definition. I explain below how this tendency “can change moral judgments and decisions”. |
2 | Their main reference point is John McDowell [2]. |
3 | Vance and Werner write that “difference-makers will tend to be non-moral properties” [1] (p. 509, my emphasis). Presumably, this is because there are cases in which higher-order moral properties depend on lower-order moral properties, as when someone’s action is unforgivable partly in virtue of being cruel. In this case, the action’s cruelty is simultaneously a moral property and a morally relevant property (relevant, that is, to the action’s unforgivableness). These chains of moral-on-moral dependency might be iterated a number of times, but they will always terminate in the base case of moral-on-nonmoral dependency [15]. |
4 | See also [16] (p. 42). |
5 | Compare [18] (pp. 336–337). Some historical and social kinds might be perceptible, in the sense of figuring in the content of perceptual experience; perhaps this is the case for gender and race categories, for example. But my point stands so long as some morally relevant properties or relations are imperceptible. |
6 | Among “sensibility theorists”, see [2] (pp. 56–57), [3] (p. 51, pp. 146–147), [4] (pp. 208–210), [5] (p. 430) and [25]. Compare [19] (p. 164). (NB Jacobson [25] reserves the term “moral knowledge” for knowledge of what one has most reason to do all things considered and argues that quasi-perceptual sensitivities cannot provide this. Nevertheless, his account of moral sensibility aims to explain knowledge of propositions such as that φ-ing is kind, which most would classify as instances of moral knowledge, and which cannot be explained by AMP). |
7 | Some theorists suggest denying that moral conversions are possible if they cannot be explained in terms of the application of prior moral beliefs to new nonmoral observations [28,29] but this seems undesirably ad hoc. For more real-life cases of moral conversion, see [30,31] (p. 137), and [32] (p. 140). |
8 | |
9 | Vance and Werner argue that AMP “can play all of the explanatory roles that the sensibility theorist needs in her theory of moral sensibilities” [1] (p. 501, my emphasis). As my citations throughout Section 3 have illustrated, the aspiration to explain the possibility of moral knowledge and moral conversions is shared by sensibility theorists such as McNaughton [2], McDowell [3], and others. |
10 | Werner [12] notes that we could sidestep this worry by endorsing “strong perceptualism”, a controversial view in the philosophy of emotion according to which emotions are literally a species of perceptions (see also [40]). But (a) with this move, CMP collapses into the Emotional Sensitivity view I will discuss in a moment and (b) there are marked differences between emotions and canonical forms of perception which arguably render strong perceptualism implausible (see [41] (pp. 83–117)). |
11 | In as yet unpublished work, Vance and Werner make a positive case for the existence of CMP, so the debate is not over yet. |
12 | |
13 | Each emotion-type is paired with a certain evaluative property (which is called that emotion’s “formal object”). A token emotion is fitting iff its target instantiates the corresponding evaluative property, e.g., an agent’s guilt is fitting iff the deed about which she feels guilty is a wrongdoing for which she is culpable; an agent’s anger is fitting iff the deed she is angry about is an offence, etc. |
14 | |
15 | This initial reaction must presumably be based on some kind of “pre-attentional monitoring of the environment for potentially important stimuli” [41] (p. 22). |
16 | |
17 | Vance and Werner [1] (p. 508) also mention that AMP might help us articulate a moral epistemology compatible with (i) moral particularism and (ii) moral expertise. Emotional Sensitivity shares these putative strengths. (i) Emotional Sensitivity enables virtuous agents to recognize particular moral truths without recourse to moral principles [63]. (ii) Emotional Sensitivity equips virtuous agents with distinctive moral-epistemic abilities, which could be part of an account of what makes moral experts special. |
18 | It is notable that many of the sensibility theorists Vance and Werner cite make statements that align better with Emotional Sensitivity than with more literal understandings of moral perception. McDowell writes that agents’ ability to “spot” values arises through the “training of feelings” [3] (pp. 146–147). Jacobson’s account is couched in terms of “seeing by feeling”, with the virtuous agent’s “perception-like sensitivity to the demands of kindness” consisting of “affective dispositions—such as the tendency to feel pity and sympathetic embarrassment for others” [25] (pp. 393–394). See also [2] (p. 113) and [16] (p. 35). We might thus suspect that, for these theorists, any talk of “moral perception” was a metaphor all along. |
19 | I am grateful for feedback from audiences at the University of Edinburgh and for comments on an earlier version from Jonna Vance and Preston Werner. |
References
- Vance, J.; Werner, P. Attentional Moral Perception. J. Moral Philos. 2022, 19, 501–525. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- McNaughton, D. Moral Vision; Blackwell: Oxford, UK, 1988. [Google Scholar]
- McDowell, J. Mind, Value and Reality; Harvard University Press: Cambridge, MA, USA, 1998. [Google Scholar]
- D’Arms, J.; Jacobson, D. Sensibility Theory and Projectivism. In The Oxford Handbook of Ethical Theory; Copp, D., Ed.; Oxford University Press: Oxford, UK, 2005; pp. 186–218. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Chappell, S.G. Moral Perception. Philosophy 2008, 83, 421–437. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- McGrath, S. Moral Knowledge by Perception. Philos. Perspect. 2004, 18, 209–228. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Siegel, S. Which Properties Are Represented in Perception? In Perceptual Experience; Gendler, T., Hawthorne, J., Eds.; Oxford University Press: Oxford, UK, 2006. [Google Scholar]
- Siegel, S. The Contents of Visual Experience; Oxford University Press: Oxford, UK, 2010. [Google Scholar]
- Bayne, T. Perception and the Reach of Phenomenal Content. Philos. Q. 2009, 59, 385–404. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Church, J. Possibilities of Perception; Oxford University Press: Oxford, UK, 2013. [Google Scholar]
- Cowan, R. Perceptual Intuitionism. Philos. Phenomenol. Res. 2015, 90, 164–193. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Werner, P. Moral Perception and the Contents of Experience. J. Moral Philos. 2016, 13, 294–317. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Werner, P. Moral Perception without (Prior) Moral Knowledge. J. Moral Philos. 2018, 15, 164–181. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Werner, P. Which Moral Properties Are Eligible for Perceptual Awareness? J. Moral Philos. 2020, 17, 290–319. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Dancy, J. On Moral Properties. Mind 1981, 90, 367–385. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Blum, L. Moral Perception and Particularity; Cambridge University Press: Cambridge, UK, 1994. [Google Scholar]
- Wu, W. Attention; Routledge: London, UK, 2014. [Google Scholar]
- DesAutels, P. Moral Perception and Responsiveness. J. Soc. Philos. 2012, 43, 334–346. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Darwall, S.; Gibbard, A.; Railton, P. Toward Fin de Siècle Ethics: Some Trends. Philos. Rev. 1992, 101, 115–189. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Miller, A. Contemporary Metaethics: An Introduction, 2nd ed.; Polity: Cambridge, UK, 2013. [Google Scholar]
- Huemer, M. Ethical Intuitionism; Palgrave Macmillan: Basingstoke, UK, 2005. [Google Scholar]
- Sinnott-Armstron, W. Moral Skepticisms; Oxford University Press: New York, NY, USA, 2006. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Moore, G.E. Principia Ethica; Cambridge University Press: Cambridge, UK, 1922. [Google Scholar]
- Ross, W.D. The Right and the Good; Oxford University Press: Oxford, UK, 2002. [Google Scholar]
- Jacobson, D. Seeing by Feeling: Virtues, Skills, and Moral Perception. Ethical Theory Moral Pract. 2005, 8, 387–409. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Tolstoy, L. A Confession; Penguin: London, UK, 2008. [Google Scholar]
- Hutton, J. Moral Experience: Perception or Emotion? Ethics 2022, 132, 570–597. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Sturgeon, N. Ethical Intuitionism and Ethical Naturalism. In Ethical Intuitionism: Re-Evaluations; Stratton-Lake, P., Ed.; Oxford University Press: Oxford, UK, 2002; pp. 184–211. [Google Scholar]
- Faraci, D. A Hard Look at Moral Perception. Philos. Stud. 2015, 172, 2055–2072. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Orwell, G. A Hanging. The Adelphi, August 1931. Available online: https://www.orwellfoundation.com/the-orwell-foundation/orwell/essays-and-other-works/a-hanging/ (accessed on 10 November 2023).
- Russell, B. Autobiography; Routledge: London, UK, 2009. [Google Scholar]
- De Waal, F. The Bonobo and the Atheist; Norton: London, UK, 2013. [Google Scholar]
- De Paul, M. Balance and Refinement: Beyond Coherence Methods of Moral Inquiry; Routledge: London, UK, 1993. [Google Scholar]
- Werner, R. Ethical Realism. Ethics 1983, 93, 653–679. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Block, N. Seeing-As in the Light of Vision Science. Philos. Phenomenol. Res. 2014, 89, 560–572. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Burge, T. Reply to Block: Adaptation and the Upper Border of Perception. Philos. Phenomenol. Res. 2014, 89, 573–583. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Chudnoff, E. Forming Impressions: Expertise in Perception and Intuition; Oxford University Press: Oxford, UK, 2020. [Google Scholar]
- Firestone, C.; Scholl, B. “Moral Perception” Reflects Neither Morality Nor Perception. Trends Cogn. Sci. 2016, 20, 75–76. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Väyrynen, P. Doubts about Moral Perception. In Evaluative Perception; Bergqvist, A., Cowan, R., Eds.; Oxford University Press: Oxford, UK, 2018; pp. 109–128. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Wisnewski, J. The Case for Moral Perception. Phenomenol. Cogn. Sci. 2015, 14, 129–148. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Brady, M. Emotional Insight: The Epistemic Role of Emotional Experience; Oxford University Press: Oxford, UK, 2013. [Google Scholar]
- Chudnoff, E. Moral Perception: High-Level Perception or Low-Level Intuition? In Phenomenology of Thinking; Breyer, T., Gutland, C., Eds.; Routledge: London, UK, 2015; pp. 207–219. [Google Scholar]
- Deonna, J.; Teroni, F. The Emotions: A Philosophical Introduction; Routledge: London, UK, 2012. [Google Scholar]
- Crisp, R. (Ed.) . Aristotle. Nicomachean Ethics; Cambridge University Press: Cambridge, UK, 2000. [Google Scholar]
- Van Norden, B.W. Translator. In Mengzi: With Selections from Traditional Commentaries; Hackett: Indianapolis, IN, USA, 2008. [Google Scholar]
- Hutcheson, F. An Inquiry into the Original of Our Ideas of Beauty and Virtue; Liberty Fund: Indianapolis, IN, USA, 2008. [Google Scholar]
- Roberts, R.; Wood, W.J. Proper Function, Emotion, and Virtues of the Intellect. Faith Philos. 2004, 21, 3–24. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Sias, J. Ethical Intuitionism and the Emotions: Toward an Empirically Adequate Moral Sense Theory. J. Value Inq. 2014, 48, 533–549. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Pelser, A. Emotion, Evaluative Perception, and Epistemic Justification. In Emotion and Value; Roeser, S., Todd, C., Eds.; Oxford University Press: Oxford, UK, 2014; pp. 107–123. [Google Scholar]
- Tolhurst, W. On the Epistemic Value of Moral Experience. South. J. Philos. 1990, 29, 67–87. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Kauppinen, A. A Humean Theory of Moral Intuition. Can. J. Philos. 2013, 43, 360–381. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Mitchell, J. The Epistemology of Emotional Experience. Dialectica 2017, 71, 57–84. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Tappolet, C. Emotions, Values, and Agency; Oxford University Press: Oxford, UK, 2016. [Google Scholar]
- Hutton, J. Unreliable Emotions and Ethical Knowledge. Unpublished manuscript.
- Milona, M. Taking the Perceptual Analogy Seriously. Ethical Theory Moral Pract. 2016, 19, 897–915. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Sosa, E. A Virtue Epistemology; Oxford University Press: Oxford, UK, 2007. [Google Scholar]
- Greco, J. A (Different) Virtue Epistemology. Philos. Phenomenol. Res. 2012, 85, 1–26. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- D’Arms, J.; Jacobson, D. The Significance of Recalcitrant Emotion (or, Anti-Quasijudgmentalism). R. Inst. Philos. Suppl. 2003, 52, 127–145. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Twain, M. Adventures of Huckleberry Finn (Tom Sawyer’s Comrade); Charles, L. Webster & Co: New York, NY, USA, 1885. [Google Scholar]
- Scherer, K. The Dynamic Architecture of Emotion: Evidence for the Component Process Model. Cogn. Emot. 2009, 23, 1307–1351. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Cuneo, T. Signs of Value: Reid on the Evidential Role of Feelings in Moral Judgement. Br. J. Hist. Philos. 2006, 14, 69–91. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Mitchell, J. Emotion and Attention. Philos. Stud. 2023, 180, 73–99. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Milona, M. Intellect versus Affect: Finding Leverage in an Old Debate. Philos. Stud. 2017, 174, 2251–2276. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
Disclaimer/Publisher’s Note: The statements, opinions and data contained in all publications are solely those of the individual author(s) and contributor(s) and not of MDPI and/or the editor(s). MDPI and/or the editor(s) disclaim responsibility for any injury to people or property resulting from any ideas, methods, instructions or products referred to in the content. |
© 2023 by the author. Licensee MDPI, Basel, Switzerland. This article is an open access article distributed under the terms and conditions of the Creative Commons Attribution (CC BY) license (https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/).
Share and Cite
Hutton, J. What Attentional Moral Perception Cannot Do but Emotions Can. Philosophies 2023, 8, 106. https://doi.org/10.3390/philosophies8060106
Hutton J. What Attentional Moral Perception Cannot Do but Emotions Can. Philosophies. 2023; 8(6):106. https://doi.org/10.3390/philosophies8060106
Chicago/Turabian StyleHutton, James. 2023. "What Attentional Moral Perception Cannot Do but Emotions Can" Philosophies 8, no. 6: 106. https://doi.org/10.3390/philosophies8060106
APA StyleHutton, J. (2023). What Attentional Moral Perception Cannot Do but Emotions Can. Philosophies, 8(6), 106. https://doi.org/10.3390/philosophies8060106