1. Introduction
Folk wisdom has it that lying is endemic to politics. Citizens of any state are likely to say that they have encountered political lies off and on in all levels of government. The academic debate picks up on politicians telling lies in democratic systems and there are opposing positions about the legitimacy of such lies. Some claim that a political lie can help to actually attain certain public goods and that they are therefore justifiable (e.g., [
1]). One of the most prominent contemporary examples for a noble lie is the Good Friday Agreement between Sinn Fein and the IRA on one side and the Ulster Unionists on the other side of the Northern Irish conflict in April 1998
1. Those defending these kinds of political lies call them “noble lies” with reference to Plato. Those opposing such views argue that lying is so foreign to democracy that it does nothing but undermine democracy itself [
2], even in cases in which it does produce welfare benefits.
In our paper, we consider another important, but poorly developed aspect of political lying: we look at the long-term consequences of noble lies for the production of public goods with a focus on those (highly likely) cases in which the noble lie is uncovered. For this purpose, we analyze the results of a series of public good experiments in which we concentrate on the “aftermath” of the noble lie. More specifically, we ask whether it is beneficial in terms of efficiency to continue telling potentially reassuring lies or to provide the truth once a noble lie has been revealed. As such, we complement Gneezy et al. [
3] who discuss the long-term consequences of lying in a sender receiver game. They show that the frequency of lying increases with experience when the gains of lying are high. In our design, continuation of lying may enhance or threaten the provision of a public good.
Specifically, participants in our experiment play two sequences of twenty rounds of a voluntary contribution mechanism game (VCM). In the first sequence, after every round, players receive feedback on the group’s average contribution; the below average and average contributors receive correct information, and the above average contributors receive inflated feedback. The intention behind manipulating the information on the average contributions is to provide an incentive for the above average contributors to keep up their above average contributions in the next round as well. This would lead to the group gaining as a whole at the expense of the cooperative players
2.
There are three treatment variations in the second sequence: (1) baseline—the arrangement of the first sequence stays unchanged and players do not know that the feedback is partly inflated; (2) lie—between sequences, the participants are told that their feedback in sequence 1 has been manipulated and they continue to receive feedback inflated in the same way during the second sequence. That means the noble lie is continuously applied, but confidence of the players in the accuracy of the feedback mechanism is (again) seriously unsettled by the revelation of the true feedback mechanism; (3) truth—between sequences, the participants are told that their feedback has been inflated in sequence 1. They are then told that in the second sequence they will receive non-manipulated feedback. Cooperation rates are compared between all three treatments.
Treatment variations (2) and (3) represent two extreme communication strategies for the aftermath of the lie. One may argue that people—after being informed that they were lied to—appreciate this efficiency enhancing manipulation as they understand that they all profit from it (e.g., Hoffmann et al. [
8]). Following this argument, the continuation of the lie has positive implications for an individuals’ willingness to cooperate in comparison to telling the truth, since people anticipate the stimulating effect of the lie. On the other hand, it could be that people appreciate unambiguous information in comparison to potentially wrong messages even if this information indicates an income loss: people may interpret the potentially wrong message in exactly the same fashion, namely as information indicating an income loss, while the lie adds additional ambiguity, for instance, about the amount that is lost. Overall, it is unclear per se whether one of the two cases (i.e., telling lies or providing the truth) leads to more efficient outcomes. That is why we test them experimentally.
Our results from the second sequence of the VCM show significantly lower average contributions in lie than in baseline. In contrast, the average cooperation rate in truth falls between the ones from the other two treatments. Differences between truth and the other treatments are not significant. We identify two effects leading to this finding: if the manipulation is revealed, contribution rates decline approximately at a similar rate independently of the type of feedback. However, the potentially manipulated feedback in lie yields significantly lower levels of initial contributions than truthful feedback. Thus, playing another sequence with potentially manipulated feedback leads to lower welfare (in the sense of accumulated payoffs) across the entire second sequence than the inconvenient truth.
Our experimental results complement a study by Hoffmann et al. [
8] who compare the welfare implications of different types of noble lies against a setting without lies
3. They show that a noble lie to all participants does not travel far, while lying selectively to very cooperative players significantly improves the social welfare compared to the setting without the lie—even if the lie’s nature is revealed between sequences. Both Hoffmann et al.’s and our paper follow a stream of literature analyzing moral concerns in lying: Gneezy [
11] shows in his seminal paper that people trade off material payoffs against moral scruples in sender–receiver games. In the same context, Sanchez-Pages and Vorsatz [
12] find a positive correlation between lying and punishing liars.
Serra-Garcia et al. explore the relation between lying and communication within repeated public good games. Serra-Garcia et al. [
13] find that precise communication leads to frequent lying, while lying is less frequent when vague communication is allowed. In turn, communication receivers do not seem to realize that vague messages indicate truthful information. Serra-Garcia et al. [
14] show that communication content that relates to promise components leads to less lying and less free riding. Related to this issue, Engel et al. [
15] and Irlenbusch and Rilke [
16] test the effect of selective feedback information in public good games. The latter paper shows that only if the selection criteria for feedback is not disclosed to the participants can samples with very cooperative players boost cooperation, while samples with very uncooperative players hamper it.
Building on this rich literature, we analyze the “best behavior” in the aftermath of a noble lie: we ask for the welfare effects of different feedback mechanisms after the noble lie has been exposed. In other words, we test whether truthful or inflated feedback yields superior payoffs in a second sequence of public good games following a first sequence of public good games with inflated feedback (the noble lie).
Our paper is organized as follows: we first discuss the details of our experimental game as well as the experimental procedure and formulate behavioral expectations. We then describe and analyze the results of the experiment and finally conclude with an answer to our questions and an outlook on future research concerning lying in politics.
2. The Experimental Design
2.1. The Game
To analyze our research question, we use the linear standard VCM as an experimental tool. This design has widely been tested experimentally by biologists, economists and political scientists (see Zelmer [
17] and Chaudhuri [
18] for surveys). The VCM allows us to investigate cooperation behavior in response to different feedback regimes. It is not tailored to a specific case or application but serves as a framework that incorporates important features common to many different situations.
All participants play two sequences of twenty periods of the following stage game in groups of four: at the beginning of each period, each player receives an endowment of 20 ECU (experimental currency units). Players simultaneously but covertly decide how many ECU they contribute to the public good, , with . Each ECU contributed to the public good is multiplied by 1.6 and then divided among the four players. Thus, each ECU contributed yields a profit of 0.4 ECU (the marginal per capita return) to each player including i. Each ECU not contributed to the public good is privately kept and yields a benefit of 1 ECU to player i only. Therefore, player i’s individual payoff function is . All parameters are common knowledge for all participants of the experiment. Throughout the entire experiment, players remain in the same group of four players, both within each sequence, and across the two sequences (i.e., from period 1 to period 40).
2.2. Procedure
An experimental session proceeds as follows: once all subjects are seated, written instructions on sequence 1 are handed to them before the experimenter reads them out loud. Subjects are then given the opportunity to ask questions in private. Before the experiment starts, subjects answer a set of questions to test their understanding of the instructions. They are informed that there will be two sequences but no details on sequence 2 are given at the start of the experiment. At the start of sequence 2, subjects receive a new set of instructions. After completing sequence 1 and 2, subjects answer a short socio-demographic questionnaire. Finally, subjects receive profits from one randomly determined period of each sequence
4.
In the first sequence, we implement the following feedback mechanism at the end of each period: participants receive feedback on the average contribution of the other three group members
(rounded to the next full integer). Subjects contributing more than average receive inflated information: their feedback shows the amount of their own contribution as being the average (i.e.,
). All other subjects are shown the actual average contribution of the other group members
5. Notice again that we clarify at the beginning of the experiment that the feedback they receive during the experiment on group averages may deviate from the true average.
Thus, players contributing more than average are likely to be too optimistic in regards to the cooperativeness of the other group members. As a result, these subjects keep up their high contribution level. This increases the total amount of income for the group and may even foster higher contributions of the other players. The latter is possible because the increased true average is shown to the below and at average contributors, thus providing an incentive for those players to increase their contributions in the next round as well. This group welfare increasing effect of the above described inflated feedback is the reason why we call this manipulation a “noble lie”.
In the second sequence, we introduce three treatment variations of the game. In the baseline condition, prior to the start of sequence 2, participants are shown the (displayed) average contribution of all other participants across the previous twenty periods. Furthermore, they are informed that they will play another twenty periods of the same game. Hence, the noble lie is not fully revealed. In the lie and truth condition, we reveal the exact feedback mechanism to all participants after sequence 1. Participants are informed that they received correct feedback if they contributed at or below average, and that feedback did equal their own contribution if they contributed above average. In addition, participants are informed about the actual average contribution and the displayed average contribution of all other participants across the previous twenty periods.
In the lie condition, the conditionally inflated feedback mechanism is implemented in the following twenty periods again. However, now players know that receiving feedback equaling their own contribution could mean either of two things: (a) their contribution is exactly at the group average or (b) it is above the group average and they do not know the true value of this average. Finally, in the truth condition, players are provided with correct feedback in sequence 2 and they are aware of this.
At the end of the second sequence, we inform participants in all treatment conditions about the true nature of the feedback provided in the two sequences, and their accumulated payoffs.
2.3. Predictions
Since subjects lose 0.6 ECU per ECU contributed, the individually optimal strategy is to keep the whole endowment—independently of the exact feedback participants receive. The collectively optimal strategy, however, is to contribute fully, since all contributed ECU’s are multiplied by 1.6 before they are divided up among the players who then receive 0.4 ECU each. The rationale of individual and social optimal strategies remains unchanged if the game is played repeatedly over a finite number of periods. As a consequence, individual contributions to the public good reflect players’ voluntary cooperation.
As shown by Hoffmann et al. [
8], partially inflated feedback fosters overall cooperativeness substantially. Therefore, we expect higher contributions in the second sequence of
baseline than in the other two treatments. The crucial question is: how do participants respond to the information that feedback was inflated in the first sequence? That is, how do subjects respond contribution-wise to potentially wrong feedback
in the second sequence of
lie compared to the corresponding correct but inconvenient feedback
in
truth. We call this latter feedback “inconvenient” because it informs the player that her fellow players are less cooperative than she is.
Suppose now that players are loss averse in the sense that they maximize their contributions as long as they receive a payoff from the public good at least equivalent to their contribution to the public good
6. That is, instead of maximizing utility
(in the case of narrow self-interest) or
(in case of social utility), subjects simply
subject to
. For the symmetric equilibrium, if all four subjects follow this strategy, this would obviously lead to full contributions by all subjects. However, if subjects hold diverse beliefs regarding contributions (and perhaps some subjects do not follow this strategy), rich dynamics may unfold.
In
truth, this leads to a decrease in contributions as long as
and to stable contributions otherwise.
In turn, players who contribute more than the average in
lie cannot follow the same rationale, since they are not informed about the true
(and are aware of this in the second sequence). Here, we assume that they form a belief regarding the true average contribution as a fraction
δ (
) of their own contribution
. Therefore, in
lie Equation (
1) changes to
As mentioned above, we inform participants about the actual average contribution and the displayed average contribution of all other participants during the first twenty periods between the first and the second sequence. Therefore, the ratio seems to be a good proxy for δ.
Importantly, Equation (
2) is independent from the actual contribution level. Therefore, we do not presume a gradual adaptation of contributions as predicted for
truth. Rather than adapting their contributions based on those of the others in the last period, contributors have to rely on their beliefs about the
lie condition. Hence, we assume that cooperative participants who usually contribute above the average do so more “cautiously” right from the start of the second sequence (i.e., after being informed about the true nature of feedback inflation). For this reason, we hypothesize
Hypothesis Average contributions in lie drop initially in the second sequence, while in truth they decrease gradually in the course of the second sequence. As a consequence, total payoffs across the second sequence are higher in truth than in lie.
3. Results
All in all, we ran ten sessions with 196 participants who were matched randomly into groups of four, totaling 49 groups; each subject participated in only one treatment condition. One group served as an independent observation and we collected 16 observations in
baseline, 16 in
lie, and 17 in
truth 7. The experiment was run in June and July 2013 as well as in February 2015 in the experimental laboratory of the Faculty of Business, Economics and Social Sciences at the University of Hamburg. The University of Hamburg is a large public university with approximately 40’000 students in the center of Hamburg, Germany. The experiment was programmed using the software package zTree [
20] (version 3.5.1, Fischbacher and Schmid, Kreuzlingen & Zurich, Switzerland), and hroot [
21] (version 2.0, Bock, Baetge and Nicklisch, Hamburg, Germany) was used for recruiting. Most participants were students (two non-students) with different academic backgrounds including economics; 58% were women, and the median age was 24. Sessions typically lasted 60 min and the average payoff was 11.51 Euros. Subjects received cash payments immediately after the session was over.
Let us start with the average contributions in the first and the second sequence of the experiment.
Figure 1 shows the evolution of average contributions by periods and across treatment conditions. Notice that, in addition, it depicts the evolution of average contributions for the sequences of twenty rounds of a VCM without any feedback inflation (
null). The comparison with our treatment conditions allows us to assess the overall benefits of applying a noble lie at all
8. As expected, there are no significant differences between our three treatments in the first sequence. However, the development contrasts with the typical evolution of voluntary cooperation in a public good game where contributions constantly decrease over time (compare the
null treatment). In our experiments, contributions remain stable at a level of about 11 out of 20 ECU with mean contributions at 10.6 in
baseline, 11.2 in
lie, and 11.0 in
truth. Comparing the contributions between our treatment conditions, both for the first period and across all periods of the first sequence, there are no significant differences
9.
Interestingly, not all players are equally likely affected by the noble lie. That is, while there are about 22 percent of players who never or almost never receive inflated feedback (at most in two out of 20 periods), there are 25 percent of players who always or almost always see inflated feedback (at least in 18 out of 20 periods)
10. Thus, there seems to be a sub-population of stable cooperators who (almost always) see false feedback in the first sequence. We will pay attention to this heterogeneity regarding the exposure to the royal lie below when we analyze how players in
lie and
truth choose their contribution in period 21 (i.e., immediately after they are informed about the exact feedback mechanism).
Turning to the second sequence of the experiment, the development of cooperation rates differs substantially between treatments after the feedback mechanism is revealed. It seems that players’ confidence in the cooperation rate is unsettled, so that contributions decrease more rapidly in
lie and
truth in comparison to
baseline. Mean cooperation rates across the entire second sequence are 10.7 in
baseline, 6.6 in
lie, and 8.1 in
truth 11. The difference between
lie and
baseline is significant (
, two-sided Wilcoxon–Mann–Whitney rank sum test), while the differences between
truth and
baseline (
, two-sided test) and between
lie and
truth are insignificant (
, two-sided test).
Despite the constantly decreasing contributions after the feedback mechanism is revealed in
lie and
truth, there is an overall gain from the introduction of the noble lie for players in comparison to
null: average contributions across both sequences are 8.9 in
lie, 9.5 in
truth, and 5.9 in
null. Differences among average contributions between
lie and
null, and between
truth and
null are significant
12.
As one sees in
Figure 1, the difference between
lie on the one hand and
truth as well as
baseline on the other is particularly pronounced in the first period of the second sequence. Here, mean contributions are 8.7 in
lie, 11.7 in
baseline, and 11 in
truth; the differences between
lie and
baseline (
truth) is (weakly) significant (
and
, respectively, two-sided tests), while the latter two differ insignificantly (
). Thus in line with our hypothesis, the initial contributions in
lie seem to be substantially influenced by the inflated feedback. The resulting difference between contributions in
lie and the other two conditions remains recognizable—though partly insignificant—until the end of the second sequence.
Result 1. In sequence 2, initial as well as average contributions across the entire sequence are lower under lie than under baseline. However, only initial contributions are lower under lie than under truth, while average contributions across the entire sequence do not differ significantly.
We hypothesized earlier that initial contributions at the beginning of the second sequence drop more rigorously in lie because informed adaptation of contributions in the course of the sequence is far more difficult for cooperative participants in this treatment than in truth. To test this claim, we use the average ratio of feedback inflation they experienced during the first sequence (and which they learn at the end of the first sequence) as an indicator for their degree of cooperativeness. The smaller this ratio is, the more cooperative they were (relative to other group members).
In turn, we compute the drop in initial contributions as the difference between the contribution with which they start the sequence after being informed precisely about the feedback inflation (i.e., the in period 21) and the contribution with which participants “normally” start a sequence of public goods games (i.e., the in period 1). The premise of our hypothesis holds if we find a positive relation between ratio of feedback inflation in lie and a zero or at least a weaker relation in truth.
Figure 2 illustrates a slightly positive relation between the ratio of feedback inflation and the change in initial contributions in both treatments. Moreover, it seems that the relation is more pronounced in
lie than in
trust. In other words, the importance of the observed accuracy of feedback in the first sequence for the initial contribution in the second sequence is substantially higher in
lie than in
truth 13.
We would like to stress that there is another insight from
Figure 2: the dashed-dotted black (dashed red) line shows the polynomial best fit for
in
lie (
truth). This best fit is negative for above average contributors (with
) and positive for below average contributors (with
) in
truth implying that initial contributions for both groups converge in the second sequence on average. However, the best fit is inverted u-shaped and negative for all contributors in
lie, implying that all players decrease their contributions on average. One can interpret this finding such that below average contributors respond to the feedback inflation (after they are informed on the true nature of the manipulation) by lowering cooperation since they cannot foster the cooperation of above average contributors with their own contributions. In this sense, the publicly known feedback manipulation in
lie undermines cooperation in the entire group.
To gain more insight into the dynamics of contributions in consecutive periods, we analyze individual responses to received feedback in a Tobit regression model with individual random effects as model I. We analyze the dependent variable which is censored within the limits 0 and 20 with periods . We estimate the coefficients for the contribution in , , the dummy variables and , which are 1 if the observation comes from the lie (truth) treatment, and 0 otherwise.
In addition, we introduce two independent variables reflecting the received feedback. stands for feedback concerning the average contributions of the other group members in if i contributed less than the average in that round. That is, the coefficient for measures the response to the correct feedback across all treatments in terms of i’s consecutive contribution. then is a dummy variable which is 1 if i contributes above average in , and 0 otherwise. Thus, indicates the response of i who contributes above average, whereas the interaction terms and indicate deviations from the former response due to potentially manipulated feedback in lie, and due to the inconvenient truth that other group members earned money at the expense of i in truth.
Finally, we consider a linear time trend
t, as cooperation rates typically decline towards the end of the experiment. As a robustness check, we estimate a level two mixed-effect maximum likelihood estimation with group fixed effects and individual random effects on the same set of independent variables in model II
14. Estimation results are summarized in
Table 1. We report estimated coefficients along with standard errors, number of observations (
), and number of independent observations (
). Asterisks indicate significance levels. The fitness of the models are tested using Wald-
-tests.
When interpreting the results, we follow a conservative approach referring to the minimum of the significance level of model I and model II for estimated coefficients. We find strong evidence for a significant positive path dependency of contributions (
) while there is an overall negative time trend (
t) in the data. Both findings are not surprising and in line with previous studies (e.g., Zelmer [
17]). In addition, there is weak evidence that the overall contribution level in
lie is lower than in the other two treatments—despite the fact that contributions in the initial period of the second sequence (i.e., period 21) are not considered in the estimations.
Regarding the effect of received feedback, we find strong evidence for an adjustment of below average contributors: the higher the contributions of the other group members are on average, the more do contributions increase in round t (see the coefficient for ). This observation suggests conditional cooperation of below average contributors. With respect to above and at average contributors, there is a significant influence of the revelation of the feedback mechanism on the adjustment of contributions: while we find no significant coefficient for , coefficients for the interaction term is significantly negative. Interestingly, observing the inconvenient truth in truth leads to a similar response: -tests cannot reject the hypothesis that the coefficients and are the same ( for model I and for model II).
Thus, both potentially inflated feedback and the inconvenient truth yield approximately the same response in terms of contributions. However, it could be that different motives lead to the decrease in contributions in truth and in lie; while above-average contributors in the former treatment reduce their contributions in order to avoid being a sucker, in the latter treatment it could be the mere uncertainty about size of contributions which drives participants to contribute more cautiously. In summary, combining the results from the earlier analysis on the difference between the initial contribution of the second and the first sequence (i.e., in period 21 and in period 1) with the regression results leads to the following:
Result 2. Initial contributions in the second sequence of lie are significantly lower than in both other treatments. However, above average contributors who receive potentially inflated feedback in lie contribute similarly as above average contributors who receive truthful feedback in truth.