1. Introduction
“Thermodynamics is a funny subject. The first time you go through it, you don’t understand it at all. The second time you go through it, you think you understand it, except for one or two small points. The third time you go through it, you know you don’t understand it, but by that time you are so used to it, it doesn’t bother you anymore.”
—Sommerfeld (see Angrist and Loren [
1], p. 215)
This paper is an attempt to establish a connection between ethics and the second law of thermodynamics (entropy) (See
Remark B1 in Appendix B). Specifically, we ask: how do scientists make their ethical decisions? Do they make them based on their religious/spiritual/philosophical outlook or do they make their decision based on other scientific laws? Einstein ([
2], p. 115) seems to provide an answer:
“It is the privilege of man’s moral genius, impersonated by inspired individuals, to advance ethical axioms which are so comprehensive and so well founded that men will accept them as grounded in the vast mass of their individual emotional experience. Ethical axioms are found and tested not very differently from the axioms of science. Truth is what stands the test of experience.”
What Einstein is perhaps suggesting or implying, I think, is that ethical axioms, at least some of them, can be founded upon science. In fact, Lindsay [
3] in an article titled, “
Entropy consumption and values in physical science,” proposed an Ethical Imperative similar to that of Kant’s
Categorical Imperative:
“We may call it the thermodynamic imperative since it is suggested by the principles of thermodynamics. In brief, and in simple language, it urges all men to fight always as vigorously as possible to increase the degree of order in their environment so as to combat the natural tendency for order in the universe to be transformed into disorder, the so-called second law or principle of thermodynamics.”
A moral imperative is a statement which can be expressed as: “I ought …,” implying that “an action of this kind to be imposed or necessitated by an objective principle valid for any rational agent as such.” (Kant, translated by Paton, [
4], p. 26). Thus an imperative is directly related to rationality. Kant’s Categorical Imperative deals with maxims, universal law, will, etc. A maxim is a purely personal principle upon which we will to act. According to Kant, this is a subjective principle. An
objective principle on the other hand implies a principle where every rational agent would necessarily act provided that this rational agent has complete (full) control over his or her actions. Kant’s categorical imperative is first given as a negative statement: “I ought never to act except in such a way that I can also will that my maxim should become a universal law” ([
4], p. 70). Later in his book, Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals, Kant expresses this imperative as a positive statement: “Act only on that maxim through which you can at the same time will that it should become a universal law” ([
4], p. 88). Lindsay [
3] used these guidelines to develop his ideas culminating in a thermodynamical imperative. In this paper, we attempt to extend and supplement Lindsay’s thermodynamic imperative, by another imperative suggesting simplicity, conservation, and harmony.
We start by asking the following question: If science, formerly and more accurately known as Natural Philosophy, is a part of Philosophy, as much as ethics is part of philosophy, then are there ethical laws stemming or emanating from the body of knowledge we now call science (Remark B2)? In other words, is it possible to use science and arrive at some rules of ethics based on science (Remark B3)? This is the primary concern in this essay. In the same spirit Newton ([
5], p. 1) said: “Natural philosophy consists in discovering the frame and operation of nature, and reducing them, as far as may be, to general rules or laws—establishing these rules by observations and experiments, and thence deducing the causes and effects of things…” There are those who say that ethics belongs to the domain of religions, while there are others who say ethics is a branch of philosophy and one can be ethical without belonging to a religious tradition or establishment. Is it possible that scientists can use science and devise a code of ethics? Sarton ([
6], p. 171) one of the greatest historian of science, says:
“Almost every man of science, whether he be historically minded or not, is obliged to do a certain amount of retrospection, because his own investigations bring him face to face with the work of some predecessor, or because of academic conventions…The fundamental questions ‘When did that happen? Where?’ are easy to answer. The questions ‘Why?’ and ‘how?’ are more difficult of course, yet they are still comparatively easy for later periods.”
It was perhaps this sort of reflection that caused many of the greatest scientists of the 20th Century to realize the potential disasters ensuing from a nuclear war (see Masters and Way [
7]).
In fact, as pointed out by Deltete [
8], Hertz in 1894 had summarized one of the goals of classical physics: “All physicists agree that the problem of physics consists in tracing the phenomena of nature back to the simple laws of mechanics.” This, in a sense, is a summary of the “mechanistic” view of nature. With the introduction of the concepts of “energetic” and “energeticism” in thermodynamics, mainly by Ostwald and others (see for example Ostwald [
9], and Deltete [
10,
11]) some physicists began to look at things from a different perspective. As Deltete [
8] provides a succinct summary of this view: “The energeticists believed that scientists should abandon their efforts to understand the world in mechanical terms, and that they should give up atomism as well, in favor of a new world view based entirely on the transfers and transformations of energy.” In fact, Ostwald [
9] went as far as saying that “…energetics coincides with that movement which has originated on philosophical ground and which pursues very similar ends under the name of ‘pragmatism’ or ‘humanism’.” This seems to be one of the earliest attempts by a scientist to connect energy (or thermodynamics) with philosophy. However, it needs to be mentioned that the concept of “energetics” as an all-encompassing theory has not been widely accepted by the science community. According to Holt [
12]: “The two major scientific critics of Energism, Max Planck and Mach, dismissed Energism as useless ‘metaphysics.’” For additional criticism and discussion of these views, we refer the reader to the papers of Carus [
13] and Hakfoort [
14]. Of course, in the current paper I am not advocating an enegeticism view of ethics or philosophy.
The objective of this essay is to show that the application of the Entropy Law to the environment, should include not only Lindsay’s thermodynamical imperative, which was based on a modern interpretation of the Entropy Law, relating it to order, organization, and sorting, but it also needs to be supplemented and indeed must be preceded by another thermodynamical imperative, which is based on a classical interpretation of the Entropy Law, relating it to conservation, simplicity, and harmony.
In
Section 2 of this paper, we discuss very briefly certain aspects of science. In
Section 3, a discussion of classical thermodynamics, including concepts such as systems, energy, and entropy is provided. In
Section 4, a few remarks relating entropy to ethics are mentioned and a new Thermodynamics Imperative (complementary to that of Lindsay’s) is suggested.
2. The Role of Science
“Scientific progress continually reminds us that dogmas are for doubting, orthodox opinions are for factual rebuttals, established facts are for disconfirming, wild conjectures are (sometimes) for entertaining, beautiful thoughts are often (alas) for unthinking, and world authorities are for deflating.”
Science has been blamed for many of the disasters, especially warfare and destruction of nature, and it has been praised for many of the advances made in health, transportation, agriculture, etc. With issues such as “Global Warming” and other (natural) catastrophes such as floods, fires, and tornadoes, very often scientists are asked to interpret, make predictions, and come up with solutions and explanations (Remark B4). Bertrand Russell ([
16], p. 78) says: “Science used to be valued as a means of getting to
know the world; now, owing to the triumph of technique, it is conceived as showing how to
change the world.” Amongst the important contributions of the 20th Century, are perhaps the Gaia Hypothesis (see Lovelock [
17]) and Connectivity Hypothesis (see Laszlo [
18]), where the organic and living nature of the environment and the connection amongst the various parts and members of the biotic community are explored. To this, we can also add the Systems Theory (Bertalanffy [
19], Laszlo [
20], Macy [
21]), in some ways, related to thermodynamics, which attempts to look at the Whole rather than the parts, and also considers the interactions among the various parts of the sub-systems.
While there are many definitions of science (Remark B5) and who a scientist (Remark B6) is, below we give a few sample definitions given by a few scientists and philosophers. For example, Lindsay [
3] says: “Science is a method for the description, creation and understanding of experience. It is, of course, not the only method for doing this, but no one can deny its success in the field to which it has generally confined itself.” Stephen Toulmin ([
22], p. 99) says: “Science is not an intellectual computing-machine: it is a slice of life. We set out on our enquiry into the aims of science, hoping to do two things: first, to define in a life-like way the common intellectual tasks on which scientists are engaged, and the types of explanation their theories are intended to provide; and secondly, to pose the problem, how we are to tell good theories from bad, and better ideas, hypotheses, or explanations from worse ones.” Bateson ([
23], p. 29) says: “Science is a way of perceiving and making what we may call ‘sense’ of our precepts. But perception operates only upon difference. All receipt of information is necessarily the receipt of news of difference, and all perception of difference is limited by threshold. Differences that are too slight or too slowly presented are not perceivable. They are not food for perception.” Russell [
24] says: “Science is the attempt to discover, by means of observation, and reasoning based upon it, first, particular facts about the world, and then laws connecting facts with one another and (in fortunate cases) making it possible to predict future occurrences.” And finally, Ziman ([
25], p. 28) defines physics, which is what is what I mean by science in this paper, as: “…the science devoted to discovering, developing and refining those aspects of reality that are amenable to mathematical analysis.”
There are two distinct and related concepts here which need to be considered: observation and reasoning based upon it. If something cannot be observed, either via our sensory organs, or instruments, then does science take a (strong) position about its non-existence? In other words, can a science based on reasoning arrive at something that no observation could have substantiated it? In general, when we talk about scientific laws, we are indirectly assuming that they are based on observation and reasoning based upon it. However, as Boulding [
26] remarks:
“Most of the great laws, however, have a strong element of a priori about them. They are the way we know things must be rather than the way we have observed them. There is a certain myth among scientists that the great laws of science are derived by induction from observation and tested by the confirmation of predictions. This may be true of the small laws, but it is not really true of the great ones, which are derived on the whole from identities that we discover in our imaginations.”
If we define physics as that branch of science which studies the physical world, then its laws are restricted to that realm of existence (see also Goswami [
27]). For example, Newton’s Third Law which says: “Action equals reaction” [
28] operates in the physical realm where action means a physical action. There are some who think that many of the laws of physics have complementary forms in non-physical realms (Remark B7). For example, one can also talk about a verbal action or a mental action (Remark B8). Each has consequences that Newton’s Third Law, in its classical form, cannot count for (Remark B9). That is, if we consider not just the physical actions, but also the verbal (vocal) and the mental (imaginative) actions, then we can question whether or not the laws of physics can or should be applied to these other two realms.
If we consider the poetic or the mystical realm belonging to the realm of imaginative activity, then clearly it is understandable that many scientists may not consider themselves as mystical. But there are many great scientists who even if they were not great poets or great mystics, had poetic and mystical tendencies. By “scientist”, in its purest form, we mean one who seeks knowledge in general, and knowledge as related to the physical world is but a limited aspect of this search (Remark B10). Many cultural values such as religious, educational, social, and family ones influence or help to create our code of ethics. A scientifically-oriented ethics allows for a person to be a scientist, yet believe in a transcendental realm. Such an orientation would imply that we would study our own code of ethics, and we would try to improve or modify it using observation (i.e., the effects of our conduct on the outer world as well as the inner world). Davis [
29] in his essay discussing “Engineering Ethics” distinguishes at least four different ways of studying ethics (Remark B11):
“…a system for ordinary morality, those standards of conduct that apply to everyone as moral agent.”
“...the art of living well.”
“…special morally-permissible standards of conduct that apply to the members of a group simply because they are members of that group.”
“…a field of philosophy (the attempt to understand ethics, in one or more of its other senses, as a rational undertaking.”
In exploring the relationship between creativity (a way of bringing meaning into one’s life) and science, Sir Peter Medawar ([
30], p. 85) offers the following guidelines:
“We must study particulars and not abstractions: after all biologists do not study the nature of life: they study living things and likewise physicians study not the concept of illness but sick people…
A scientist will shun an explanation which while it has outwardly the form of an explanation, does no more in fact than interpret one unknown in terms of another…
A scientist will take evidence from all quarters likely to be informative, not excluding introspection, for no good would come of self-righteously abjuring such an important source of evidence.
A scientist must be resolutely critical, seeking reasons to disbelieve hypotheses, perhaps especially those which he has thought of himself and thinks rather brilliant.”
From this list we can identify key phrases such as studying specific problems, avoiding useless explanations, collecting data from various sources and being critical as important concepts.
Having discussed, albeit very briefly and selectively, some aspects of science and ethics, in the next Section, we will discuss some of the ideas in classical thermodynamics, especially the 2nd law of thermodynamics (the entropy law) and explore its possible connections to ethics.
3. Classical Thermodynamics: The First and the Second Laws
“The task of the theorist is to bring order into the chaos of the phenomena of nature, to invent a language by which a class of these phenomena can be described efficiently and simply. Here is the place for ‘intuition’ and here the old preconceptions, common among natural philosophers that nature is simple and elegant, has led to many successes. Of course physical theory must be based in experience, but experiment comes after, rather than before, theory. Without theoretical concepts one would neither know what experiments to perform nor be able to interpret their outcomes.”
According to Callen ([
32], p. 11) Leibniz in 1693 was the first person who stated a conservation principle, for the sum of the kinetic energy
and the potential energy
for a simple mechanical mass point. As more complicated systems were studied, initially it appeared that the established form of this conservation principle had failed, but later it was shown that with the addition of new mathematical terms, i.e., new kinds of energy (which were later shown physically to exist), the conservation principle has held its place. Thus, in a sense, the first law of thermodynamics has been modified but never violated.
Before we look at the (four) laws of thermodynamics, we will discuss concepts such as systems, states, processes (paths), stability, etc. According to classical thermodynamics (Remark 12) there are three (or four) types of systems (see Massoudi [
33]).
An
isolated system is a system which does not exchange energy or matter with the outside environment. And an
adiabatically isolated system is one in which the transfer of heat and matter are excluded, but other forms of energy can be transferred across the boundaries (Denbigh [
34]).
A closed system is one in which only energy is exchanged with its environment. Earth is an example of such a system.
An open system is one in which both matter and energy can be exchanged with the environment. (Remark B13)
Within a closed system, for example the earth, it is possible to have isolated sub-systems, closed sub-systems, and open sub-systems. Most of the naturally occurring systems, such as human beings and other living creatures, and “unnatural” systems, such as refrigerators are open systems and in these cases (the standard form of) the entropy law does not apply. Within any system, it is possible to have many sub-systems (also called elements, constituents…) which move (or can be transformed) from one state to another state. The process (or the path) that this transformation takes place can be reversible (which implies frictionless processes where there is no dissipation) or irreversible (Remark B14). A state may be in equilibrium (Remark B15) or non-equilibrium, stable or unstable. In general, all these concepts have to be defined before we can discuss the laws of thermodynamics, in a meaningful way.
Callen ([
32], pp. 13–32) has provided an outstanding and very concise summary of classical thermodynamics; he has presented the four postulates of thermodynamics as:
Postulate I. “There exists particular states (called equilibrium states) of simple systems that, macroscopically, are characterized completely by the internal energy , the volume , and the mole numbers of the chemical components.”([
32], p. 13)
We can think of equilibrium states as states which are time independent; it is intrinsically assumed in classical thermodynamics that “in all systems there is a tendency to evolve toward states in which the properties are determined by intrinsic factors and not by previously applied external influences,” (Callen, [
32], p. 13). Furthermore, we often talk about
quasi-static processes. These generally refer to the cases where things are happening very slowly or in a technical sense where processes are occurring with “infinite slowness.”
Postulate II. “There exists a function (called the entropy ) of the extensive parameters of any composite system, defined for all equilibrium states and having the following property: The values assumed by the extensive parameters in the absence of an internal constraint are those that maximize the entropy over the manifold of constrained equilibrium states.”([
32], p. 27)
At this stage of the development of classical thermodynamics, it is important to recognize that there are no references to this entropy function being related to the order or disorder and chaos in the system. As mentioned by Callen ([
32], p. 26): “The single, all-encompassing problem of thermodynamics is the determination of the equilibrium state that eventually results after the removal of internal constrains in a closed, composite system.” For our purpose here, it is not important to discuss composite systems. Postulate II is at the core of classical thermodynamics, for as mentioned by Callen ([
32], p. 28) if the fundamental relation of a particular system, which is the relation which specifies the entropy as a function of the extensive parameters, is known, then all “conceivable” thermodynamical information about that system can be ascertained. This fundamental relationship can have the following form:
Postulate III. “The entropy of a composite system is additive over the constituent subsystems. The entropy is continuous and differentiable and is a monotonically increasing function of the energy.”([
32], p. 28)
And according to this Postulate, we can define a non-negative quantity called the temperature such that:
Since Equation (1) is a single-valued continuous and differentiable function, it can be inverted and solved for
such that:
And thus, we can talk about minimizing the internal energy
, instead of maximizing the entropy
. In simple language, if the total entropy of a system is known as a function of the various extensive parameters of the subsystems, then by differentiating it, and on the basis of the second derivative, we can see whether these extrema can be classified as minima, maxima, or as horizontal inflections. Thus, now we are in the position to talk about stable or unstable equilibrium states (Callen [
32], p. 31).
Postulate IV. “The entropy of any system vanishes in the state for which (that is, at the zero temperature).”([
32], p. 30)
The vanishing of this derivative indicates the vanishing of the temperature, which means that zero temperature implies zero entropy. This is an extension, due to Planck, of the so-called third law of thermodynamics.
As Callen ([
32], p. 27) points out, based on previous experience with many physical theories it is expected that a suitable equilibrium criterion would be expressed in terms of an extremum principle where the values of the extensive parameters in the final equilibrium state are simply those that maximize some physically meaningful function, which in our case is the entropy
. In general, within the context of classical thermodynamics, we can talk about mechanical, thermal, or chemical equilibrium. As stated by Callen ([
32], p. 203):
“The basic extremum principle of thermodynamics implies that and that , the first of these conditions, stating that the entropy is an extremum and the second stating that the extremum is, in particular, a minimum.”
We can recall, from classical mechanics, that similarly, the stable equilibrium of a rigid pendulum is at the position where the potential energy is minimum. One of the interesting stability (Remark B16) criteria in thermodynamics is that of Le Chatelier’s Principle, where (Callen ([
32], p. 211) “any inhomogeneity that somehow develops in a system should induce a process that tends to eradicate the inhomogeneity.” That is, given enough time, there seems to be a tendency for the fluctuations and the disturbances to die out and for the system to return to its equilibrium state. For example, unless externally enforced and sustained, turbulences tend to damp out within the fluid flow and inhomogeneities in concentration diffuse to uniformity.
The science of thermodynamics is primarily based on experiment and much of the classical thermodynamics is based on the four fundamental laws of thermodynamics (see Kestin [
35]). By the time the now well-known two laws of thermodynamics were formulated, it was recognized that another fundamental law had to precede them, and this has become known as the
Zeroth law, formulated by Fowler in 1931, which states (Kestin [
35]: “Two systems in thermal equilibrium with a third system are in thermal equilibrium with each other.” Also according to Kestin and Dorfman ([
36], p. 15)): “The Third law asserts that the entropy difference in an isothermal process tends to zero as the thermodynamic temperature tends to zero.” There are other ways of expressing this law, as for example done by Nernst, Planck, etc. The first law of thermodynamics, also known as the law of conservation of energy, states that “
all matter and energy in the universe is constant, that it cannot be created or destroyed.” (Remark B17) Feynman et al., ([
28], Chapter 4) says:
“There is a fact, or if you wish, a law, governing all natural phenomena that are known to date. There is no exception to this law—that is exact so far as we know. The law is called the conservation of energy. It states that there is a certain quantity, which we call energy, that does not change in the manifold changes which nature undergoes. That is a most abstract idea, because it is a mathematical principle; it says that there is a numerical quantity which does not change when something happens...It is important to realize that in physics today, we have no knowledge of what energy is...It is an abstract thing in that it does not tell us the mechanism or the reasons for the various formulas.”
Interestingly, as Asimov [
37] says:
“No one knows why energy is conserved, and no one can be completely sure it is truly conserved everywhere in the universe and under all conditions. All that anyone can say is that in over a century and a quarter of careful measurement, scientists have never been able to point to a definite violation of energy conservation, either in the familiar everyday surroundings about us, or in heavens above or in the atoms within.”
The first law (Remark B18) of thermodynamics does not say anything about the direction of this change, this transformation from one state to another state; it is the second law of thermodynamics which provides this information (Remark B19). There does not seem to be any controversy or disagreement with regard to the form or the interpretation of the first law of thermodynamics: it is accepted that energy is conserved. In most textbooks on thermodynamics, energy is usually defined as the capacity of a system to perform work. In physics, the known forms of energy are chemical, potential, kinetic, nuclear, etc., which in some ways can be measured or quantified. Physics does not directly specify or discuss whether there is any energy due to one’s thoughts and whether the energy caused by one’s thoughts and one’s words is conserved (Remark B20).
The entropy law has been known for more than 150 years. While there have been many attempts to challenge its status as a law of physics, such as the many claims of perpetual machines of the first or second kind, it has never been disproved. There are different ways of looking at the Second Law. One could look at it from the Classical Thermodynamics or from the Statistical Thermodynamics perspective. It could also be related to irreversibility and disorder (Remark B21). The important thing about the entropy law (Remark B22) is “that it is neither a theorem deducible from the principles of classical mechanics nor a reflection of some man’s imperfections or illusions. On the contrary, it is as independent a law as, for example, the law of universal attraction, and just as inexorable.” (Georgescu-Roegen, [
38], p. 9). Entropy in a classical thermodynamical process is related to the free energy of that system. As Lindsay [
3] explains: “If the essence of the first principle in everyday life is that we cannot get something for nothing, the second principle emphasizes that every time we do get something we reduce by a measurable amount the opportunity to get that something in the future, until ultimately the time will come when there will be no more getting.”
According to Seifert [
39] and others, Clausius in 1850 invented the concept of entropy (Remark B23) “to describe and measure the loss in available energy which occurs in most natural processes.” Feynman, et al. ([
28], on the other hand says, “The so-called second law of thermodynamics was thus discovered by Carnot before the first law!” There are two well-known statements of the second law in classical thermodynamics (see Cengal [
40]). In one case the emphasis is on the efficiency of conversion of heat into work (Remark B24), and in the other case on the irreversibility (Remark B25) of nature. According to Adkins [
41], these statements are:
The Kelvin Statement (Remark B26):
No process is possible whose sole result is the complete conversion of heat into work.
The Clausius Statement:
No process is possible whose sole result is the transfer of heat from a colder to a hotter body.
The first statement indicates that it is impossible to achieve 100 percent efficiency in the conversion of heat into work and the second statement indicates that the natural tendency for heat is to flow from hotter to colder bodies, unless there is an external agent (such as extra work) to reverse this direction (refrigeration being an example of such a process (Remark B27)). These two statements explain the impossibility of two different forms of perpetual motion. For example, it is because of the first statement that we cannot have a perpetual machine of the first kind which is a machine operating continuously by creating its own energy. It is because of the second statement that we cannot have a perpetual machine of the second kind “a machine that cannot be made which runs continuously by using the internal energy of a single heat reservoir,” (Adkins, [
41], p. 54). As indicated by Denbigh [
34], to be proper, the second law of thermodynamics applies only to System 1 and System 1-b defined earlier, whereas for Systems 2 or 3 the entropy may actually decrease “due to an outward passage of heat and/or matter across the boundary surface.”
Up to now, in this paper, I have attempted to provide a brief summary of the relevant issues from the perspective of classical thermodynamics, and I have also tried to discuss important ideas such as systems, stability, equilibrium, etc. In the next and final section of this paper, I take the “leap of faith”, where I will first look at how the concepts of (dis)order and (dis)organizations, through the introduction of statistical and irreversible thermodynamics, have been used for proposing ethical imperatives. I will then show that classical thermodynamics can also be used and with a similar leap of faith, it can provide another thermodynamic imperative.
Section 4 will have more of a philosophical twist about it with some conjectures about the relationship between entropy (mainly form a classical thermodynamics perspective) and ethics.
4. Brief Remarks on Possible Ethical Aspects of the Entropy Law
“Even when the individual believes that science contributes to the human ends which he has at heart, his belief needs a continual scanning and re-evaluation which is only partly possible... And if we adhere simply to the creed of the scientist, that an incomplete knowledge of the world and of ourselves is better than no knowledge, we can still by no means always justify the naive assumption that the faster we rush ahead to employ the new powers for action which are opened up to us, the better it will be.”
Most of what we discussed in the previous section pertain to the concept of entropy as developed and used in classical thermodynamics. However, according to Prigogine ([
43], p. 9), Boltzmann was “the first to note that entropy is a measure of molecular disorder,” and he concluded “that the law of entropy increase is simply a law of increasing disorganization.” This is perhaps the beginning of the introduction of new ideas, such as order and disorder (Remark B28) into thermodynamics. Lindsay [
3], like many other physicists, looked at entropy as a measure of the orderliness of a system (Remark B29): “Increase in entropy means a transition from a more orderly state to a less orderly state.” He furthermore indicated that:
“In any naturally occurring process, the tendency is for all systems to proceed from order to disorder. The maximum entropy of Clausius is the state of complete disorder or thorough randomness, out of which no return to order is practically possible because it applies to the universe as a whole; nothing short of an inexpressibly improbable revolution could reverse the process and decrease the entropy. From this point of view, the trend from order to disorder with production of entropy is inexorable. The second law always wins in the end. A gloomy outlook indeed! But, there is perhaps a silver lining in the cloud.”
It is through the living organisms, the conscious and the aware ones, that perhaps the hope lies. A complex system (Remark B30) may or may not be a disorderly one. For example, to build a house one has to organize various elements such as bricks, pipes, wires, etc., in an orderly fashion. According to Denbigh [
44]: “A system is said to be organized when it has a function, or a set of functions; that is to say when the system in question is able to do certain things, or can be made to do them.” Therefore, while a house is a complex system (Remark B31) (in a relative sense), it is also an orderly system. However, if the house is destroyed, due to earthquake for example, while the level of complexity may not have changed, the disorder has certainly increased. Clearly organization is related to or has an important relationship with the notion of complexity, which Denbigh [
44] defines as: “…a measure of the number of distinct components (e.g., atoms, molecules, cells, etc.,) that a particular system can contain under the prevailing physical conditions.” Not all living organisms make a system more orderly. Additional and conscious efforts of sorting or ordering are needed. As Orrell ([
45], p. 11) explains: “A defining property of complex systems is that they exhibit what is known as emergent behavior (see also [
46]): properties which emerge from the system but cannot be predicted using the knowledge of the system’s components alone.” Living organisms are complex systems and in living organisms, we talk not only about the production but also the consumption of entropy (Remark B32).
An area where physics can provide some ethical guidelines, and in fact, some warning signs, is the application of the entropy law, not only in scientific and environmental realms, but perhaps also on a personal level and relating to our livelihood. While there are categories of ethics dealing with different aspects of environment, including animal rights and the rights of nature (see [
47,
48,
49,
50,
51,
52,
53]), in general, entropy law, in my opinion, can also be used to suggest certain ethical guidelines. The (ethical) consequences of the Entropy Law are generally stated in the form of Consequentialist Ethics, or a form of Deontological Ethics. Lindsay [
3], following the Deontological approach, suggests:
“...while we do live we ought always to act in all things in such a way as to produce as much order in our environment as possible, in other words to maximize the consumption of entropy. This is the thermodynamic imperative, a normative principle which may serve as the basis for a persuasive ethic in the spirit of the Golden Rule and Kant’s categorical imperative.”
Thus, in a sense, Lindsay seems to be associating the maximization of the consumption of entropy with the creation of some type of order in the environment. That is, by intentionally consuming entropy, i.e., by organizing, sorting and putting things in order, we create a more orderly state of living. There is conscious effort involved here. This statement can be put in the following form, as a Thermodynamical Imperative (TI):
TI.2. One ought to do things, in so far as possible, in such ways that the consumption of entropy is maximized ([3]). This imperative, however, does not address the issue of how the disorder came into existence (was created) in the first place and whether it was caused naturally. For example, a tornado will cause much destruction and create a lot of disorder in its path. Undoubtedly, we as humans, by cleaning up the mess caused by a tornado, i.e., by consuming the existing entropy, can help to create a more orderly, organized and cleaner environment. However, not all disorders are caused by natural phenomena; many are man-made, and because of this, I think the imperative suggested by Lindsay needs to be supplemented by another one which should precede it. That is, we should try to do things, in so far as possible, in such ways that we minimize the production of entropy. Stating this in the form of a Thermodynamical Imperative, we have
TI.1. One ought to do things, in so far as possible, in such ways that the production of entropy is minimized (Remark B33).
Thus we can say that while this statement is concerned with conservation, simplicity, and harmony, the imperative proposed by Lindsay [
3] involves ordering, sorting, and organizing.
While most modern technical inventions such as organizers, computers, cell phones, etc., can order and organize things for us (the mess which we have created due to our entropy production) there are few or no (modern) inventions which help us live simply and with more in harmony and peace with our environment. These are more difficult to do and they are qualitatively dependent on the individual and they are more of a personal nature; how to live in harmony and more simply come from within each individual and are related to our worldview and to our perception of how we fit in the world, and what our responsibilities are to the world. For example, TI.1 suggests or implies that we should abstain from using things such as minerals, resources, etc., which are not renewable [
54]. If we need to use these things, then we should take measures to protect against excessive use. It is only after enforcing this imperative that we would apply TI.2. For example, recycling is primarily a form of reorganizing the waste or the by-product; similarly every time we re-order or re-organize a system, for whatever reason, we can use TI.2. However, these activities at the same time involve the use of more available energy (see [
55]). That is, activities such as emission control, improving efficiency, etc., on a large scale, are actions we can do and ought to do in order to organize or minimize the waste or pollution. This is indeed necessary and useful. However, these types of activities do not address the more fundamental and underlying issue, namely: How or why was the waste created in the first place? This type of questioning requires the implementation of TI.1. For example, if we walk into a room and see clothes, shoes, books, etc., all over the room, we can immediately recognize this as being a dis-organized environment. By intentionally consuming the entropy, i.e., the disorder, through our efforts, we can make the room more organized. This, however, does not address how or why was the room in such a disordered state? As Ben-Naim ([
56], p. 188) says: “The Second Law of Thermodynamics states that in any spontaneous process in an isolated system, the entropy increases. The Second Law does not state anything as to why the entropy increases, nor does it address the question as to why a spontaneous process occurs at all.”
Therefore, the issue is not whether we should maximize the consumption of entropy (TI.2) (this we should do), but how can we minimize the production of entropy (TI.1)? In my opinion, this is a question that has been addressed by the World’s Wisdom traditions (see [
57,
58]), where we are encouraged to preserve and protect mature and all beings in it, to the extent possible, and to conserve and to let things be. Yet, we see a world rapidly decaying, fast becoming a trash-bin where we discard and dump things so easily, not realizing or not caring that there is no place for the waste to go; it will have to come back to us. I think in some ways, we can relate TI.1 to a measure of simplicity in our life (Remark B34). Whether or not and how much each of us can simplify our life remains an individual choice and decision (Remark B35). For example, as Thoreau ([
59], p. 323) said:
“I learned this, at least, by my experiment; that if one advances confidently in the direction of his dreams, and endeavors to live the life which he has imagined, he will meet with a success unexpected in common hours. He will put some things behind, will pass an invisible boundary; new and universal, and more liberal laws will begin to establish themselves around and within him; or the old laws be expanded, and interpreted in his favor in a more liberal sense, and he will live with the license of a higher order of beings. In proportion as he simplifies his life, the laws of the universe will appear less complex, and solitude will not be solitude, nor poverty poverty, nor weakness weakness. If you have built castles in the air, your work need not be lost; that is where they should be. Now put the foundations under them.”
A dead organism (Remark B36) perhaps has the lowest production of entropy, since it is only through external means such as soil, insects, wind, moisture, heat, etc. that is able to exchange mass with its surroundings. For a living being, perhaps the state of lowest production of entropy is in some sense similar to a monk or a nun or any person capable of sitting quietly in meditation, in perfect Samadhi [attention, concentration], and in full control of his or her senses, simply breathing in and breathing out, not engaged in any physical, vocal or even mental activities. On the surface, any individual who can also sit still for a while, with a closed mouth would also fit this category; however, the difference between this individual and the one whose mind is at peace is that the latter does not produce or create any thoughts of anger, jealousy, hatred, greed (all related to high entropy activities). Instead, the person in the state of Samadhi can actually guide his or her peaceful thoughts towards all beings by producing or generating thoughts of harmony, love, and compassion. Praying and contemplative meditations are also forms of this type of activity (Remark B37). While most of us are not able to sit still in meditation for long periods on any given day, we can find the right balance in our life.
In so far as our external activities related to our physical or verbal actions, we can try to use TI.2 as closely as possible (Remark B38). For our mental activities, we can try to use TI.1 by keeping our mind at peace and act in a compassionate manner, with loving-kindness towards all beings.
The application of TI.1 is not limited to mental actions only; this imperative also has practical implications related to our physical actions, for example, how we (ought to) live. Issues related to our livelihood, our source of income, and how we spend our money and whether we walk or bike to work instead of driving... Ultimately these are decisions made by an individual; they can be guided by the application of the entropy law. As mentioned by Brillouin ([
60], p. 558) the second law of thermodynamics “is a death sentence, but it contains no time limit… The principle states that in a closed system S will increase and high-grade energy must decrease; but it does not say how fast… The second principle is an arrow pointing to a direction along a one-way road, with no upper or lower speed limit.” It is necessary to make a distinction between different forms of energy. Georgescu-Roegen ([
61], Chapter 3) says: “The free energy to which man can have access comes from two distinct sources. The first source is a stock, the stock of free energy of the mineral deposits in the bowels of the earth. The second source is a flow, the flow of solar radiation intercepted by the earth.” The stock of free energy in the form of mineral deposits is similar to one’s money in a savings account, whereas the flow of solar radiation is similar to one’s income deposited regularly in a checking account. Cloud [
62] indicates: “Here is where entropy becomes critical. All of these minerals, without exception, are produced, beneficiated, and transformed into low-entropy products at a cost in available energy. All of the energy utilized is concentrated and brought to focus on useful work at a cost in materials. All of this energy is also irreversibly transformed into unavailable, high-entropy states. All of the low-entropy metals and other mineral products utilized become disordered high-entropy waste with time. They can only be restored to states useful to man, recycled that is, with further inputs of energy. Entropy inexorably increase.” When the natural deposits are taken out, processed, and used, either they could never be replaced or it will take thousands or millions of years or so, before the stocks could reach the point where they can again be used as a source of energy. The use of solar energy, advocated by the energy conservation movement, on the other hand, for all practical purposes, presents an unlimited source of energy. In summary, we can rephrase these two imperatives in the following order as the two thermodynamic imperatives (TI):
TI.1. We ought to do things, in so far as possible, in such ways that the production of entropy is minimized.
TI.2. We ought to do things, in so far as possible, in such ways that the consumption of entropy is maximized (Lindsay [3]). Norbert Wiener in his article titled “
Some moral and technical consequences of automation,” [
42] warned us about the dangers of blindly following scientific adventures: “It is my thesis that machines can and do transcend some of the limitations of their designers, and that in doing so they may be both effective and dangerous.” He compared machines with slaves: “Complete subservience and complete intelligence do not go together.” We cannot and should not expect that science or technology will solve all our problems. They cannot. And as these two imperatives indicate, we as individuals, especially those familiar with the laws of physics in general, and specifically with the entropy law, have a responsibility to implement these ethical imperatives in our daily lives, as much as we can. Tagore ([
63], p. 101) says:
“I ask once again, let us, the dreamers of the East and the West, keep our faith firm in the Life that creates and not in the Machine that constructs—in the power that hides its force and blossoms in beauty, and not in the power that bares its arms and chuckles at its capacity to make itself obnoxious. Let us know that the Machine is good when it helps, but not so when it exploits life; that Science is great when it destroys evil, but not when the two enter into unholy alliance.”