2. Preliminaries
In this article, X will always denote a nonempty set.
Definition 1. A binary relation on X is a subset of the Cartesian product . Given two elements , we will use the standard notation to express that the pair belongs to .
In association with a binary relation on X, we consider its negation (respectively, its transpose) as the binary relation (respectively, ) on X given by for every (respectively, given by for every . We also define the adjoint of the given relation , as .
A binary relation defined on a set X is called the following terms:
- (i)
Reflexive if holds for every ;
- (ii)
Irreflexive if holds for every ;
- (iii)
Symmetric if and coincide;
- (iv)
Antisymmetric if ;
- (v)
Asymmetric if ;
- (vi)
Complete if ;
- (vii)
Transitive if for every .
In the particular case of a set X where some kind of ordering has been defined, the standard notation is different.
Definition 2. A preorder ≿ on X is a binary relation on X that is reflexive and transitive. An antisymmetric preorder is said to be an order. A total preorder ≿ on a set X is a preorder such that if then holds. If ≿ is a preorder on X, then as usual we denote the associated asymmetric relation by ≻ and the associated equivalence relation by ∼ and these are defined by and .
A total preorder ≿ defined on X is usually called a (crisp) preference on X.
Definition 3. Let be a binary relation on X. We say that decomposes into a symmetric binary relation (denoted by ) and an asymmetric binary relation (denoted by ) if and .
Proposition 1. Let ≿ be a preorder on a set X. It decomposes into ≻ and ∼. It is the unique decomposition of ≿ into asymmetric and symmetric relations.
Proof. See the proof in [
23] (Theorem 1). ☐
Definition 4. A fuzzy subset H of X is defined as a function . The function is called the membership function of H. In the particular case when is dichotomic and takes values in , the corresponding subset defined by means of is a subset of X in the classical crisp sense (the term crisp is usually understood in these contexts as meaning nonfuzzy).
Definition 5. A fuzzy binary relation on X is a function . We say that R is symmetric if for every , and we say that R is asymmetric if, for every , implies that holds. Moreover, R is said to be reflexive if for any .
Definition 6. A triangular norm (t-norm for short) is a function satisfying the following properties:
- (i)
Boundary conditions: , and , for every .
- (ii)
Monotonicity: T is nondecreasing with respect to each variable; that is if and , then holds true.
- (iii)
T is commutative: holds for every .
- (iv)
T is associative: holds for any .
Definition 7. A triangular conorm (t-conorm for short) is a function satisfying the following properties:
- (i)
Boundary conditions: , and , for every .
- (ii)
Monotonicity: S is nondecreasing with respect to each variable; that is, if and , then holds true.
- (iii)
S is commutative: holds for every .
- (iv)
S is associative: holds for any .
Henceforth, the symbol T will denote a t-norm whereas the symbol S will stand for a t-conorm.
Remark 1. - (i)
In this article, we will use t-norms and t-conorms to define the decomposition of a fuzzy binary relation. However, in the proofs below, we will only use properties i and of Definitions 6 and 7. This fact shows that we could define a decomposition with respect to a more general category of operators (for example preaggregation functions [24], copulas [25], fusion functions [26], mixture functions [27], overlap functions [28], penalty functions [29], etc.). - (ii)
We have decided to use t-norms and t-conorms because they are the fuzzy generalizations of the classic intersection and union operators and, more importantly, because we want to be coherent with the pre-existing literature that analyzes, studies and uses decompositions in practice [3,5,6]. - (iii)
In addition, in the search of an even more general setting than the one considered here with t-norms and t-conorms, we should also make a choice (e.g., copulas) and update to the current year the existing literature. However, as far as we know, the most recent literature on these more general categories of operators seems to use decompositions only in particular cases and regarding some very concrete and particular question or application in practice, mainly related to algorithms (see [30]) or computer science (see [31]). - (iv)
Notice, in addition, that those new references do not work, a priori, with the intention of constructing a normative theory that could encompass other previously issued decompositions, as we intend to construct here for t-norms and t-conorms. Instead, as already said, they just work with quite particular and concrete aspects of practice (see, e.g., [30]). - (v)
Other totally different kinds of decompositions of fuzzy relations, paying attention to algebraical aspects of matrix theory, may be seen in [32]. However, they seem to be unrelated to the scope of the present manuscript.
Let , and be fuzzy binary relations on X. Then, the notation will mean from now on that, for every , holds. Obviously, we use a similar convention for a t-conorm S.
Definition 8. Let T and S, respectively, be a t-norm and a t-conorm. An element is said to be a 0-divisor of T if there exists some such that . Also, an element is called a 1-divisor of S if there exists some such that .
Definition 9. A t-norm T (respectively, a t-conorm S) is called strict if it is strictly increasing on each variable on (respectively, ). In other words, for all with , if (respectively, if ).
3. Decompositions of Fuzzy Binary Relations
In the present manuscript, we study decompositions based on t-norms and t-conorms, respectively, playing the crisp intersection and union roles. This approach motivates the following definition used by Dutta [
15] in his first article studying the fuzzy Arrovian model. Recently, it has been rescued by Subramanian [
33] in his study of the Arrovian model.
Definition 10. Let and I be fuzzy binary relations on X (with P an asymmetric fuzzy binary relation and I a symmetric binary relation). Let T (respectively, S) stand for a triangular norm (respectively, conorm). We say that R strongly decomposes, with respect to , into , if and .
Even if the decomposition defined above is the natural generalization of the usual crisp decomposition, it is not widespread in the literature. Indeed, many authors use some weaker versions [
3,
5,
6,
15,
16]. The following definition follows the same spirit but disregards the role that any t-norm could play:
Definition 11. Let R be a fuzzy binary relation on a set X. Let S be a t-conorm. We say that R weakly decomposes into (with P an asymmetric fuzzy binary relation and I a symmetric binary relation) if and if for every it holds true that if , then .
We have two comments about the definitions above. First, notice that the weak decomposition is more general than the stronger one. Moreover, they are not equivalent. The following example proves it:
Example 1. Let and let R be a fuzzy binary relation defined on X as follows: and . We define the symmetric relation I as and . If we define P as and 0 on the remaining cases, we can check that R weakly decomposes into with respect the t-conorm maximum . However, R does not strongly decomposes into with respect to the conorm and any t-norm T because .
The second observation is about the second condition in Definition 11. It has been introduced after removing the t-norm from Definition 10 because we need decompositions to be generalizations of the crisp one (Definition 3). It implies that crisp relations must decompose into two crisp relations and these must be unique. But, without this condition, if and a fuzzy binary relation R on X is defined as , it decomposes to with and and 0 otherwise.
Finally, in a previous paper [
23] the authors proved some necessary conditions for these kinds of decompositions. We will include them here for the sake of completeness.
Proposition 2. Let S be a t-conorm. Let R be a fuzzy binary relation defined on X. Assume that R can be expressed as (where I (respectively, P) is a symmetric (respectively, asymmetric) fuzzy binary relation). Then, for every it holds that .
Proof. See the proof in [
23] (Proposition 2). ☐
Proposition 3. Let S be a t-conorm. Every fuzzy relation R on X can be expressed as (where I (respectively, P) is a symmetric (respectively, asymmetric) fuzzy binary relation) if and only if S is continuous in the first coordinate (with respect to the Euclidean topology on the unit interval ).
Proof. It is straightforward to notice that the proof is in everything similar to that of [
23] (Proposition 3). That is why we omit it here. ☐
The proof of Proposition3 in [
23] gave us a method to obtain a candidate for the asymmetric component
P computed from
R. In other words, if
R decomposes, one of its decompositions is the pair
provided by this method.
As Proposition 2 states, the I component is a minimum, whereas the candidate for the P component is defined as .
To abbreviate that, in the sequel we use the notation .
Remark 2. Notice that since S is commutative, continuity on one of its coordinates implies continuity on both coordinates (considered separately). However, it does not imply the continuity for a general symmetric real function. However, since S is nondecreasing, both conditions are equivalent (see, e.g., [34] (Proposition 1)). Then, in Proposition 3, S being continuous in the first coordinate is equivalent to S being continuous. In spite of this fact, in this article we will specify over which component S must be continuous. We proceed this way because the same results could be useful for the noncommutative operators we have listed in Remark 1.
In the literature, there are similar results to that stated in Proposition 2 (see [
3,
5,
6]). In fact, even Fono and Andjiga [
6] use a similar strategy to the one we use in Proposition 3. However, the definitions of decompositions used in these works are more general than the weak decomposition defined in the present manuscript. Their definition is so general that they have to impose additional constraints. They end up studying
regular decompositions, and these are actually less general than Definition 11.
In addition, in contrast to the work of Fono and Andjiga [
6], here we do not assume a priori any continuity condition on
S. Although they assume upper continuity in the definition of its decomposition, we have seen using Proposition 3 above that the continuity on the first component is a necessary condition for the existence of our decompositions. So, the continuity condition over
S is a consequence of
S admitting decompositions, and it is not imposed a priori.
In
Section 4, we will characterize the existence and the uniqueness of strong decompositions, whereas in
Section 5 we characterize them for weak decompositions.
Given a fuzzy binary relation
R, we could study the conditions that should satisfy
R in order to decompose. However, in the Social Choice models [
3,
5,
15,
16] we usually impose that all of the binary relations of a suitable set must admit a decomposition. For that reason, we will start studying under which conditions all elements in
(the set of fuzzy binary relations on
X) decompose. Next, in
Appendix A we will explore the decomposition on subsets of
, mainly the subsets obtained by imposing some kind of transitivity and connectedness to fuzzy binary relations.
4. Analysis and Structure of Strong Decompositions of Fuzzy Binary Relations
This section contains two main results. We characterize the existence and the uniqueness of strong decompositions based upon the divisors of a t-norm T and a t-conorm S. First, we start with some more specific (and preparatory) results, which will motivate the general theorems to be proved next.
First, we focus on the case in which the used t-norm is the drastic t-norm
(see its definition in Example A1 in
Appendix B). The following results prove that being decomposable with respect
is a necessary condition for being decomposable with respect to any other t-norm.
Proposition 4. Let R be a fuzzy binary relation on X. Let S be a t-conorm and T a t-norm. If R strongly decomposes into (with respect to S and T), then R decomposes into with respect to S and .
Proof. It is straightforward if we use the following fact: every t-norm is bounded below by the drastic t-norm. ☐
Considering the result above, we characterize as a first step the existence of decompositions with respect .
Proposition 5. Let S be a t-conorm continuous in the first component. Any is strongly decomposable with respect to S and if and only if every is a 1-divisor (with respect to S).
Proof. To prove the direct implication, let and consider a fuzzy binary relation R such that, for a pair of values , and . By hypothesis, there exist P and I such that and because . Hence, is a 1-divisor.
To prove the converse implication, it is enough to see that the weak decomposition proposed in the proof of Proposition 3 satisfies, for every , that . If we assume that , then , , and or . If , then and , but this contradicts the fact that . Moreover, if (and ), we state that and, since , is a 1-divisor. So, there is an with . However, by the definition of P, we have that , and this is a contradiction. ☐
The above proposition makes us think that the relation between the 0-divisors (respectively, 1-divisors) of a t-norm T (respectively, of a t-conorm S) is the keystone in the existence of strong decompositions.
The argument in the proof is based upon avoiding being positive. Since I could achieve any value (see Proposition 2), any of these values must have a 0-divisor.
The next step is the generalization of Proposition 5 to any t-norm. For that reason, we state the following definition.
Definition 12. Let S (respectively, T) be a triangular conorm (respectively, a t-norm). Given any , we define the 1-interval associated with w as . (It is straightforward to check that and are intervals because of the monotonicity of S and T. Moreover, and are always satisfied.) Similarly, the 0-interval associated with w is defined by .
Proposition 6. Let S and T, respectively, be a t-conorm and a t-norm, and let X be a set. Every fuzzy binary relation on X is strongly decomposable with respect to S and T if and only if for all it holds true that , and the triangular conorm S is continuous on the first coordinate.
Proof. To prove the direct implication, for every consider a fuzzy binary relation R with and . By hypothesis, R strongly decomposes into a pair . We have that and , and now using that (Proposition 2), we obtain that .
To prove the converse implication, we only need to see that the decomposition obtained in the proof of Proposition 3 satisfies for all . To do so, we can assume without loss of generality that . First, when , we have that . In this situation, we claim that because S is continuous on the first component. Moreover, since is the minimum of , and , we conclude that and we see that . In addition, when , we define as the fuzzy binary relation that coincides with R everywhere except on the pair , for which we define . decomposes into . It can be checked, using the definition, that . Finally, notice that we are now in the previous situation already analyzed, because , and . ☐
Taking into account the previous proof, the condition of uniqueness is quite natural. The set contains all the possible values for the asymmetric part . Hence, in order to achieve uniqueness, it is enough to request this set to have just a single element.
Proposition 7. Every binary fuzzy relation on X is strongly decomposable with respect to S and T, in a unique way, if and only if the t-conorm S is continuous in the first component and for all it holds true that .
Proof. Suppose that there are with and such that . We fix now a pair and define a binary relation as and if . Additionally, we define three binary relations for every as follows: , if , and . It remains to prove that R strongly decomposes in as well as , and therefore the decomposition is not unique.
Using the arguments in the proof of Proposition 6 we only need to check that and . But these assertions are indeed true because and by hypothesis.
Suppose that R strongly decomposes into and . Proposition 2 guarantees that , so there are such that . Now, we define , and . To conclude, by the definition of a strong decomposition we can guarantee now that . ☐
The main problem that we face when dealing with strong decompositions is that the conditions for their existence and uniqueness are too restrictive. In
Appendix B, we can see some examples for the most usual t-norms and t-conorms. For that reason, we will study now a weaker version of a decomposition defined by only using a t-conorm.
Furthermore, another reason to proceed in that way is that the main literature, as far as we know, uses this second type of decomposition, namely the so-called weak decomposition.
5. Weak Decompositions of Fuzzy Binary Relations
We can encounter, in the specialized literature, some pioneer introductions of decompositions similar to the weak ones considered here, as isolated proposals to derive two binary relations from a single one generalizing the crisp decompositions. However, no general framework discussing decompositions was proposed in those studies [
1,
4,
15,
16,
35].
Richardson in [
36] proposed a general framework, and it has been adopted by other authors, such as Fono and Andjiga in [
6] or Gibilisco et al. in [
3]. The general framework introduced by Richardson is a priori more general than Definition 11. However, in order to obtain results, they request that all their decompositions satisfy a property that they call simplicity, and then, because of having asked this extra property, our Definition 11 becomes more general than theirs with that condition of “simplicity” added.
Proposition 8. Let S be a t-conorm and X a set. Every fuzzy relation R on X admits a weak decomposition if and only if S is continuous in the first coordinate (with respect to the Euclidean topology on the unit interval ).
Proof. Notice that Proposition 3 guarantees the direct implication. For the converse implication, we also use the decomposition defined from R proposed in the proof of Proposition 3. It only remains to show that such a pair is a weak decomposition. But this is indeed the case because, if (with ), then and . ☐
In the following example, we compute some weak decompositions for the main t-conorms, using the formula from Proposition 3, namely .
Example 2. Let R be a fuzzy binary relation on X. Let S be a t-conorm. Using the proof of Proposition 3, we can compute a decomposition of R with respect to several well-known t-conorms (Example A1 contains their definitions).and (for every ). We point out that these decompositions already appeared as suitable expressions in the previous literature, in this setting. For instance, was considered in [15,35], in [4,15] and in [3]. The last proposition in this section characterizes the uniqueness of weak decompositions (provided that they exist).
Proposition 9. Let S be a t-conorm that is continuous in the first coordinate. Let R be a fuzzy binary relation on X. R has a unique weak decomposition in terms of S if and only if S is strictly increasing in the first coordinate. (Here, being strictly increasing has to be interpreted in the sense of Definition 9. No t-conorm is strictly increasing on the whole domain .)
Proof. Suppose that R decomposes into two distinct weak decompositions and . We can suppose without a loss of generality that there exist such that . Also, because . Hence, using the condition of strict increasingness, we see that . Thus, we have obtained a contradiction, and, consequently, the decomposition is unique.
If S is not strict, there are with and . We can define a binary relation R as , for some and at any other pair . It can be checked that R weakly decompose into and defined as (for every ) and , whereas and at any other pair . ☐
In the
Appendix B,
Table A1 furnishes information about decomposability, analyzing which ones among the main t-conorms can decompose all fuzzy binary relations.
6. Applications of Decompositions of Fuzzy Binary Relations into Preference Modeling under Uncertainty
In this section, we will apply the results of the previous sections about the decomposition of fuzzy binary relations to fuzzy Arrovian models.
In the literature, it is required to obtain a strict preference
P and an indifference preference
I from a weak preference
R. However, the most common tendency is to first define a rule to obtain
P and
I and then study their properties [
3,
16,
35]. Moreover, most of the authors in the Arrovian literature have used the type of decompositions studied in
Section 4 and
Section 5 to define such rules [
3,
5,
6,
15,
37]. For instance, the probabilistic t-conorm induces a unique decomposition (see Equation (
3) in Example 2 and
Table A1). In the following pages, we will see that the decomposition generated by the probabilistic t-conorm satisfies the desired properties in fuzzy Social Choice. However, other conorms behave differently. Consider the following example:
Example 3. Consider the following t-conorm S defined as the ordinal sum of a Łukasiewicz t-conorm (see [38] (Definition 3.68)).Any fuzzy binary relation weakly decomposes with respect to S because it is continuous (see Proposition 8). However, consider the binary relation R on , defined as and . It decomposes into , where , and . How could it be that, despite x and y playing the same role in R, x is strictly preferred over y? This is one of the situations that are avoided implicitly in fuzzy Arrovian models [3]. Therefore, we will first define what we expect (as Social Choice practitioners) from R, P, I and the relationship among them and, straightaway, how strong and weak decompositions can be used to obtain suitable decomposition rules.
With that purpose in mind, we use the concept of the preference structure (see, e.g., [
39,
40]) because its definition does not rely upon any concept related to decomposition rules. A preference structure is a triplet
of fuzzy binary relations satisfying the properties of Definition 13 below.
Definition 13 ([
41] (Definition 2.15))
. Given a set X, a fuzzy preference on X is a triplet of fuzzy binary relations on X that satisfies the following conditions:- (FP1)
implies , for all (P is asymmetric);
- (FP2)
, for all (I is symmetric);
- (FP3)
for every ;
- (FP4)
if and only if , for every ;
- (FP5)
If , then , for all ;
- (FP6)
If and , then holds true for every .
We call R the weak preference component, P the strict preference component and I the indifference component.
Using this definition, we state a framework to study the decomposition rules. It is equivalent to the standard definitions in several fuzzy Arrovian models [
3,
6,
15]. Now, we can use this framework to apply the decompositions studied in the previous sections to decomposition rules. First, we need to define what we understand as a decomposition rule:
Definition 14. Let be a family of fuzzy binary relations on a set X. A decomposition rule on is a map , such that for every , if , then is a fuzzy preference in the sense of Definition 13.
Our goal in this section will be to study when the decompositions already introduced through
Section 4 and
Section 5 induce or are compatible with a decomposition rule, in the following sense of the next Definition 15.
Definition 15. Let T be a t-norm, S a t-conorm and ϕ a decomposition rule on :
- (i)
We say that ϕ is -strong (resp. S-weak) compatible if, for every , it holds true that is a strong (resp. weak) decomposition of R with respect to T and S (resp. S).
- (ii)
We say that ϕ is induced by (resp S) if ϕ is -strong (resp. S-weak) compatible and for every it holds, in addition, that is the unique decomposition of R, which induces a preference. That is, if is a decomposition of R and is a preference, then . In that case, we denote by (resp. ) the induced decomposition rule.
Example 4. The decomposition rule defined in as and is neither -strong nor S-weak compatible for any T and S: if and , then .
Moreover, consider the decomposition rules (see Example 2) and defined as if and otherwise. They are both -weak compatible, so neither of them are induced by . Finally, Proposition 11 proves that is induced by .
First, we will focus on the case in the Definition 15 above. We will study which t-norms and t-conorms admit decomposition rules compatible with them. Next, we will focus on the t-norms and t-conorms that induce decomposition rules (case ).
As in the previous sections, we will restrict our study to the case , since other domains could lead to different results.
Proposition 10. Let R be a fuzzy binary relation on X. Let S be a t-conorm and let T be a t-norm. If is a strong or a weak decomposition of R with respect to T and S or respect to S, then the properties , , , and and the direct implication in the statement of Definition 13 hold true.
Moreover, the converse of is satisfied if for every there exists a neighborhood of 0 in which is strictly increasing.
Proof. Conditions and are obtained from the definition of a decomposition. To prove , notice that .
To prove notice that if , then .
Property is a direct consequence of the monotonicity of S.
Finally, to prove the direct implication of , observe that if , by property it follows now that holds true. But, since I is symmetric, so that , we obtain .
Additionally, suppose that S satisfies the last property. If , then . Hence, we may now conclude that . ☐
In the following example, we can see a decomposition that satisfies all the properties above but with the converse implication in and, consequently, does not give rise to a fuzzy preference.
Example 5. Let R be a fuzzy binary relation defined on a set X. Consider the fuzzy binary relations P and I on X defined as follows:and . Notice that R weakly decomposes into with respect to and this decomposition is not the same as the one arising in Example 2. The case of a weak decomposition with respect to is paradigmatic in the literature, and we will use it to motivate the main result in this section.
The decomposition (
1) shown in Example 2 actually appeared early in the specialized literature [
35], usually as a suitable decomposition rule in several contexts. The example above shows that it is not the unique weak decomposition with respect to
. However, the following proposition proves that it is the unique decomposition that defines a fuzzy preference. That is,
induces a decomposition rule.
Proposition 11. Let R be a fuzzy binary relation on a set X. There exists a unique decomposition of R with respect to the t-conorm satisfying that is a fuzzy preference.
Proof. Consider a fuzzy binary relation R. The maximum is a continuous t-conorm. By Proposition 3, R is decomposable. Suppose that there are two different decompositions and of R such that both and are fuzzy preferences. First, by Proposition 2, holds. If , we can assume, without a loss of generality, that there are with .
From the equality , we obtain that . Using that (Proposition 2), we conclude that . We have finally arrived at a contradiction because, using , we obtain that . ☐
Remark 3. In Proposition 10, we have proved that the property of S “for every t, having a neighbourhood of 0 such that is strictly increasing” implies .
If we could find a property of S equivalent to , then the characterization of decompositions that are a preference would be completed. Unfortunately, Example 5 makes us think that such a property does not exist.
Assuming the existence of such a property q, may or may not satisfy q. If satisfied it, then all weak decompositions (with respect to ) should define a preference, but the decomposition in Example 5 does not define a preference. Conversely, if case satisfied q, then no weak decomposition should define a preference, but, according to Proposition 11, this is not true.
Then, such a property q should not exist. We conclude that an equivalence to relies on something more than some properties of t-conorms.
The following proposition generalizes the previous example to any t-conorm that may be used in weak decompositions.
Proposition 12. Let S be a t-conorm continuous in the first coordinate. S induces a weak decomposition rule if, and only if, for every with it holds true that, if , then .
Proof. To prove the direct implication, suppose that there are such that , and we will prove that there is an , which has at least two decompositions that induce fuzzy preferences.
To see that, given a pair , define a fuzzy binary relation R satisfying ; and if and also . Consider now the three fuzzy binary relations for all , if , and .
Now, we can assert that and are weak decompositions of R. Moreover, and are preferences because they are defined by means of a decomposition and it is immediate to check that they indeed satisfy . Therefore, S can not induce any decomposition rule.
Concerning the converse implication, we may notice that the unique property of the maximum used in the proof of Proposition 11 is just our hypothesis here. We could transcript the same proof after interchanging “From the equality we obtain that ” with “From the equality we obtain that ”. ☐
Remark 4. Notice that if S is strictly increasing in the first coordinate, S satisfies the hypothesis of the Proposition 12, because if , then . This fact is consistent with the combination of Propositions 9 and 10, which also guarantees the existence of the induced decomposition rule .
7. Conclusions
We are faced with variable forms of uncertainty and indeterminacy in many areas of life, which require reliable and effective treatment from the point of view of practice. All of this raises active control technical problems, within which the use of fuzzy controllers is now a natural possibility. Having in mind possible future research in order to cope with these problems, first of all it is necessary to state a solid theoretical background. In the present paper, we have intended to do so, around the notion of a fuzzy preference. This concept, defined as a triplet that reminds us of the usual weak preference, strict preference and indifference arising in the crisp setting, has been analyzed from the point of view of the existence of decompositions in which the fuzzy weak preference generates, in a way, the associated strict fuzzy preference as well as the fuzzy indifference. In the crisp setting, the decompositions are always unique, whereas this is no longer true in the fuzzy setting. Consequently, we have also analyzed questions related to the existence and uniqueness of decompositions of fuzzy preferences, as shown in the main sections of the present manuscript: Propositions 6–9 provide a novel characterization of the existence and uniqueness of strong and weak decompositions, whereas Proposition 12 characterizes the uniqueness of (weak) decomposition rules.
As already commented in Remark 1, in the present paper we have only used t-norms and t-conorms to define the decomposition of a fuzzy binary relation. However, in the proofs of some results achieved then, we did not use all of their properties. Therefore, thinking of future lines for research, we could also consider, and consequently define, a decomposition with respect to a more general category of operators. As we explained, the decision of using here only t-norms and t-conorms is due to the fact that they are the fuzzy generalizations of the classic intersection and union operators and, more importantly, because we wanted to be coherent with the pre-existing literature that analyzes, studies and uses decompositions in practice, paying special attention to the setting of Arrovian-like models in fuzzy Social Choice. Needless to say, in forthcoming works we could address the study of decompositions based upon other disparate operators.
We have been looking for a normative theoretical definition of a decomposition (at least for the case of t-norms and t-conorms). In this sense, we have compared our approach and the definitions we have launched with other ones encountered in the literature, showing that ours are more general. In our opinion, this is a relevant achievement at this stage: namely, with the definitions of a fuzzy decomposition that we have introduced, we provide the researcher with a generalized theoretical framework that systematically includes, as we have been discussing throughout the work, the (somewhat more restrictive) definitions that had already been introduced in this literature. At least, this applies, in our opinion, to decompositions associated with Arrovian-like models in the fuzzy setting.
Last but not least, in the introduction of the present article, we have exposed that, in Social Choice, the sets of suitable preferences used to be restricted by transitivity and connectedness properties. In future work, we plan to extend our study to the sets of preferences restricted by these properties instead of . The appendices contain a preliminary analysis of these sets where we expose a possible resolution of the problem by means of some figures. Based on our exploration, we hypothesize that when some connectedness condition is imposed, the possibility of the existence of decomposition rules increases.