Translating Values into Quality: How We Can Use Max Weber’s Ethic of Responsibility to Rethink Professional Ethics
Abstract
:1. Introduction
2. Values—A Core Problem of Professional Ethics
- (1)
- The discussion of ethics and professions was shaped by Talcott Parsons. In his article for the International Encyclopedia of Social Sciences, Parsons wrote that “a full-fledged profession must have some institutional means of making sure that such competence will be put to socially responsible uses” [20] (p. 535). Consequently, within academic textbooks, “altruism” has become a hallmark of professions [21]. However, already in the 1960s and 1970s there were different, influential, interpretations of professions, which saw them in the context of capitalist power structures [22], as an upward mobility project of bourgeois groups, or the “professional project” [23]. Viewed from such perspectives, altruism on the part of professions seems unlikely.
- (2)
- What we can observe is that professions are developing codes of ethics. This has shifted the discussion so that professional ethics revolve around codes of ethics. The development of a code of ethics may be taken as an expression of professionalization [24]. Many professions have developed codes of ethics, often oriented towards the Hippocratic Oath in medicine [25] and occasionally supported by ethical–philosophical considerations on the adequate criteria for such [3,26]. Abbott distilled characteristics of the use of professional codes of ethics, emphasizing that the code of ethics is a corporate phenomenon [27]. In a neo-Weberian approach, codes of ethics would represent a defensive tool to justify a form of market monopoly [11].
- (3)
- Years later, Abbott emphasized the role of values in professional practice [28], similar to Durkheim [18], but without the Durkheimian assumption that group norms and commitments emerge from professional work. From a philosophical point of view, professional practice could in principle be grounded in social values [29], seeing professions as “inherently ethical practices” [30] (p. 7). If we want to avoid referring to values, we could instead consider the professional sense of obligation in terms of virtue. I see in this context the sociological discussion about phronesis in professional practice [31,32,33]; Aristotle classically defined phronesis as practical wisdom or prudence, representing a kind of virtue. From a philosophical perspective, professionality as such could even be seen as a special—i.e., professional—virtue [34].
3. Weber, Freidson
3.1. Weber: An Ethic of Responsibility—In Terms of Objective Rationality
3.1.1. Weber’s Outline of the Ethic of Responsibility
We need to be clear that all ethically oriented action can be guided by either of two fundamentally different, irredeemably incompatible maxims: it can be guided by an ‘ethics of conviction’ or an ‘ethics of responsibility’. […] there is a profound abyss between acting in accordance with the maxim governing an ethics of conviction and acting in tune with an ethics of responsibility. In the former case this means, to put it in religious terms: ‘A Christian does what is right and leaves the outcome to God’, while in the latter you must answer for the (foreseeable) consequences of your actions.[1] (p. 83)
[…] I find it immeasurably moving when a mature human being—whether young or old in actual years is immaterial—who feels the responsibility he bears for the consequences of his own actions with his entire soul and who acts in harmony with his ethics of responsibility reaches the point where he says, “Here I stand, I can do no other”. That is authentically human and cannot fail to move us. For this is a situation that may befall any of us at some point, if we are not inwardly dead. In this sense an ethics of responsibility and an ethics of conviction are not absolute antitheses, but are mutually complementary, and only when taken together do they constitute the authentic human being who is capable of having a “vocation for politics.”
3.1.2. Starr’s Review of Weber’s Outline of the Ethic of Responsibility
These struggles [between values and between rationalities, in and between different spheres of life] are not susceptible to rational resolution precisely because what counts as rational is designated differently within each of the warring factions, and there is no apparent overarching rationality that can mediate between the intersecting values and spheres. Here we have the context of Weber’s ethic of responsibility. What stance is available to the ethically serious person in such a world?[45] (p. 424)
3.2. Freidson: Personal Professional Responsibility and the “Institutional Ethics” of Professions
3.2.1. Personal Professional Responsibility
3.2.2. Collegial, Work-Organizing Level
3.2.3. Corporate Level of the Profession, Institutional Level of Professionalism
4. Risk and Responsibility in Professional Work
4.1. Linking the Discourses of Risk and Responsibility
4.2. Professional Responsibility within the Professional–Client Model: Sharing Responsibility with the Profession
4.3. Professional Responsibility in Organizational Contexts: The Relational Nature of Responsibility
- New forms of organizational control: We find professionalism as a “disciplinary logic which describes ‘autonomous’ professional practice within a network of accountability and governs professional conduct at a distance” [77] (p. 280).
- Globalization of work relations: Last but not least, we see the rise of global professional firms, for instance in law, accounting, engineering, or architecture, with transnational professional standards and work regimes [81].
[…] the imbalance of power between the professional and these [dependent] stakeholders, who are located in the inner ring of the stakeholder map, places a higher moral expectation on professionals to honor their responsibility, both morally and legally, to these more vulnerable stakeholders.[82] (p. 84)
5. The Concept of Professional Responsibility
5.1. The Concept of Professional Responsibility—Providing Quality
- For the individual professional, the ability to refer to quality standards set by the profession means sharing responsibility for professional practice with the profession. The shared responsibility provided by the profession allows the individual professional to prudently assume greater risks in providing professional services (mandated risks) than they would likely be willing to assume in the absence of this professional framework of qualifications and standards.
- From this perspective, it becomes understandable why codes of professional ethics are a corporate matter for the professions, as both Freidson [48] and Abbott [27] have pointed out, rather than for individual professional practice. Given the implicit risks of professional practice, such codes of ethics serve to reduce the burden on members of the profession as well as to discipline them.
- In order to justify their professional practice, individuals may be required to improve their expertise and knowledge to meet the quality standards required by their professional bodies. This leads to a certain pressure for continuing education and orientation, which is exerted on the individual professional and which the profession helps to alleviate through conferences and continuing education programs (e.g., in architecture [87]).
- For the individual professional, the relational nature of responsibility comes to the fore. When professionals work in organizations (e.g., as doctors in a hospital, in an industrial enterprise, or even in a prison), these relationships are multiplied. As already described, this can lead to a hybrid form of professionalism [79], for example when a job requires management functions and skills. The reference to professional quality can also be used by the organization (to legitimize practices) and thus increase the accountability of the employed professional (“responsibilization” [17]).
5.2. What Can Be Considered Professional Altruism? Social Responsibility; Translating Values into Quality
5.3. Three Problems of Professional Ethics Revisited
6. Discussion
6.1. Does the Consideration of Responsibility Provide a Sufficient and New View of Professional Ethics?
- (i)
- Universal distribution: “nearly all professions have some kind of formal ethical code” (p. 857);
- (ii)
- Enforcement dependent on visibility: “formal prosecution under professional ethics rules is a function largely of the public visibility of the offense” (p. 859);
- (iii)
- Individualism: “professional ethics codes deal with individuals and individual behavior” (p. 860);
- (iv)
- Emphasis on colleague obligations: “obligations toward fellow professionals predominate, especially those that restrain competition for clients, such as pricing policies, rules against client stealing, and the like” (p. 862);
- (v)
- Correlation with intraprofessional status: “both belief in and compliance with formal ethics codes seem to be related positively to intraprofessional status” (p. 858).
- (1)
- The limited appeal of “progressive idealism” (p. 95). Brint shows that for many industries in which professionals work, we cannot expect them “to embrace ideas about reducing inequality and serving the underserved” (p. 98). However, the introduced Weberian interpretation of professional responsibility is based on risk sharing (taking into account potential conflicts of value) and not on “social idealism” in the way that Brint [10] (p. 99) understands the core of any responsibility. The professional is bound by the standards of the profession, and does not need to be socially motivated (although social motivation may be helpful to the work).
- (2)
- The significance of skill and expertise. Brint argues that skill, although dominant in professionalism, can have any combination with “social idealism” [10] (p. 99). Similarly, Koehn argues from a philosophical perspective that expertise is “inherently untrustworthy” as being unrelated to any “client’s good” [30] (pp. 21–22). From the perspective of responsibility-based professional ethics, however, the point is that because of the importance of their particular expertise, professionals have a relationship of responsibility to clients and society—and must be able to justify their work. The justification of expertise is all the more necessary, given repeated claims of a “crisis of expertise” [95]. We know from psychological research on expertise that the range of reliable expertise is generally much narrower than some experts claim or the public expects [96].
- (3)
- The decisive role of formal organizations. Brint argues that today organizations clearly play a more important role than individuals, and speaks of a “collective organizational worker” [10] (p. 100). Brint’s argument goes in the same direction as the multilevel solution described above: professionals and the profession share the risk. However, there are at least two reasons why, despite the advantages of organizations, there is still a need for individual professionals: First, there are not enough organizations—such as hospitals—to meet the demand for service. Second, from the perspective of responsibility, the use of individual experts—as a form of human capital [96]—has a distinct advantage compared to an organization: In case they err, single experts can be dismissed more easily than an organization. It is easier to replace a single expert (as a bundle of skills and knowledge) than a whole organization or a profession.
- (4)
- The “contested and unsettled nature of professional responsibilities in practice” [10] (p. 94). Brint’s argument is less an objection than a description of the relational nature of responsibility: Professional responsibility means an obligation to respond to the various demands of clients, society, and all other stakeholders [82]. A vivid example is provided by Bayles’ book on professional ethics, which detailed the various obligations of professions and professionals in different scenarios (e.g., serving an immoral client). The second edition took into account even more constellations [29], such as the obligations of employed professionals or obligations of clients to professions. Especially when it comes to translating values into quality, it is important to know the many—sometimes conflicting—values. A new version of professional ethics should be able to capture the “contested and unsettled nature of professional responsibilities in practice”.
6.2. A New Understanding of Weber’s Contribution to Work and Organization, or Just a New Functionalism?
Funding
Institutional Review Board Statement
Informed Consent Statement
Data Availability Statement
Acknowledgments
Conflicts of Interest
1 | An alternative would be to introduce the concept of responsibility as part of a neo-Weberian approach to the sociology of professions [11]. This would be possible because Weber’s initial introduction of the ethics of responsibility occurred within the context of questions on the value of freedom of science—and thus of science as a profession [12], a context that can be connected to reflections on professions as science-based occupations [13]. In earlier versions of this paper, I pursued this path, but it proved too complex to develop a theory of professions and to justify a non-standard application of Weber’s ethic of responsibility at the same time. It seems to me that using Freidson’s approach facilitates an easier connection with current strands of the sociology of professional groups [4,14]. |
2 | “Ethic” or “ethics”: In this paper, I will use the singular “ethic” for a form of morality that is distinct from other forms (ethic of responsibility vs. ethic of conviction, work ethic, Protestant ethic). The plural will be used for the expanded version of an “ethic” as a formulated theory (e.g., responsibility ethics). In directly quoted passages, the use of ethic/ethics matches the original source. Weber described the ethics of responsibility and conviction as two different “maxims”. For German listeners and readers of his time, it must have been clear that he was referring to Kant, who used the term to describe a “subjective principle of volition” (“subjektives Prinzip des Wollens” [42]). The distinction between “morality” as a set of norms and “ethics” as a theory of morality only emerged in Germany after Scheler [43]. |
3 | The phrase “Here I stand, I can do no other. God help me.” is attributed to Martin Luther, who in 1521 was called before Emperor Charles V to defend his religious teachings and writing. |
4 | Because of the moral relevance of discretion, some authors advocate the use of the concept of “phronesis” [31,33]. Phronesis, or practical wisdom, is what we need in non-standard, unclear cases, particularly at the fringes of a profession’s core work. However, phronesis does not seem to be particularly professional or, to use Kristjánsson’s words: “Phronesis, as an Aristotelian concept, is relevant to professional ethics, not to professionalism in a more general (non-moral) sense.” [32] (p. 307). Personal professional responsibility would then be no different from general moral behavior. |
References
- Weber, M. Politics as a vocation. In Max Weber: The Vocation Lectures; Owen, D., Strong, T.B., Eds.; Hackett: Indianapolis, IN, USA, 2004; pp. 32–94. [Google Scholar]
- Satkunanandan, S. Max Weber and the ethos of politics beyond calculation. Am. Political Sci. Rev. 2014, 108, 169–181. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Gert, B. Morality, moral theory, and applied and professional ethics. Prof. Ethics 1992, 1, 5–30. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Evetts, J. Professionalism: Value and ideology. Curr. Sociol. 2013, 61, 778–796. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Illich, I. Disabling professions. India Int. Cent. Q. 1978, 5, 23–32. [Google Scholar]
- Turner, S.P. The Politics of Expertise; Routledge: New York, NY, USA, 2014. [Google Scholar]
- Dzur, A.W. Democratic Professionalism; The Pennsylvania State University Press: University Park, TX, USA, 2008. [Google Scholar]
- Crystal, N.M. An Introduction to Professional Responsibility; Aspen Law & Business: New York, NY, USA, 1998. [Google Scholar]
- Mitchell, D.E.; Ream, R.K. (Eds.) Professional Responsibility: The Fundamental Issue in Education and Health Care Reform; Springer: Cham, Switzerland, 2015. [Google Scholar]
- Brint, S. Professional responsibility in an age of experts and large organizations. In Professional Responsibility; Mitchell, D.E., Ream, R.K., Eds.; Springer: Cham, Switzerland, 2015; pp. 89–107. [Google Scholar]
- Saks, M. Analyzing the professions: The case for the neo-Weberian approach. Comp. Sociol. 2010, 9, 887–915. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Weber, M. Der Sinn der “Wertfreiheit” der soziologischen und ökonomischen Wissenschaften. Logos Int. Z. Für Philos. Der Kult. 1917, 7, 40–88. [Google Scholar]
- Brante, T. Professions as science-based occupations. Prof. Prof. 2011, 1, 4–20. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Evetts, J. A new professionalism? Curr. Sociol. 2011, 59, 406–422. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Giddens, A. Risk and responsibility. Mod. Law Rev. 1999, 62, 1–10. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Renn, O. Risk Governance; Earthscan: London, UK, 2008. [Google Scholar]
- Le Bianic, T. Certified expertise and professional responsibility in organizations. Sociol. Rev. 2011, 59, 803–827. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Durkheim, É. Professional Ethics and Civic Morals; Forgotten Books: London, UK, 2012; Lectures from 1908. [Google Scholar]
- Tawney, R.H. The Aquisitive Society; Bell and Sons: London, UK, 1922. [Google Scholar]
- Parsons, T. Professions. In International Encyclopedia of the Social Sciences; Sills, D.L., Ed.; Macmillan: New Yok, NY, USA, 1968; Volume 12, pp. 536–547. [Google Scholar]
- Hodson, R.; Sullivan, T.A. The Social Organization of Work; Wadsworth: Belmont, CA, USA, 1990; p. 258. [Google Scholar]
- Johnson, T.J. Professions and Power; Macmillan: New York, NY, USA, 1972. [Google Scholar]
- Larson, M.S. The Rise of Professionalism; University of California Press: Berkeley, CA, USA, 1977. [Google Scholar]
- Wilensky, H.L. The professionalization of everyone? Am. J. Sociol. 1964, 70, 137–158. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Meskó, B.; Spiegel, B. A revised Hippocratic oath for the era of digital health. J. Med. Internet Res. 2022, 24, e39177. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Gould, C.C. New paradigms in professional ethics: Feminism, communitarianism, and democratic theory. Prof. Ethics 1992, 1, 143–154. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Abbott, A. Professional ethics. Am. J. Sociol. 1983, 88, 855–885. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Abbott, A. Processual Sociology; The University of Chicago Press: Chicago, IL, USA, 2016. [Google Scholar]
- Bayles, M.D. Professional Ethics, 2nd ed.; Wadsworth: Belmont, CA, USA, 1989. [Google Scholar]
- Koehn, D. The Ground of Professional Ethics; Routledge: New York, NY, USA, 1994. [Google Scholar]
- Flyvbjerg, B. Making Social Science Matter; Cambridge University Press: Cambridge, UK, 2001. [Google Scholar]
- Kristjánsson, K. Phronesis as an ideal in professional medical ethics. Theor. Med. Bioeth. 2015, 36, 299–320. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed]
- Champy, F. The sociology of prudential activities: From collective commitment to social innovations. Sociol. Probl. E Práticas 2018, 88, 79–94. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Kultgen, J. Ethics and Professionalism; University of Pennsylvania Press: Philadelphia, PA, USA, 1988. [Google Scholar]
- Elkin, K.J.; Spittal, M.J.; Elkin, D.J.; Studdert, D.M. Doctors disciplined for professional misconduct in Australia and New Zealand, 2000–2009. Med. J. Aust. 2011, 194, 452–456. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Elkin, K.; Spittal, M.J.; Elkin, D.; Studdert, D.M. Removal of doctors from practice for professional misconduct in Australia and New Zealand. BMJ Qual. Saf. 2012, 21, 1027–1033. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Glendon, M.A. A Nation under Lawyers: How the Crisis in the Legal Profession Is Transforming American Society; Harvard University Press: Boston, MA, USA, 1996. [Google Scholar]
- Green, B.A. Prosecutors and Professional Regulation. Geo. J. Leg. Ethics 2012, 25, 873. [Google Scholar]
- Guttmann, D. Ethics in Social Work: A Context of Caring; Routledge: Abingdon, UK, 2013. [Google Scholar]
- Heyneman, S.P. Education and Corruption. Int. J. Educ. Dev. 2004, 24, 637–648. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Muzio, D.; Faulconbridge, J.R.; Gabbioneta, C.C.; Greenwood, R. Bad Apples, Bad Barrels and Bad Cellars: A ‘Boundaries’ Perspective on Professional Misconduct; University Lancaster: Lancaster, UK, 2016; Available online: http://eprints.lancs.ac.uk/80776/1/Muzio_Faulconbridge_Gabbioneta_Greenwood_final_onlinbe_version.pdf (accessed on 11 September 2024).
- Kant, I. Grundlegung zu Einer Metaphysik der Sitten [Fundamental Principles of the Metaphysic of Morals]; Hartknoch: Riga, Estonia, 1785. [Google Scholar]
- Scheler, M. Der Formalismus in der Ethik und die Materiale Wertethik [Formalism in Ethics and Non-Formal Ethics of Values], 2nd ed.; Niemeyer: Tübingen, Germany, 1921; Original Work Published 1913–1916. [Google Scholar]
- Weber, M. The Theory of Social and Economic Organization; Parsons, T., Ed.; Oxford University Press: Oxford, UK, 1947; Free Press edition, 1984. [Google Scholar]
- Starr, B.E. The structure of Max Weber’s ethic of responsibility. J. Relig. Ethics 1999, 27, 407–434. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Kalberg, S. Max Weber’s types of rationality. Am. J. Sociol. 1980, 85, 1145–1179. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Levine, D. Rationality and freedom: Weber and beyond. Sociol. Inq. 1981, 51, 5–25. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Freidson, E. Profession of Medicine: A Study of the Sociology of Applied Knowledge; The University of Chicago Press: Chicago, IL, USA, 1988; original work published 1970, Harper & Row. [Google Scholar]
- Carr-Saunders, A.M.; Wilson, P.A. The Professions; Clarendon Press: Oxford, UK, 1933. [Google Scholar]
- Freidson, E. Professionalism: The Third Logic; Polity Press: Cambridge, UK, 2001. [Google Scholar]
- Becker, H.S.; Geer, B.; Hughes, E.C.; Strauss, A.L. Boys in White: Student Culture in Medical School; The University of Chicago Press: Chicago, IL, USA, 1961. [Google Scholar]
- Freidson, E. Professional Powers: A Study of the Institutionalization of Formal Knowledge; The University of Chicago Press: Chicago, IL, USA, 1986. [Google Scholar]
- Brint, S. Saving the “soul of professionalism”: Freidson’s institutional ethics and the defense of professional autonomy. Knowl. Work Soc. 2006, 4, 101–129. [Google Scholar]
- von Neumann, J.; Morgenstern, O. Theory of Games and Economic Behavior; Princeton University Press: Princeton, NJ, USA, 1944. [Google Scholar]
- Beck, U. Risk Society; Sage: London, UK, 1992. [Google Scholar]
- Jonas, H. The Imperative of Responsibility; The University of Chicago Press: Chicago, IL, USA, 1984. [Google Scholar]
- Strydom, P. The challenge of responsibility for sociology. Curr. Sociol. 1999, 47, 65–82. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Sena, B. The sociological link between risk and responsibility. Int. Soc. Sci. J. 2014, 65, 79–91. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Luhmann, N. Risk: A Sociological Theory; Aldine de Gruyter: Hawthorne, CA, USA, 1993. [Google Scholar]
- Klinke, A.; Renn, O. The coming of age of risk governance. Risk Anal. 2021, 41, 544–557. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed]
- Commonwealth of Australia. National Strategy for Disaster Resilience. 2011. Available online: https://www.homeaffairs.gov.au/emergency/files/national-strategy-disaster-resilience.pdf (accessed on 11 September 2024).
- Lucas, J.R. Responsibility; Clarendon Press: Oxford, UK, 1995. [Google Scholar]
- Lenk, H. Responsibility in science: The philosophical view. In The Responsibility of Science; Mieg, H.A., Ed.; Springer: Cham, Switzerland, 2022; pp. 11–50. [Google Scholar]
- Hughes, E.C. Professions. In The Professions in America; Lynn, K.S., Ed.; Houghton Mifflin: Boston, MA, USA, 1965; pp. 1–14. [Google Scholar]
- Luhmann, N. Funktionen und Folgen Formaler Organisation [Functions and Consequences of Formal Organization]; Duncker & Humblot: Berlin, Germany, 1964; pp. 172–190, (translated). [Google Scholar]
- Lipsky, M. Street-Level Bureaucracy; Russell Sage: New York, NY, USA, 1980. [Google Scholar]
- Molander, A. Discretion in the Welfare State; Routledge: Abingdon, VA, UK, 2016. [Google Scholar]
- Molander, A.; Grimen, H. Understanding professional discretion. In Sociology of Professions: Continental and Anglo-Saxon Traditions; Evetts, J.J., Svensson, L.G., Eds.; Daidalos: Gothenburg, Sweden, 2010; pp. 167–187. [Google Scholar]
- Galligan, D.J. Discretionary Powers; Clarendon Press: Oxford, UK, 1990. [Google Scholar]
- Rueschemeyer, D. Power and the Division of Labour; Polity Press: Cambridge, UK, 1986. [Google Scholar]
- Abbott, A. The System of Professions; The University of Chicago Press: Chicago, IL, USA, 1988. [Google Scholar]
- Mieg, H.A.; Evetts, J. Professionalism, science, and expert roles. In The Cambridge Handbook of Expertise and Expert Performance, 2nd ed.; Ericsson, K.A., Hoffman, R.R., Kozbelt, A., Williams, A.M., Eds.; Cambridge University Press: Cambridge, UK, 2018; pp. 127–148. [Google Scholar]
- Baer, W.C. Expertise and professional standards. Work Occup. 1987, 13, 532–552. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Harvey, N.; Fischer, I. Taking advice: Accepting help, improving judgment, and sharing responsibility. Organ. Behav. Hum. Decis. Process. 1997, 70, 117–133. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- El Zein, M.; Bahrami, B.; Hertwig, R. Shared responsibility in collective decisions. Nat. Hum. Behav. 2019, 3, 554–559. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Mieg, H.A. Social reflection, performed role-conformant and role-discrepant responsibility, and the unity of responsibility: A social psychological perspective. Soz. Syst. 2015, 19, 259–281. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Fournier, V. The appeal to “professionalism” as a disciplinary mechanism. Sociol. Rev. 1999, 47, 280–307. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Treviño, L.K.; Weaver, G.R.; Gibson, D.G.; Toffler, B.L. Managing ethics and legal compliance. Calif. Manag. Rev. 1999, 41, 131–151. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Noordegraaf, M. From “pure” to “hybrid” professionalism. Adm. Soc. 2007, 39, 761–785. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Kuhlmann, E.; Saks, M. (Eds.) Rethinking Professional Governance: International Directions in Healthcare; Policy Press: Bristol, UK, 2008. [Google Scholar]
- Faulconbridge, J.R.; Muzio, D. Professions in a globalizing world. Int. Sociol. 2011, 27, 136–152. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Montgomery, K. How institutional contexts shape professional responsibility. In Professional Responsibility; Mitchell, D.E., Ream, R.K., Eds.; Springer: Cham, Switzerland, 2015; pp. 75–88. [Google Scholar]
- Bovens, M. Analysing and assessing accountability. Eur. Law J. 2007, 13, 447–468. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Fox, J.A. Social accountability: What does the evidence really say? World Dev. 2005, 72, 346–361. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Pellizzoni, L. Responsibility and environmental governance. Environ. Politics 2004, 13, 541–565. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Kuye, J.O.; Mafunisa, J.M. Responsibility, accountability and ethics. J. Public Adm. 2003, 38, 421–437. [Google Scholar]
- Nicol, D.; Pilling, S. (Eds.) Architectural Education and the Profession; Spon Press: Abingdon, UK, 2000. [Google Scholar]
- Saks, M. Professions and the Public Interest: Medical Power, Altruism, and Alternative Medicine; Routledge: Abingdon, UK, 1995. [Google Scholar]
- Rhode, D.L. Pro Bono in Principle and in Practice; Stanford University Press: Redwood City, CA, USA, 2005. [Google Scholar]
- Duff, A. Corporate social responsibility reporting in professional accounting firms. Br. Account. Rev. 2016, 48, 74–86. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Vanhaecht, K.; De Ridder, D.; Seys, D.; Brouwers, J.; Claessens, F.; Van Wilder, A.; Panella, M.; Batalden, P.; Lachman, P. The history of quality. Eur. Urol. Focus 2021, 7, 937–939. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed]
- Oevermann, H.; Mieg, H.A. Urban development planning and world cultural heritage: Two perspectives of planning practice dealing with industrial heritage. Plan. Pract. Res. (PPR) 2021, 36, 430–441. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- French, P.A. Collective and Corporate Responsibility; Columbia University Press: New York, NY, USA, 1984. [Google Scholar]
- Knapp, S.; Handelsman, M.M.; Gottlieb, M.C.; VandeCreek, L.D. The dark side of professional ethics. Prof. Psychol. Res. Pract. 2013, 44, 371. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Eyal, G. The Crisis of Expertise; John Wiley & Sons: Hoboken, NJ, USA, 2019. [Google Scholar]
- Mieg, H.A. The Social Psychology of Expertise; Lawrence Erlbaum: Mahwah, NJ, USA, 2001. [Google Scholar]
- Goode, W.J. Community within a community: The professions. Am. Sociol. Rev. 1957, 22, 194–200. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Brante, T. Sociological approaches to the professions. Acta Sociol. 1988, 31, 119–142. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Saks, M. Defining a profession. Prof. Prof. 2012, 2, 1–10. [Google Scholar]
- Adams, T.L. Self-regulating professions: Past, present, future. J. Prof. Organ. 2017, 4, 70–87. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Trebilcock, M.J. Paradoxes of Professional Regulation: In Search of Regulatory Principles; University of Toronto Press: Toronto, ON, Canada, 2022. [Google Scholar]
- Mieg, H.A. Two factors of expertise? Excellence and professionalism of environmental experts. High Abil. Stud. 2009, 20, 91–115. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
Disclaimer/Publisher’s Note: The statements, opinions and data contained in all publications are solely those of the individual author(s) and contributor(s) and not of MDPI and/or the editor(s). MDPI and/or the editor(s) disclaim responsibility for any injury to people or property resulting from any ideas, methods, instructions or products referred to in the content. |
© 2024 by the author. Licensee MDPI, Basel, Switzerland. This article is an open access article distributed under the terms and conditions of the Creative Commons Attribution (CC BY) license (https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/).
Share and Cite
Mieg, H.A. Translating Values into Quality: How We Can Use Max Weber’s Ethic of Responsibility to Rethink Professional Ethics. Societies 2024, 14, 183. https://doi.org/10.3390/soc14090183
Mieg HA. Translating Values into Quality: How We Can Use Max Weber’s Ethic of Responsibility to Rethink Professional Ethics. Societies. 2024; 14(9):183. https://doi.org/10.3390/soc14090183
Chicago/Turabian StyleMieg, Harald A. 2024. "Translating Values into Quality: How We Can Use Max Weber’s Ethic of Responsibility to Rethink Professional Ethics" Societies 14, no. 9: 183. https://doi.org/10.3390/soc14090183
APA StyleMieg, H. A. (2024). Translating Values into Quality: How We Can Use Max Weber’s Ethic of Responsibility to Rethink Professional Ethics. Societies, 14(9), 183. https://doi.org/10.3390/soc14090183