1. Introduction
In several Western legal systems, there has been an increasing amount of attention paid to the future child. Nowadays, we know more about risk factors linked to the child’s existence that may cause physical or psychosocial harm, such as parents who lack the ability to raise a child, or severe genetic conditions. Since these types of risks can only be prevented before the child is conceived, the only way to prevent harm is to take the interests of the child into account before the child’s conception. The interests of the future child constitute a normative guideline in the regulation on procreation issues. For example, restrictions on the use of assisted reproductive technologies (ARTs) and access to fertility treatments, or the criteria for embryo selection, are justified with an appeal to the future child’s interests. What is important is that this regulation can result in the prevention of the future child’s existence. This prevention is justified by the assumption that it is in the future child’s interest not to be born at all. Some even claim that some children have a
right not to be born [
1]
1.
The appeal to the future child’s interests as a justification for legal measures has received much criticism, in particular in the bioethical debate
2. The most important point of critique, based on Parfit’s non-identity problem ([
6], p. 351), is that the appeal to the best interests of the future child cannot serve as a justification; since the children in the cases mentioned in this article will most likely have a life worth living, it cannot be assumed that they would be harmed by being brought into existence and that it therefore would be better for the child not to be born at all. Moreover, it has been argued that non-existent entities are not able to have interests [
7] and that the anticipation of the future child by law by means of the so-called welfare principle is unjust, disingenuous and incoherent [
8,
9].
Despite this criticism, it is a fact that the future child gains increasing attention in law and that the appeal to its interests serves to justify regulation on procreation. For this reason, it is important to look further than the wrongful life-debate and entertain a legal-theoretical perspective on this issue. After all, beside the bioethical critiques, the rise of the future child in law also creates the legal question of the extent to which the law can address and represent this non-existing entity. However, up to now this question has been unaddressed.
This paper argues that the current legal vocabulary is unequipped in representing the future child. The future child is presented as a subject of interests and therefore a subject. However, it does not fit in the concept of law’s subject: the legal person. The argument of this paper focuses on those cases in which the child’s existence is prevented by an appeal to the future child’s interests. Although this might only happen in a small number of cases, it is precisely this specific situation that has that result in two representation problems. First of all, legal vocabulary lacks the concepts to represent a non-existing entity with an interest in non-existence. Second, a representation paradox is created since the future child is treated as a subject and a non-subject at the same time.
In order to show that legal vocabulary lacks the proper concepts to represent the future child, I first elaborate several examples in which an appeal to the future child’s interests is made in law (
Section 2), in order to illustrate the role the future child has gained in law as a subject of interests. After this, I explore the extent to which the concept of legal personhood can be applied to the future child. I will do so by systematically analyzing three perspectives on legal personhood: the naturalistic approach (
Section 3), the constructivist approach (
Section 4) and finally legal personhood by anticipation (
Section 5). The discussion of these perspectives will lead to the conclusion in the final section that law cannot represent the future child in its traditional legal vocabulary and that the current appearance of the future child in law is paradoxical, for it is treated as a subject and a non-subject at the same time.
2. The Interests of the Future Child in Law
As a result of developments in procreation technology, we have gained more control over procreation itself. ARTs and contraception, for example, make it possible to influence who may procreate, which child will come into existence, and under which circumstances. Obviously, controlling birth and the conception of new life is a highly sensitive matter and the development of reproductive technology has led to morally sensitive questions: Should everyone have access to fertility treatment? Under which conditions is embryo selection (PGD) acceptable? Should some people be prevented from having children at all costs? These questions are addressed within regulation on procreation and can result in restrictions on the use of ARTs and access to fertility treatment. In several West European legal systems, such restrictions are usually justified by an appeal to the interests of the future child.
For example, in the ECHR case S.H.
et al. v. Austria, the Court was confronted with the question of whether a ban on heterologous use of fertilization techniques
3 was a violation of Article 8 of the Convention
4. The right to private life ex Article 8 also covers several aspects of procreative autonomy: According to the Court, it includes the right to “respect [...] the decision to become a parent or not”
5 and the right of a couple “to make use of medically assisted procreation techniques” for the purpose of conceiving a child
6. The prohibition of heterologous use of fertilization techniques constituted a breach of this right. The Austrian government claimed that the ban was justified in order to protect several interests, such as the interests of the female donors, but also the interests of the future child. With the help of the current legislation in Austria (including the prohibition on heterologous techniques), the government aimed at safeguarding the future child’s wellbeing
7 and its interest in knowing its (genetic) descent
8.
Additionally, Italian legislation on fertility treatments illustrates that the interests of the future child provide a ground for not only banning several techniques, but also regulating access to fertility treatments. In a Review of the subject conducted by the Italian Parliamentary Commission for Social Affairs, it was claimed that the ban on heterologous techniques was necessary to prevent a violation of the psycho-social welfare of the child ([
10], p. 85). Similarly, the exclusion of homosexual couples and single women from fertility treatment was justified in order to avoid “psycho-social damage to the child, which can result from parenting models which are not consolidated” ([
10], p. 88).
Another example of the appeal to the future child’s interest can be found in UK law, in which “the welfare of the child” is explicitly mentioned in the Human Fertilisation and Embryology Act. Section 13(5) holds that “[a] woman shall not be provided with treatment […] unless account has been taken of the welfare of any child who may be born as a result of the treatment […].”
9 Initially, the legislator did not intend this welfare principle to be an eligibility requirement; the principle merely placed a responsibility upon the fertility clinics ([
11], p. 4). However, in 2005, the Human Fertilisation and Embryology Authority (HFEA) pointed out that there was considerable uncertainty about the interpretation of this principle, since the legislation provided no guidance on this point. After a survey, the HFEA concluded that the welfare of the child principle should be understood as the responsibility of the clinics to collect information from patients on possible risk factors to the child’s wellbeing. Although the principle of treatment implies that patients seeking treatment should not be easily refused, the HFEA Code of Practice states that a treatment should be refused if the fertility centre involved concludes that the resulting child
10 “is likely to be at risk of significant harm or neglect” or if they “cannot obtain enough information to conclude that there is no significant risk”([
12], Section 8, 15)
11.
The interests of the future child are also a normative guideline in Dutch regulation on access to fertility treatments and embryo selection (PGD). The medical, professional guidelines for moral contraindications for fertility treatments
12 provide physicians with standards of conduct for excluding patients from fertility treatment based on non-medical, but moral reasons. Interestingly, the only moral reason mentioned in the protocol is “the wellbeing of the future child”. If there is a reasonable expectation that the quality of the resulting child’s life will not meet the standard of reasonable wellbeing, proceeding with the fertility treatment and enabling the child to come into existence would be a violation of that future child’s interests. This could be used as a justification for terminating the fertility treatment
13. With regard to pre-implantation genetic diagnosis (PGD)
14, the Dutch Secretary of State of Public Health stated that the treatment is only acceptable if it benefits the future child that will be born as a result of the procedure
15. If the future child runs an increased risk of a serious disease, PGD is in the future child’s interests, for it (as the Secretary of State claimed) provides the possibility to prevent the child from suffering from a life affecting disease
16. For the same reason, selection on other grounds, such as gender or HLA-type, is not allowed, unless the future child itself runs the risk of a (gender-linked) condition. Only then would the application of the technique (also) serve the interests of the future child, and not only the interests of the parents or an ill sibling
17.
Furthermore, a recurring question in the Dutch public and political debate is whether the interest of the future child can also require forced contraception. In 2010, a member of Parliament suggested that in case of “irresponsible parenthood”,
i.e., in cases of extreme child abuse or neglect, the State should have the power to enforce contraception on parents to prevent another child being born to such parents. The MP argues that the child would have no interest in growing up with such parents, since this would constitute too much of a risk that this future child would also become a victim of neglect, abuse or poor upbringing
18. Although this proposal never resulted in legislation, there is still an ongoing public debate concerning the question of whether the government should prevent children from being born in order to protect their interests and wellbeing [
13,
14,
15,
16,
17].
In sum, these examples show that, in several West European legal systems, the assumed interests of the future child are used as an important justification for restrictions on the use of procreation techniques and access to fertility treatment. In some cases, as in the Dutch medical professional guidelines, it is the only justification. The appeal to the future child’s interests has several implications, however. First, when the interests of the future or resulting child are taken into account, the “child” is not conceived. Therefore, the interests are attributed to an entity that does not even exist, making this “future” child the subject of interests. Additionally, these interests of the future child apparently justify legal measures that prevents the child’s conception: If a fertility treatment is not performed, the child in question will never be born at all, just like it will never come into existence if it is deselected in the PGD process or its conception is prevented through forced contraception. Of course, the prevention of the child’s conception will only occur in a small number of cases, but what is important is that, if the child’s existence is prevented, this is justified by the appeal to its own interests. In other words, in these specific cases, the subject of interests is not only non-existent, but, as a direct result of the attribution of the same interests, the subject will never come into existence at all. Since it is assumed that the regulation is properly justified because it serves the future child’s interests, the regulation attributes to the child an interest in its own non-existence. After all, the regulation implies that, rather than being born into a life with the risk of being harmed, it is in the interest of the future child not to exist at all.
This article focuses specifically on those cases in which the future child’s existence is prevented because of its assumed interest in non-existence. The assumption of this interest in non-existence is quite controversial. Many philosophers have discussed whether and when an interest in non-existence can be assumed in the wrongful life debate ([
2,
3,
4]; [
5], p. 9; [
18], p. 17; [
19,
20]). The most important point of criticism in this debate is that an individual can only be harmed by being brought into existence—and consequently have an interest in non-existence—if he or she has “a life not worth living”. That is, if the quality of life is so low that non-existence would be preferable ([
5], p. 16). The problem is that, in most of the cases described above in which an interest in non-existence is assumed, it is not evident that the future child would indeed have a life not worth living, since its quality of life would not be so poor that non-existence would be preferable ([
3], p. 97); [
21], p. 75). This means that these children would not (necessarily) be better off if they are never born at all, and thus there would be no solid justification for the prevention of their existence.
Because of the increasing appeal to the future child’s interests in law, despite the criticism, it is pivotal to look beyond the wrongful life debate and explore the extent to which law is capable of representing this unique entity. Since the future child is presented as a subject, namely, the subject of interests, the question rises whether it can be presented in law with the help of the concept of the law’s subject: the legal person. The legal person is the actor in law and the subject of legal rights and duties
19. It is a complex concept, since most legal systems have no consolidated “law of the person”,
i.e., a unified set of rules concerning legal personhood and which defines the legal person. Instead, in the words of Naffine, law is inconsistent in its definition of the legal person ([
22], p. 176). Different areas of law have different perspectives on legal personhood and attribute different features to it ([
23], p. 371). Still, some main perspectives on legal personhood can be distinguished, so the question is whether the future child fits in any of these perspectives.
In the following sections, I elaborate on three perspectives on legal personhood which are dominant in the legal doctrine of several West European legal systems
20. First, it describes several naturalistic approaches, in which the legal person is understood as a reflection of the human being of daily life, and shows that the future child as a non-existent entity does not fit in any of these approaches. Second, it moves on to a constructivist approach in which the legal person is seen as a legal-technical construct that can be applied to almost anything. However, even if the legal person was merely an artificial construct, it still cannot conceive the unique qualities of the future child as it does not address the connection between the future child and the actual child it may become. Third, a perspective on legal personhood in which this connection is addressed is explored, namely, legal personhood by anticipation. It will be argued that the future child also does not fit in this approach, since its existence is prevented, and that there is therefore no entity to anticipate.
4. Legal Personality as a Construct
In constructivist approaches, the legal person is not defined as a reflection of the human being of daily life, but as a legal construct, which, according to some, can be anything.
44 It denies any connection between the legal person and the human being of flesh and blood. Kelsen, one of the most important proponents of this approach, stresses that a human being is a biological-psychological entity and not a legal concept. The human being in its entirety, with all its physical-biological and mental aspects, is not relevant for the law; only those actions that are addressed by law are important ([
30], pp. 52–53). In other words, biological, rational or metaphysical characteristics, as long as they are not addressed by law, are not relevant for the legal person in this perspective and thus do not provide themselves a ground for legal respect or legal protection. Instead of reflecting daily life, law “translates” events of this reality into its own language; therefore, it has its own perception of the physical reality or it “constructs” its own, legal reality.
This constructivist perspective, in which law is not merely a reflection of the physical reality, is also visible with regard to some aspects of legal personhood. One example is the temporal boundaries of the legal person. As mentioned earlier, the beginning and end of legal personhood are based on the biological birth and death of the human being. Notably, these boundaries are not always absolute. Law can “pretend” that the legal person begins or ends at an earlier moment by employing the nasciturus fiction or the concept of brain death. These constructs expose (at least partly) the constructivist nature of the legal person: Law is not strictly tied to the real human being in its representation, but it makes its own construction what this entity is in law.
What is important is that, in this approach, legal personhood is not attributed because the entity of the physical reality possesses inherent features, such as rationality or human dignity. According to Kelsen, a legal person is the allocation point of rights and duties or even “is” the bundle of rights and duties ([
30], p. 52). It is an artefact created by law. Instead of inherent features, the attribution of legal personhood depends on a legal construction,
i.e., it is a consequence of a legislative decision. In the words of Lawson: “All that is necessary for the existence of the person is that the lawmaker […] should decide to treat it as a subject of rights or other legal relations” ([
31], p. 915). The most common examples of this are the corporation and the State. These entities have legal personhood not because they meet certain metaphysical requirements, but because the law attributes it to them.
45 Since the attribution of legal personhood does not depend on inherent traits, it implies that the legal person has no specific characteristics ([
22], pp. 35–36; [
24], p. 374; [
32], p. 351). Tur points out that this conception of legal personhood is “wholly formal”; the legal person is “an empty slot that can be filled by anything that can have rights or duties” ([
26], p. 121). It all depends on what the law defines as a legal person: “If legal personhood is the legal capacity to bear rights and duties, then it is itself an artificial creation of the law, and anything or anyone can be a legal person. It all depends on the particular, concrete rules of particular legal systems”([
26], p. 121).
The constructivist approach towards legal personhood seems to offer opportunities to conceive the future child as a legal person. In this interpretation, the legal person is not connected to an entity of the physical world and has no inherent features; for this reason, anything can be a legal person ([
26], p. 121; [
33])—even a non-existent entity. What makes the legal person is the allocation of legal rights and duties; from a purely legal-technical view, the future child could be the subject of rights. Gray points out that, from a legal perspective,
technically, there is no difficulty in attributing rights to an unborn child. A newborn is equally incapable of exercising its rights; it can only exercise its rights through, for example, a legal guardian. Since there is not much difference between the child just before birth and just after birth, “[i]t is just as easy to attribute the will of a guardian, tutor or curator to the one as to the other”([
25], p. 38). In a similar way, this construction could be applied to the future child; technically, the future child could be the allocation point of rights (instead of interests), such as a “right not to be born”; by doing so, it would be a legal person. Of course, the attribution of rights to an unborn or future child causes other problems, like conflicts with the rights of the mother in the case of abortion or the impossibility of conducting stem cell research involving the destruction of embryos. However, the question of whether the future child
should have legal personhood is of a political nature; from a legal perspective (according to the constructivist approach), even a non-existent entity could fill the empty slot.
The emptiness of the constructivist legal person is sometimes considered an important benefit of the constructivist approach. Grear, for example, considers this plasticity a necessary benefit, since, in her opinion, it is most responsive towards the complexity of society and the creation of hybrid subjects and therefore indispensable ([
33], pp. 2, 23). New entities, such as trees, animals, future generations, artificial intelligence, unborn and future children, that do not fit in the naturalistic perspective of the legal person can be understood as a legal person in a constructivist perspective; that way, they could gain more legal protection and their interests could be protected better
46. A constructivist approach could be adopted in order to evade the birth requirement: Following this line of argumentation, it would not be necessary for the future child to actually be born in order to become a legal person, but it would be a legal person because law attributes legal personhood to it. The reason why legal personhood would be attributed is to offer the future child legal protection; that way, the interests of the future child would be better protected. Instead of interests, it would have rights, such as “the right not to be born”.
However, applying the constructivist approach is misleading; speaking of attributing legal personhood to the future child in the same way as attributing legal personhood to animals, trees, or entities with artificial intelligence suggests that the future child has interests of its own that require legal protection, just like, for example, animals have their own set of interests. This approach splits the future child from the actual child, as if both entities have their own set of interests. The future child, to the contrary, is not an independent entity that needs protection; instead, it is the allocation point of interests that transgress the temporal boundaries of the actual child’s existence; as an allocation point, it becomes the subject of interests. The future child is a construct, a tool, to be able to anticipate those interests in the present. The aim of this construct is to protect the actual child, once it is born, from the risk of harm. In other words, it is the actual child that needs protection, not the future child. This point is illustrated by the chosen formulation of written regulation. For instance, Section 13(5) of the HFEA, which speaks of the “child who may be born as a result of the treatment”. Moreover, the Dutch medical professional guidelines state that the “wellbeing of the future child” is determined by the ”psychosocial circumstances the child is born into”, implying it is concerned with harm that the actual, born child might suffer. Therefore, it is the risk of harm the actual child runs that constitutes the interests of the future child, as these interests are an anticipation of the risk. The interests of the future child are derived from the actual child, and this creates an inextricable link between the future child and the actual child; as a result, they cannot be seen as separate entities. The future child can still be understood as a subject of interests, but these interests are based on the interests the actual child could have.
The constructivist approach is capable of attributing legal personhood to a non-existent entity such as the future child. However, adopting this approach to “protect the interests of the future child” wrongfully suggests that the future child has interests of its own, which therefore does not address the essential connection between the future child and the actual child. These two entities are inextricably linked, for the future child is only constructed to protect the interests of the actual child, or at least those interests of the actual child that transgress the temporal boundaries of the child’s existence, i.e., the interest in preventing preconceptual harm to the actual child. In other words, the future child as a concept is created to anticipate the actual child. Perhaps there might be a legal construction that is able to address this link properly, but it needs further investigation to understand how this construction is constructed and whether this construction requires the attribution of legal personhood in order to articulate the characteristics and nature of this entity. For now, the current constructive approach is not able to properly address the future child because it is not an independent entity. For this reason, it would be more logical to, instead of constructing legal personhood, explore the possible expansion of the legal protection of interests that corresponds with legal personhood. The question then is not which approach to legal personhood can include the future child as a legal person, but whether the legal personhood of the actual child can be extended to the moment before its conception and affect the future child. The following section therefore explores whether the future child can be seen as a legal person if legal personhood is constructed upon the idea of anticipation.
5. Legal Personality as Anticipation
Several areas of the law show an anticipatory form of protection of entities that may exist in the future with respect to the legal personhood it one day will have. One example already given is the Dutch regulation on techniques such as human cloning and germ line cell therapy. These techniques are banned because of the possible violation of human dignity (although it was not explicated whose human dignity was at stake). Another example is the case Vo
v. France, in which the European Court of Human Rights was confronted with the question of whether an embryo falls within the scope of Article 2 of the Convention (and should therefore get legal protection in case of involuntary abortion). The Court did not answer that question, but did claim that “the potentiality of that being and its capacity to become a person […] require protection in the name of human dignity, without making it a ‘person’ with the ‘right to life’ for the purposes of Article 2”
47. Karnein proposes a theory on the representation of future persons in law based a similar idea: Potential, future persons must be treated “in anticipation of the respect that is due to the actual persons” ([
34], p. 33)
48. Karnein points out that stages previous to the attribution of legal personhood, in this case, the stages before birth, matter ([
34], p. 28). After all, events that occur during these stages can affect the actual person. Therefore, once a person exists or is born, obligations to the entity of a previous stage (such as the embryo) arise retrospectively, e.g., not to cause prenatal harm. Since these obligations towards the embryo will exist in the future, we should anticipate them now:
“Our obligations to embryos arise retrospectively (once they have become persons). They are applied in a forward-looking manner only via speculation (as to an embryo’s future) and as a matter of caution so that we avoid violating our (retrospective) obligations”.
The anticipation of these future obligations does not imply that the “not yet” person is to be treated equally as the person it will become; such an approach would, for example, imply that it is unacceptable to destroy embryos or abort a pregnancy
49. However, this theory does explain how interests can transgress the temporal boundaries of the entity’s existence and therefore provides a reason to anticipate the interests the actual child has once it is born.
Karnein limits her research to the status of the embryo and does not include the unconceived, future child. Still, the claim that “previous stages matter” is not necessarily limited to the embryo. After all, harmful events not only occur between conception and birth, but they can also happen prior to conception, which is the stage of the future child. For example, conceiving a new person by creating a human clone or a human-animal hybrid could also be understood as a violation of respect for the person it will become. Similarly, once the child is conceived, certain facts become unchangeable: for instance, mutations in the genetic blueprint or the biological parents. These facts can also constitute physical or psychosocial harm to the later person. This harm can only be prevented by anticipating the person that one day may exist when it is still a non-existent, future child. In sum, anticipating the future person (in order to prevent all sorts of harm) may also be required in the stage of the future child. Consequently, legal protection based upon anticipating later obligations (arisen in retrospect) is not necessary limited to the embryo, but may also apply to the future child. Therefore, Karnein’s theory is not only helpful for understanding not only the attribution of interests to unborn children, but also the non-existent future children.
Buchanan
et al. wondered whether the acknowledgement of prenatal and preconceptual harm (like in a wrongful life law suit) to an existing child implies that we have duties to a non-existent entity or whether this non-existent entity has interests or rights ([
2], p. 236). In their opinion, the wrongful life claim (and the corresponding assumption that the child is better off if it does not exist at all) is based on the violation of the right not to be born into a life not worth living. The assumption of this right and its violation constitute the core of a wrongful life law suit. However, according to Buchanan
et al. this right comes into existence when the child is born (and thus the legal subject exists). The creation of the right and its violation happen at the same time, namely, the moment the child is born; for this reason, there is no need to attribute interests to the child before it is born: “[I]t is not necessary to attribute to beings that do not yet exist rights not to be brought into existence at some future time with a life not worth living. If the child never is brought into existence, there never is a being with the right that would have been violated had it been brought into existence with a life not worth living” ([
2], p. 236). In this line of reasoning, it is indeed not necessary to attribute rights or interests to the future child in order to be able to justify a wrongful life claim. Importantly though, the wrongful life claim works retrospectively; once the child is born and harmed by being born, the claim in the law suit serves to compensate for its harms. The legal measures that are discussed in this article are proactive: Before the child is born, harm is prevented by preventing the child’s existence. If there are no interests because there is no existing subject, then there is no justification for the legal measures
50. In other words, if the justification for the prevention of existence is based on the interests of the future child, then that implies that interests are attributed to a non-existent, preconceptual entity. Therefore, the question remains how law can represent an non-existing entity as the subject of interests.
Karnein’s theory offers an explanation and justification for anticipating the interests of future entities and therefore explains how these future entities can be represented in law. This is not only important for the way in which law deals with future and unborn children, but also future generations. Nevertheless, the future child differs from the other two entities in a fundamental way. Karnein distinguishes between the embryo that is aborted, destroyed or used for research and the embryo that is carried to term, that is the unborn child ([
34], p. 34). Only the latter will grow into a person (or, more specifically, there is a clear intention of the parents to let this entity grow into a person. Medical complications could of course still alter the actual result). Since the latter embryo will become a person with certain rights and interests, society has an obligation to anticipate its interests. The same goes for future generations: Although we do not know
which individuals will be part of future generations, the future generation
as an entity itself will come into existence, unless the whole human race becomes extinct ([
35], p. 730). Unlike the unborn child and the future generations that come into existence, the future child’s existence is prevented. Since the future child in this case will not come into existence, there will never be a person to anticipate. No individual will ever exist in order to induce the application of retrospective respect for its unborn predecessors, including the future child. Accordingly, Karnein’s approach, in which legal protection of interests is based on anticipation of an actual person, does not offer a solution to the case of the future child.
6. Conclusion: The Problems of Representation
As the previous sections have shown, the future child does not fit in any of the three current perspectives on legal personhood. This is caused by the unique qualities of the future child. Since it does not exist, it does not fit in the naturalistic perspectives on legal personhood. The constructivist approach seems promising, but it overlooks the fact that the future child has no interests of its own, but is created to anticipate the interests of the actual child. Nevertheless, the future child can also not be understood as an anticipation of the interests of a person that will exist in the future, since that person will never come into existence. In short, this entity that does not and never will exist creates a whole new and unique situation in law, whose representation in law cannot be formulated within the current legal vocabulary. Consequently, law is confronted with a problem of representation; law lacks the concept to properly represent the future child.
This first representation problem is caused by the fact that the future child does not exist and will never come into existence. The fact that the future child’s existence is prevented because of its own interests causes a second representation problem, i.e., the paradox of representation. The representation of the future child in law is paradoxical. On the one hand, because the interests of the future child are taken into consideration, the actual child retrospectively gains a stronger legal position. By taking its interests into account, the future child is given a “voice” in the decision-making process, where it otherwise would have none. As the subject of interests, it gains legal protection against the risk of harm. On the other hand, the importance or value of the future child’s status is denied by the fact that its existence can be prevented. Preventing or ending one’s existence because he or she assumingly has an interest in his or her own non-existence is not as easy if it concerns an unborn child or a living human; it would only be possible with consent of the mother or the person him or herself. For example, euthanasia can only be realized if the patient requests this himself and not because a third party believes the patient’s life is of such poor quality that he would be better off dead. It is essential that the patient has a mechanism of expressing autonomy. The “voice” that is given to the future child, however, is simultaneously silenced by the prevention of its own existence. Appealing to the future child’s interests in its own non-existence makes this entity’s status not just ambiguous, it is paradoxical: The future child is treated as a subject of interests, which result in its becoming a non-subject.
The complexity of the future child, which results in two distinct representation problems, is at the moment unaddressed in regulation and policy guidelines invoking the interests of the future child. The fact that this complexity is underexposed becomes even more problematic when the moral impact is taken into account. The regulation of access to fertility treatments, embryo selection and forced contraception determines who should come into existence and who should not. They are tools used to select offspring and future members of our society. While claiming that it is in the future child’s interests not to come into existence, the regulation actually determines which life is worth living. Instead of explicitly addressing this aspect of the regulation, it seems to be obscured by the appeal to the interests of the future child.
The strong focus on the interests (or rights) of the future child is understandable. The rhetoric of individual rights and interests fits into the vocabulary of the liberal society, and attempts to distance the regulation from eugenic programmes of the past, which are the reason for our aversion towards selection in the first place. Nevertheless, the rhetoric of interests cannot undo the fact that regulation regarding PGD, access to fertility treatments, and forced contraception entails possibilities for the selection of offspring. At best, it might offer justification for this selection. However, this justification is challenged by representation problems raised by the vocabulary of interests. Sandel has pointed out that, with regard to the difficult issues raised by the developments in biotechnology, the liberal vocabulary of rights, interests and autonomy fails to provide proper vocabulary for articulating and discussing these issues ([
36], pp. 9–10). This seems not only to be the case for genetic enhancement, but also with the prevention of the future child’s existence, as the appeal to interests turns out to be rather paradoxical in this case. Nevertheless, since law’s attention for the future child and its interests increases, despite the fact that this entity does not fit in the legal vocabulary, it is important that the concept of the future child is further elaborated. Further research is needed in order to understand what this entity actually is, what its characteristics are and how it functions in the law. A first step could be looking beyond the traditional legal vocabulary of rights and persons, and accepting that the legal vocabulary needs to adapt or respond to the changing environment and develop new concepts and constructs for entities such as the future child.