3.1. The New Kinematics of Quantum Mechanics
The constraint given by Equation (
1)—which in [
6] is called the
elliptope inequality—was known and discussed, albeit in contexts far removed from physics, as early as the 19th century by figures such as Udny Yule, Ronald A. Fisher and Bruno de Finetti [
6] (chp. 3). As Janas, Cuffaro & Janssen explain, its derivation relies on the following fact about linear combinations of
X,
Y and
Z:
where
,
and
are real numbers. Modelling Equation (
2) in a local hidden-variable theory requires a joint probability distribution over the possible values of
X,
Y and
Z. When there are two possible values per variable, the possible probabilistic correlations between
X,
Y and
Z are describable geometrically as a tetrahedron (see
Figure 3) lying entirely within the elliptope. When there are three or more values per variable, the associated polyhedra become further and further faceted and more closely approximate the elliptope, but become exceedingly difficult to compute. In contrast to a local hidden-variable theory, quantum theory (as John von Neumann observed in [
37]) allows us to assign a value to a sum of observable quantities—represented, for instance, by an operator
—without, in general, requiring that we assign values to the individual summands
,
and
(cf. [
26] (p. 376)). Janas, Cuffaro & Janssen show how, as a consequence, the probabilistic correlations describable in quantum mechanics saturate the entire elliptope—already for spin-
systems (the analogue of a two-valued variable) as well as for all higher values of spin.
That an assignment of values to a sum of observable quantities entails an assignment of values to the individual observables involved in the sum is always true in classical theory. By contrast, the kinematical structure of quantum theory—the constraints it imposes on our physical description of a system independently of the specifics of its dynamics ([
6] (chp. 1); [
38] (pp. 26–52))—is more general. Slogans such as “quantum mechanics is all about information” or “quantum mechanics is all about probabilities” are meant (at least for the informational approach under discussion here), not as ontological claims, but to emphasise that these constraints (as we will see in more detail in a moment) are probabilistic in nature—that the conceptual
novelty of quantum mechanics lies ([
6] (sct. 6.3); [
1] (sct. 4.3)) in the way that it constrains probability assignments. The slogan also conveys the idea that quantum mechanics is a framework that can in principle be applied to any type of physical system, for instance computational systems, the fictitious “quantum bananas” of [
13] and so on ([
39]; [
6] (chps. 1, 6); [
40,
41]).
Understanding why quantum mechanics, but not classical mechanics, saturates the elliptope for all values of spin is only one example of a problem that can be fully explained by appealing exclusively to quantum mechanics’ kinematical constraints. In addition, Janas, Cuffaro & Janssen [
6] (sct. 6.4) describe three further examples of physical problems from the history of quantum mechanics that seemed, at first, to call for dynamical solutions but that were solved as a direct result of considering the change introduced into physics via quantum mechanics’ novel kinematics. These are: accounting for the particle term in Einstein’s 1909 formula for energy fluctuations in black-body radiation (pp. 188–189), accounting for the formula for the electric susceptibility of diatomic gases (pp. 189–191), and accounting for why electron orbits seem to depend on which coordinates one chooses to impose the quantisation condition (pp. 191–194).
The ‘measurement problem’, as it is usually framed (see, e.g., [
42], p. 63), also seems to call for a dynamical solution, i.e., on the one hand, quantum mechanics describes the dynamics of systems as unitary in the absence of a measurement; yet, on the other hand, given a measurement the apparent ‘collapse’ of the vector representing a system’s state is non-unitary. But positing special measurement dynamics is ad hoc, or so the argument goes, since it should be possible to describe a measurement interaction as a physical interaction like any other. In fact, quantum mechanics agrees with this in the following sense: a quantum description of a measurement interaction can be provided, in unitary terms, to any desired level of detail given an appropriate placement of the ‘Heisenberg cut’, on one side of which lies our quantum description of the interaction, and on the other, our classical description of the observation of its results. Stated in these terms, the ‘problem’ can be seen as one of closing this gap, either by proposing a new theory to explain the connection between the two sides of the Heisenberg cut, or by arguing that quantum mechanics, in some sense, is all that one needs to make theoretical sense of it.
The Everett interpretation, as is well known, chooses the second option [
43]. The same is true of the approach under discussion in this paper, though for very different reasons as we will soon see. The appearance of one rather than another of the possible outcomes of a measurement interaction is not thought of, in fact, in terms of a dynamical process at all—i.e., it is simply not taken to be described, in this sense, by quantum mechanics—let alone as a non-unitary dynamical collapse of the state vector. As Bub explains:
A unitary dynamical analysis of a measurement process goes as far as you would like it to go, to whatever level of precision is convenient. The collapse, as a conditionalization of the quantum state, is something you put in by hand after observing the actual outcome. The physics doesn’t give it to you.
There is, of course, more to be said. In particular, by considering how the kinematical structure of quantum mechanics departs from that of classical mechanics, one can discern two conceptually separate aspects of the so-called problem. In classical mechanics [
6] (sct. 6.3), an observable
A is represented by a function,
, defined on the phase space of a system. With
, one can associate a Boolean algebra
, in which the possible yes-or-no questions concerning
A that can be asked regarding the system, questions of the form “Is the value of the observable
A within the range
?” may be expressed. In classical mechanics, merely specifying a system’s dynamical state,
, is enough to yield a determinate answer to every such question for every observable quantity associated with the system. In logical terms, this means that in classical mechanics, the Boolean algebras corresponding to each of the system’s observables can be embedded within a globally Boolean algebra, such that a particular state assignment (which may or may not be probabilistic as, for instance, in classical statistical mechanics) suffices to fix the answers (or the probabilities over possible answers in the case of a probabilistic state assignment) to all of the possible questions that one can ask concerning any observable associated with the system. This is the sense in which the classical state is what Bub & Pitowsky [
12] (p. 433) call a ‘truthmaker’ in relation to a system’s observables. (Note that the term ‘truthmaker’ is intended here only in the logical sense described above, rather than in any metaphysical sense. For more on the use of the term ‘truthmaker’ in philosophical contexts, see [
44].)
In quantum mechanics [
6] (sct. 6.3), an observable,
A, is represented by a Hermitian operator,
, acting on the Hilbert space associated with a system, whose possible values are given by the eigenvalues of
. As with
in the classical case, with
one can associate a Boolean algebra
representing the possible yes-or-no questions that one can ask about
A. But the quantum state, unlike the classical state, fails to be a ‘truthmaker’ in relation to a system’s observables in two ways, corresponding to what I will be calling the ‘big’ and the ‘small’ measurement problems. The ‘big problem’ is that unlike in classical mechanics, where one can always in principle eliminate the indeterminacy associated with any given probabilistic phenomenon by including further parameters in one’s dynamical model of the system of interest, in quantum mechanics, fully specifying the normalised vector
representing the state of the system of interest can only ever yield the probability, which is in general neither 0 nor 1, that the answer to a given experimental question will take on a particular value. Given that it will nevertheless be possible, conditional on the selection of an observable to measure, to describe the observed relative frequencies of the various possible outcomes of the (by assumption, projective) measurement in terms of a classical probability distribution as given by the Born rule, this departure from classicality is arguably only minor, at least in comparison with the ‘small measurement problem’, the more significant way in which the kinematics of quantum mechanics diverges from classical mechanics. This refers to the fact that the classical probability distributions that can be associated with the system’s observables, in the way just described, cannot be embedded into a global classical probability distribution over all of the system’s observables, or alternately that the Boolean algebras corresponding to each of the system’s observables cannot be embedded within a globally Boolean algebra. Moreover, quantum mechanics’ unitary description of a measurement interaction does not, by itself, prefer any one of these classical (i.e., Boolean) ways of effectively characterising the system [
6] (p. 224). In the next section, we will consider what to say about the significance of this on the informational, or (neo-)Bohrian, approach under discussion in this paper. (Note that the distinction between a ‘big’ and a ‘small’ measurement problem was first introduced by Pitowsky [
45], and is further developed in [
12], [
13] (in the first edition) and in [
6]. Brukner [
4] also distinguishes between the same two aspects of the measurement problem but inverts the labels and does not use inverted commas. Here, I am following [
6]. Note that although the ‘big’ and especially the ‘small’ problems are formulated somewhat differently in [
6] than in [
12], I take there to be no difference of substance. Although Bub and Pitowsky’s idea that the ‘small’ problem is resolved by “considering the dynamics of the measurement process and the role of decoherence in the emergence of an effectively classical probability space of macroevents to which the Born probabilities refer” [
12] (p. 438) is not incorrect, it is (in my view) misleading insofar as the formulation seems to suggest that this, by itself, is enough to yield an observer-independent description of the dynamics of a measurement interaction. Whether a dynamical analysis to this end can be made to work is an interesting question (for further discussion, see [
46,
47]). But that this question is not Bub and Pitowsky’s is evident, in any case, later in the same article where they explain that the goal of such a dynamical analysis is to provide “a
consistency proof that the familiar objects of our macroworld behave dynamically in accordance with the kinematic probabilistic constraints on correlations between events.” [
12] (p. 452, emphasis mine). In other words, it is taken for granted, in any such analysis, that specific observables have been selected for measurement that have particular phenomena associated with them, or as Bub has put it in his more recent publications, it is required that one posits some “ultimate measuring instrument” that is not included in one’s quantum-mechanical description of a measurement interaction [
14] (pp. 8–9). In my terms this amounts to a Boolean frame. Note that the ‘small measurement problem’ is what Everettians call the ‘preferred basis problem’. It is also what is highlighted by the (in)famous thought experiment of Frauchiger & Renner [
48]. For some recent commentaries on this and similar thought experiments that are directly relevant to the approach to quantum mechanics under discussion in this paper, see [
16,
49,
50].)
3.2. The Subjective Character of the Idea of Observation–Schematising the Observer as a Postulate
On what I will call the
traditional metaphysical picture—the one lying behind Bell’s insistence that in any physical theory worth its salt, “[o]bservables are
made out of beables” [
51] (p. 41, emphasis in original)—the possible values of dynamical variables like position, momentum, the direction of a particle’s spin and so on, are understood to be the manifestations of an underlying reality whose properties are revealed in our experiments with physical systems. (Note that, in the sequel, I will for the most part be using the term property rather than beable, in part to convey that the traditional metaphysical picture I am referring to here transcends quantum mechanics.) The trouble with quantum mechanics, given this picture, is that because of the big and especially the small ‘measurement problems’, the possible values of dynamical quantities—represented, in quantum mechanics, as the eigenvalues of a given Hermitian operator (cf. [
52,
53,
54])—cannot be taken to represent determinate properties of a single classically describable physical system in the following logical sense: there is no globally Boolean algebra in which one can embed all of the individual Boolean algebras corresponding to the various observables associated with the system, that can be used to derive, given a state assignment, an unconditional probability distribution over the possible values of a given observable, let alone a determinate value. Given the traditional metaphysical picture, there are, broadly speaking, two attitudes that one can take towards quantum mechanics. First, one can take it to be incomplete and pursue a research programme to complete it by positing further, perhaps unobservable, physical parameters not described by quantum mechanics that can be used to provide us with an absolute representation of a system in some sense (see, e.g., [
55,
56]). Alternately, one can insist that quantum mechanics already provides us with a globally Boolean picture of the world—but that that world is a multiverse rather than the single classically describable universe we at one time imagined it to be [
43].
As for the approach under discussion here (cf. Stein’s [
26] (pp. 369, 409–410) distinction between what he calls the epistemological and metaphysical senses of interpretation), it is not opposed to the traditional metaphysical picture per se. That picture would be apt if classical mechanics (or some other theoretical framework with a globally Boolean algebra of observables) were our fundamental framework. But it is also open to the possibility that that picture is not apt; for how one carves nature at the joints, so to speak, is something that, for the informational interpreter, should be motivated by physical theory rather than a priori. The informational interpreter is certainly committed to something a priori, but it is not a particular metaphysical thesis about the way the world must be. What the informational, or (neo-)Bohrian, interpreter is committed to, rather, is the
empiricist methodology through which one reasons, from the values revealed in experiments with what we take to be physical systems, carried out under precisely specified—to the relevant scale and for the relevant purposes (cf. [
24] (sct. 5, sct. 11, point 5))—experimental conditions, to a picture of the world that is anchored in the dynamical model one builds of the phenomena in a given context. (Note that the local hidden-variable models (in the form of raffles), for spin correlations described in [
6] (chps. 2–3), are (toy) examples of such models. To say that an overarching theoretical picture must be anchored in a toy model like this is to say that that toy model must remain valid when one restricts the phenomena under consideration to those associated with the experimental context that the toy model was designed to characterise (cf. [
2] (pt. 2)).)
The approach under discussion is not a ‘realist’ one in the sense that ultimately it is taken to be the goal of a physical theory—even a so-called fundamental physical theory—to represent
phenomena rather than the so-called reality that one might imagine to be in some sense responsible for the phenomena, in a systematic way ([
13] (p. 227); [
1] (pp. 135–139); [
6] (pp. 219–222); [
33] (pp. 111, 118); cf. [
25] (p. 50); [
23] (pp. 639, 645)). (Note that, in this context, the word ‘fundamental’, of course, cannot be construed as pertaining to ‘fundamental stuff’; rather, a (candidate) fundamental theory should be understood, for one defending the approach that we are discussing here, as one that we take to be capable of representing all known phenomena.) Insofar as one does this for the purposes of using physical theory as a tool, the approach can be called instrumentalist (cf. [
57] (p. 2)). But instrumentalism in this sense is compatible with realism on a more reasonable (methodological) construal of what the latter means. To put it succinctly, the important question on this approach to quantum mechanics is not whether but
how to use physical theory to assign physical properties to what one takes to be the system of interest responsible for a given phenomenon ([
6] (pp. 8–10 and chp. 6); [
2] (p. 118); cf. [
26] (p. 371)).
One could perhaps conceive of a more radical form of empiricism that is not even realist in this methodological sense. Although this is, presumably, a logically possible attitude to take to science, I confess that I struggle to imagine what a science that followed such a methodology would be like. For the methodological realism advocated on the approach we are discussing here amounts to the demand [
58] (p. 310) that we be able to meaningfully account to one another how we have set up a particular experiment (“what we have done”), and what information it yields (“what we have learned”) about an object that we model as able to interact with our experimental apparatus in a particular way [
2] (pp. 44–45). This is the methodology characteristic of what Bohr called the “ordinary causal description” of phenomena that a framework like classical mechanics makes precise and for which quantum mechanics provides a generalisation. And it is in this methodological sense that the ordinary causal description functions as a fundamental constraint on the approach to quantum mechanics under discussion.
Stein famously suggested that the principal difficulty in making sense of the connection between the ‘observational’ and ‘theoretical’ parts of a physical theory is that of how to account, theoretically, for observation, or as he puts it, “how to get the laboratory inside the theory.” [
23] (p. 638). This issue, for Stein, is of the highest importance, for “[i]t would … be impossible to
understand a theory, as anything but a purely mathematical structure—impossible, that is, to understand a theory
as a theory of physics—if we had no systematic way to put the theory into connection with observation (or experience).” [
23] (p. 639).
Stein observes that Carnap’s approach to the question, which assumes that the connection between the theoretical and observational parts of language (at least in physics) is deductive, faces a fundamental barrier insofar as (according to Stein) that assumption is de facto false: “there is no department of fundamental physics in which it is possible, in the strict sense, to
deduce observations, or observable facts, from data and theory.” [
23] (p. 638). Instead, Stein suggests that the way that theory and experiment are connected is by “schematizing the observer within the theory” ([
23] (p. 649); cf. [
26] (sct. XVII)). Curiel elaborates on the idea:
We need a way to understand the substantive, physically significant contact—the epistemic continuity, as it were—between a precisely characterizable situation in the world of experience and the mathematical structures of what we usually think of as our theories. Such understanding should at a minimum consist of an articulation of the junctions where meaningful connections can be made between the two, and would thus ground the possibility of the epistemic warrant we think we construct for our theories from such contact and connection.
“By ‘schematize the observer’,” Curiel writes, “I mean something like: in a model of an experiment, to provide a representation of something like a measuring apparatus, even if only of the simplest and most abstract form, that allows us to interpret the model
as a model of an experiment or observation.” [
24] (p. 9). As one of a number of physical examples he uses to motivate the idea, Curiel considers the case of the International Practical Temperature Scale, originally specified in [
59] and revised in subsequent decades, the goal of which is to represent the ideal thermodynamic temperature scale as closely as possible throughout its range. As Curiel explains, between the primary fixed point 0.01C and the secondary fixed point 630.5C, the scale may be defined in terms of the Callendar equation which relates temperature to the resistance of platinum as measured when immersed in various media and taking into account the particular features of the kind of platinum being used. Importantly, the variables related by the Callendar equation are defined, in part, by interpolation on the basis of our knowledge of measurements carried out at a particular scale [
24] (p. 13). In particular, below and above these two fixed points, the Callendar equation diverges from the thermodynamic scale, requiring other measurable quantities to be taken into account. Curiel takes this to show that “one cannot even define physical quantities—e.g., temperature—without explicit schematic representation of the observer, much less have understanding of how to employ their representations in scientific reasoning in ways that respect the regime of applicability.” [
24] (p. 14).
Note that it does not follow from the fact that one requires of a physical concept that it have operational significance that one is committed to operationalism in the strong sense sometimes attributed to Percy Williams Bridgeman [
60]. Requiring that a concept have operational significance to
qualify as a physical concept is not the same thing as taking a given set of operations to exhaust its meaning, or requiring that a given concept be uniquely specified by a given set of operations (see also [
61], (sct. 9.3); [
27]; [
62], (pp. 141–145)). (The density operator, for instance, clearly does not satisfy the latter criterion insofar as there are infinitely many given state preparations that correspond to a given density operator whenever the latter is not pure. I will have more to say about the physical significance of the density operator in the next section.)
Curiel’s general point was one that was well understood by Bohr. In his aforementioned ‘Como paper’, commenting on the use of the superposition principle to explain particle-like quantum phenomena in terms of the concept of a ‘wave packet’, Bohr pointed out that:
Rigorously speaking, a limited wave-field can only be obtained by the superposition of a manifold of elementary waves corresponding to all the values of and , , . But the order of magnitude of the mean difference between these values for two elementary waves in the group is given in the most favourable case by the condition
where denote the extension of the wave-field in time and in the direction of space corresponding to the co-ordinate axes.
Here,
refers to the frequency, and
refer to the wavenumbers for the elementary waves in the directions of the coordinate axes. All else equal, the broader the spread of wavenumbers/frequency in the wave group, the more determinate the spatiotemporal extent of the resultant packet, and vice versa. Now, according to the de Broglie relations,
,
, where
is the reduced Planck’s constant. If we multiply Equation (
3) by
ℏ, this gives us Heisenberg’s uncertainty relations:
which give the upper bound on the accuracy of momentum/position determinations with respect to the wave-field.
As the wave-field associated with the object gets smaller—thus allowing us to ‘zoom in’, so to speak, on its position and time coordinates—the possibility of precisely defining changes in the energy and momentum associated with the object decreases in proportion. And the opposite is also true: given a larger wave-field, it will be possible to ‘zoom out’ for the purposes of a determination of the object’s momentum (or energy), but in this case, one foregoes a precise definition in relation to the object’s spatiotemporal coordinates. Note that ‘zooming in’ and ‘zooming out’ are associated with different experimental arrangements. For the case of a -ray microscope, they are associated with the finite size of the microscope’s aperture. The indeterminacy in our assignments of position and momentum to the system is not due to the interaction between the object and the measuring apparatus per se, but to the fact that certain experimental arrangements, well-suited for precisely determining momentum, make it such that in the limit, it becomes impossible to define changes in the object’s spatiotemporal coordinates, and vice versa. Bohr sums this up as follows:
Indeed, a discontinuous change of energy and momentum during observation could not prevent us from ascribing accurate values to the space-time co-ordinates, as well as to the momentum-energy components before and after the process. The reciprocal uncertainty which always affects the values of these quantities is, as will be clear from the preceding analysis, essentially an outcome of the limited accuracy with which changes in energy and momentum can be defined, when the wave-fields used for the determination of the space-time co-ordinates of the particle are sufficiently small.
[
20] (p. 583. emphasis mine)
Quantum mechanics, on the approach we are discussing, is to be understood as elevating the insight, which Stein and Curiel (as we discussed above) have referred to as the practical and epistemic necessity—for understanding a theory as a theory of physics—of “schematising the observer,” to the level of a postulate (cf. [
63]). Bohr was explicit about this:
In the treatment of atomic problems, actual calculations are most conveniently carried out with the help of a Schrödinger state function, from which the statistical laws governing observations obtainable under specified conditions can be deduced by definite mathematical operations. It must be recognized, however, that we are here dealing with a purely symbolic procedure, the unambiguous physical interpretation of which in the last resort requires a reference to a complete experimental arrangement. Disregard of this point has sometimes led to confusion, and in particular the use of phrases like ‘disturbance of phenomena by observation’ or ‘creation of physical attributes of objects by measurements’ is hardly compatible with common language and practical definition.
[
58] (pp. 392–393, my emphasis)
On the (neo-)Bohrian approach under discussion here, an observer is represented by a ‘Boolean frame’ [
6] (p. 213)—the Boolean algebra within which one represents the possible yes-or-no questions concerning a given observable,
A, that can be asked about the system of interest: questions of the form “Is the value of
A within the range
?”. Given the schematic representation, to the relevant scale and for the relevant purposes, of an observer in this sense, one may then use the language of quantum mechanics to give a physical analysis, in terms of the states of two interacting dynamical systems,
and
(representing the measuring device), of how the observed relative frequencies of outcomes of assessments of
will be (assuming the measurement is ideal) describable using a particular classical probability distribution over possible values of
A that can be thought of as determined in conformity with the dynamics of
and
[
6] (pp. 202–212). In classical mechanics, because the state is a truthmaker in the sense we discussed in
Section 3.1,
as a matter of logic one can always argue that any given schematisation of the observer in the above sense is superfluous, at least in principle. (Note that what I mean by superfluous is that the question: “Is the value of
A within the range
?” is equivalent, in classical mechanics, to the question of whether
[
64] (p. 61), where
is the function defined on the system’s phase representing the observable
A (see
Section 3.1).) This is not the case in quantum mechanics, where the imposition of a Boolean frame is required in order to interpret the outcome of a measurement interaction as providing us with information about the world.
3.3. The Classical Idea of Isolated Objects and the Quantum-Mechanical Concept of an Open System
If it is only ever possible to describe one’s experience
as the experience of a system in the context of an interaction between what one takes to be that system and something else, then the system that one takes oneself to be describing is in every case an open system. (For more on the physics and philosophy of open quantum systems, see [
65].) In an article published in
Dialectica, in which he argued that quantum mechanics should be judged to be incomplete, Albert Einstein wrote:
Without … an assumption of the mutually independent existence (the ’being-thus’) of spatially distant things, an assumption which originates in everyday thought, physical thought in the sense familiar to us would not be possible.
([
66], as translated by Howard [
67] (p. 187))
This passage, and the wider argument of which it is a part, has been much commented on (see, for instance, [
1] (chp. 4); [
67,
68]). Here, I only want to point out that it amounts to the demand that we be able to treat spatially separated subsystems of the universe as isolated (cf. [
69]), and that arguably, we should construe this as a methodological demand—a claim about what we must be able to assume if we are to be able to practice physics in the sense familiar to us at all—rather than an a priori claim about how the world is. (In any case it can be plausibly read in this way given Einstein’s career-long concern with methodological issues (see [
70]). For a discussion of Einstein’s mutually independent existence condition, in particular, that interprets it in this way, see [
1] (chp. 4) and also [
71].) As with Bohr, my goal here is not Einstein exegesis. Irrespective of what he actually understood himself to be saying in this passage, the idea of understanding the “assumption of mutually independent existence” of spatially distant things as a methodological requirement on physical inquiry is prima facie plausible. And understanding how the principle, construed in this way, is (
pace Einstein) satisfied by quantum mechanics, illuminates important aspects of the informational approach under discussion in this paper.
Besides allowing us to express that a given system has been prepared in one of a number of states,
, with probabilities
, a density operator like
where
is the projection operator associated with the state vector
, is also used in quantum mechanics to represent the state of an open system, by which I mean one dynamically evolving under the influence of an external ‘environment’: for instance, a measurement device
that has interacted with the system. When it refers to an open system, a density operator like the one given in Equation (
5) is said to represent an ‘improper’ mixture [
72,
73] of the ‘pure states’,
—improper because, owing to the fact that
and
are entangled, it is actually impossible to interpret Equation (
5) as literally describing a system that is in a given pure state
with a given probability
(because a subsystem of an entangled system can never be in a pure state).
Of course, if
and
were not entangled, we could interpret Equation (
5) as representing our ignorance regarding the actual state,
, that the system is in. In this case, we would say that the density operator represents a ‘proper’ mixture of the pure states
(although even in this case such statements should be taken with a grain of salt, because for a given ensemble whose state is represented by some density operator
, there are in general infinitely many preparation procedures that will give rise to it, i.e.,
, whenever
and
are related by a unitary transformation [
40] (p. 103)). These two physical situations (i.e., those represented by an improper and a proper mixture, respectively) are not the same. Nevertheless, a sequence of measurements on the members of an improperly mixed ensemble will be effectively indistinguishable from—in the sense that they will be described by the same probability distribution as—a sequence of those same measurements on a properly mixed ensemble whose state is also described by
. In the context of a consideration of spatially separated systems, this amounts to the ‘no-signalling’ condition (a misnomer as it is not a relativistic constraint per se), which asserts that the marginal probabilities associated with outcomes of local experiments on a subsystem of any quantum-mechanically described system are independent of whatever particular experiments are performed (or whether any are performed at all) on the other subsystems. This effectively means that we can treat physical systems in different regions of space
as if they had mutually independent existences for the purposes of experiments local to those regions ([
71]; [
1] (chp. 4); cf. [
74]). It is important to emphasise that the existence of nonlocal correlations is not being denied. Instead, what is being affirmed is the fact that according to quantum mechanics, we can learn about them using local means.
On the informational approach we are discussing, a quantum state description is
not taken to represent a property or a collection of properties that one can think of as possessed by a system independently of a given experimental context, for it is precisely the experimental context, represented as a Boolean frame, that allows one to give an account, consistently with a given state assignment, of how the experimental apparatus involved dynamically interacts with a system, thus allowing us to conceive of some phenomenon as representing a value of a given property of the system in the first place. What the quantum state
does represent is the structure of and interdependencies among the possible ways in which one can give a probabilistic characterisation of a system in the context of a physical interaction ([
6] (p. 186); [
65] (pp. 19–20)). A classical state is no different in this sense. (Consider, for instance, Curiel’s construal [
75] (sct. 3) of the configuration space of an abstract classical system as encoding a description of its kinematically possible interactions with other abstract classical systems.) But because the probability distributions over the values of every classical observable are determined by the state independently of whether a physical interaction through which one can assess those values is actually made, there is an invitation to think of them as originating in the properties of an underlying physical system that exists in a particular way irrespective of anything external. (At least this is true when one considers the situation abstractly, and in particular, when one disregards arguments along the lines of Curiel’s and Stein’s that should make one skeptical about whether it actually makes sense, even in classical physics, to speak in such absolute terms.) Although it is not denied that one can make such a picture work (along the lines we discussed at the beginning of
Section 3.2) if one really wants to [
6] (pp. 229–230), the more complex structure of observables related by quantum mechanics does not similarly invite the inference from the values of observable quantities to the properties of an underlying system in the sense that there is no globally Boolean frame that one can use to characterise all of a given system’s observables. And since the informational interpreter is not committed to seeking a globally Boolean picture, she is not committed to the project of making such a picture work
in spite of quantum mechanics.
The elliptope and polyhedra depicted in
Figure 2 and
Figure 3 are a way to visualise, in the general setup I introduced in
Section 2, the sense in which local hidden-variable theories are able to represent only a special case of the phenomena that more general frameworks like quantum mechanics can represent. But just as in classical mechanics, in a given measurement context that we can—by assumption—effectively describe in Boolean terms, one can, consistently with quantum mechanics, provide a dynamical model of the measurement interaction also in such terms (e.g., some mixture of the classical raffles discussed in [
6] (chps. 2–3)). Such a model will not ‘suffer from the small measurement problem’ (since the observables associated with that measurement context commute). As for the ‘big measurement problem’, the short answer is that for the informational interpreter, one simply accepts it as a brute fact that nature is indeterministic [
6] (p. 11). But if one insists on a deterministic model, then the informational interpreter will point out that in any given measurement context (and associated Boolean frame), it will always be possible to interpret the indeterminacy of individual measurement results, in a given experimental run, as if they stem from our inability to completely specify some relevant physical parameter in the model.
But can nothing really be said, on this informational view, about what the world is like independently of observation? On the contrary, our assignments of values to non-dynamical quantities like mass, spin and charge are valid irrespective of the experimental context they are relevant to ([
1] (p. 184); [
6] (p. 217). Regarding dynamical quantities, one may say that the world is such that all of the effectively classical (i.e., Boolean) pictures that one can draw of it, under the precisely specified experimental conditions corresponding to each of them, are precisely relatable to one another, probabilistically, in a way that is necessarily constrained by the kinematical structure of quantum mechanics. Neither of these statements is trivial. But one may nevertheless wonder (assuming one finds this to be objectionable), whether the second truth somehow depends upon the actual existence of conscious observers. The (neo-)Bohrian will answer no. (Note that this is, I think, one way to distinguish (in the sense of where their main focus lies) the view under discussion in this paper from some of the other approaches to interpretation that we mentioned at the beginning of
Section 1 like QBism [
8].) Rather, in describing the structure of our world in this way, a schematic representation of what relevantly constitutes an observer—a Boolean frame—is used as a formal tool with which to describe how the various dynamical possibilities, or ‘propensities’ [
6] (p. 218), that are implicit in the world necessarily relate to one another. A particular Boolean frame acquires physical significance through the specification, which can be given using the language of quantum mechanics, of a dynamical model of how the associated measuring apparatus interacts with a given system, but the specification of a given context in this sense in no way implies that it must actually be instantiated or actually be interpreted by anyone; it only specifies (schematically)
how to do so. (Note that the term ‘propensities’ should not necessarily be taken in the sense of the interpretation of probability first formulated and defended by Karl Popper [
76], but only to signify that (as is also the case in Popper’s interpretation) the probabilities for outcomes of experiments can be thought of as determined given a specification of the experimental setup. Since (as I explained in
Section 3.2) a subjective component is necessarily involved in one’s characterisation of a given setup, however, and since, given an experimental setup, one may (as I mentioned in the previous paragraph) interpret the indeterminacy of individual measurement results in a given run as if they were due to our incomplete knowledge of some relevant physical parameter, it would arguably be more appropriate to think of the probabilities of outcomes of measurements in a given context as if they were more akin to what Wayne Myrvold [
62] (pp. 106–121, 209–210) has called ‘epistemic chances’ rather than to Popper’s propensities.)