The Multidimensional Spectrum of Imagination: Images, Dreams, Hallucinations, and Active, Imaginative Perception
Abstract
:1. A Potent and Protean Concept
2. Deflation or Inflation?
3. McGinn on the Discontinuity of Imagination and Perception
- (1).
- Will: We can freely choose to imagine pretty much anything we want, at any time, but we can perceive only what is actually now before us ([30], pp. 12ff.);
- (2).
- Observation: Perception can bring us new information about our current environment, but imagination cannot ([30], pp. 17ff.);
- (3).
- Visual field: Our eyes can only take in things within a physiologically fixed angular field of view, and the things we see must always appear at some particular location in this visual field. Imagination, by contrast, suffers from no such limitations ([30], pp. 22ff.);
- (4).
- Saturation: McGinn is aware that the hoary argument that mental images can be indeterminate in a way that percepts cannot is unsound.7 However, he defends the related view that perceptual experiences are always “saturated” (i.e., some quality is always manifested at every point in the visual field), whereas images are typically unsaturated or “gappy”: an object, such as a face, may be visualized without every detail, every shade of color at every point, being specified ([30], pp. 25f.);
- (5)
- Attention: “I can pay attention to what I am seeing or I can fail to pay attention to it; but I do not have this choice in the case of images: here I must pay attention in order to be imaging at all…[I]mages necessarily involve attentive intentionality…[O]ne has to attend to the object of the image in order for the image to exist” ([30], pp. 26ff.);
- (6)
- Absence: If we say that we perceive something, this implies that the something is really there in the world, present to our senses. By contrast, if we say that we imagine something, this implies that it is not there, not present to our senses ([30], pp. 29f.);
- (7)
- Recognition: One knows the identity of the object of one’s imagining simply in virtue of the fact that one has chosen to imagine that thing. No further act of recognition is needed in order to identify it. By contrast, perceiving what something is does require an act of recognition, because the identity of the object is determined not by the will, but by how the world is ([30], pp. 30f.);
- (8)
- Thought: Although you can perfectly well be seeing X and, simultaneously be thinking of Y, you cannot be imagining X and simultaneously be thinking of Y. ([30], p. 32);
- (9)
- Occlusion: Unlike real things, imaginary things do not block or occlude the visual scene. If there is a tree in front of us, we will not be able to see whatever might be hiding behind it, but if we imagine a tree in front of us, however vivid it may be it will not hide anything that is really there ([30], pp. 32ff).
4. Reestablishing Continuity: (i) Will
5. Of Passive Perception, Visual Impressions, Retinal Images, and Eye Movements
6. Reestablishing Continuity: (ii) Recognition
7. Reestablishing Continuity: (iii) Attention
8. Reestablishing Continuity: (iv) Visual Field
9. Reestablishing Continuity: (v) Absence and its Consequences
This joining of imagistic and perceptual space is particularly perplexing…The intentional object of the image fuses with the object located by the percept, as if the objects of imagination have come down to earth temporarily—jumped spaces, as it were. (I know this is very obscure, but someone has to say it.)([30], p. 172, note7)
10. Dreams and the Spectrum of Imagination
11. Hallucinations
- (1)
- What seems best described as exceptionally intense, colorful and vivid mental imagery. This often has bizarre content (often including abstract patterns), may have synaesthetic elements (music or other sounds may trigger experiences of color and light, for example), and partially escapes voluntary control, but it can be experienced with the eyes closed at least as well as with the eyes open, and subjects are rarely, if ever, tempted to think of it as experience of things actually physically existing out in the environment. It seems like mental imagery, or at least it seems quasi-perceptual, rather than being like actual perception.
- (2)
- Probably the more salient aspect of most psychedelic experience is a marked change in the way that the things that really are out there in the environment are experienced. It is not seeing things that are not there; rather it is a phantasmagoria of imaginative perceiving run amok, with imagination intruding even more on perception than it normally does. Meaningless shapes and patterns may become meaningful. Inanimate objects may seem to pulsate with life, or their shapes may appear distorted. Objects (and people) may take on strong emotional valences that they do not normally have. They may directly appear to be threatening, or benign, or emblematic in one way or another. A house might suddenly seem like a bejeweled palace or a filthy hovel, for instance; an ordinary pencil might somehow seem terribly important or significant; or a perfectly ordinary woman might appear to be (not be thought of as, or believed to be, but visually appear to be) a fairy princess, or a wicked witch.
- (3)
- Occasionally, reports of psychedelic experience include accounts of what seem to be dreamlike episodes, wherein the subject is transported to another world or another place, or where they believe they are doing things, in their current environment (or something resembling it), that they actually are not. It seems likely (though I am not aware of it having been confirmed scientifically) that, like a sleeping dreamer, people in such states are temporarily largely unaware of what is really going on around them.
12. Imagining That
13. Concluding Remarks: Creativity and Imaginativeness
Acknowledgments
Conflict of Interest
References
- Eva T.H. Brann. The World of the Imagination: Sum and Substance. Savage, MD: Rowman & Littlefield, 1991. [Google Scholar]
- Thomas McFarland. Originality and Imagination. Baltimore, MD: Johns Hopkins University Press, 1985. [Google Scholar]
- Jennifer Ouellette. “The death and life of American imagination.” The Rake. 16 October 2007. http://www.rakemag.com/2007/10/death-and-life-american-imagination/.
- Blaise Pascal. Pensées. Edited by Louis Lafuma. Translated by John Warrington. London: Dent, 1960, Original French, c. 1670. [Google Scholar]
- Richard Kearney. The Wake of Imagination: Ideas of Creativity in Western Culture. London: Hutchinson, 1988. [Google Scholar]
- Harry Caplan. Gianfrancesco Pico della Mirandola: On the Imagination: The Latin Text with an Introduction, an English Translation, and Notes. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press, 1930. [Google Scholar]
- Lorraine Daston. “Fear and loathing of the imagination in science.” Dædalus 127, no. 1 (1998): 73–95. [Google Scholar]
- Nigel J.T. Thomas. “Imagining minds.” Journal of Consciousness Studies 10, no. 11 (2003): 79–84. [Google Scholar]
- Kendal L. Walton. Mimesis as Make-Believe. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1990. [Google Scholar]
- Derek Matravers. “Why we should give up on the imagination.” Midwest Studies in Philosophy 34, no. 1 (2010): 190–99. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Paul Crowther. “How images complete us: Imagination and the unity of self-consciousness.” Journal of Consciousness Studies 20, no. 11–12 (2013): 101–23. [Google Scholar]
- Gilbert Ryle. The Concept of Mind. London: Hutchinson, 1949. [Google Scholar]
- Annis Flew. “Images, supposing and imagining.” Philosophy 28, no. 106 (1953): 246–54. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Peter F. Strawson. “Imagination and perception.” In Experience and Theory. Edited by Lawrence Foster and Joe W. Swanson. London: Duckworth, 1971, pp. 31–54. [Google Scholar]
- Anthony Flew. A Dictionary of Philosophy. London: Macmillan and Pan, 1979, p. 152. [Google Scholar]
- Francis Sparshott. “Imagination—the very idea.” The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 48, no. 1 (1990): 1–8. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Leslie Stevenson. “Twelve conceptions of imagination.” British Journal of Aesthetics 43, no. 3 (2003): 238–59. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Amélie O. Rorty. “Imagination and power.” In Mind in Action: Essays in the Philosophy of Mind. Boston, MA: Beacon Press, 1988, pp. 330–45. [Google Scholar]
- Alan R. White. The Language of Imagination. Oxford: Blackwell, 1990. [Google Scholar]
- Robert Nozick. The Nature of Rationality. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1993. [Google Scholar]
- Shaun Nichols, and Stephen Stich. “A cognitive theory of pretense.” Cognition 74, no. 2 (2000): 115–47. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Ruth M.J. Byrne. “The Rational Imagination: How People Create Alternatives to Reality.” Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press, 2005. [Google Scholar]
- Susanna Schellenberg. “Belief and desire in imagination and immersion.” Journal of Philosophy 110, no. 9 (2013): 497–517. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Nigel J.T. Thomas. “Imagery and the coherence of imagination: A critique of White.” Journal of Philosophical Research 22 (1997): 95–127. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Amy Kind. “Putting the image back in imagination.” Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 62, no. 1 (2001): 85–109. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Percy B. Shelley. “A defense of poetry.” In A Study of Shelley’s A Defense of Poetry. Edited by Fanny N. Deslisle. Salzburg: Institut für Englische Sprache und Literatur, Universität Salzburg, 1974. [Google Scholar]
- William Wordsworth. “The prelude.” In The Prelude: A Parallel Text. Edited by J.C. Maxwell. Harmondsworth, UK: Penguin, 1971, pp. 520–21. [Google Scholar]
- William Blake. “Milton.” In The Complete Writings of William Blake. Edited by Geoffrey Keynes. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1966, pp. 480–535. [Google Scholar]
- Samuel T. Coleridge. Biographia Literaria. Edited by George Watson. London: Dent, 1975, p. 167. [Google Scholar]
- Colin McGinn. Mindsight: Image, Dream, Meaning. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 2004. [Google Scholar]
- Colin McGinn. “Can we solve the mind-body problem? ” Mind 98, no. 391 (1989): 349–66. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Colin McGinn. The Mysterious Flame: Conscious Minds in a Material World. New York, NY: Basic Books, 1999. [Google Scholar]
- Nigel J.T. Thomas. “Fantasi, eliminativisme og bevidsthedens forhistorie.” Slagmark: Tidsskrift for Idéhistorie 46 (2006): 15–31. In Danish, but an English draft is available online: http://www.imagery-imagination.com/ieph/ieph.htm (accessed on 17 November 2013). [Google Scholar]
- David Hume. A Treatise of Human Nature, 2nd Oxford ed. Edited by L.A. Selby Bigge and P.H. Nidditch. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1978. [Google Scholar]
- Immanuel Kant. Critique of Pure Reason, 2nd ed. N.K. Smith, trans. and ed. London: Macmillan, 1933. [Google Scholar]
- Mary Warnock. Imagination. London: Faber & Faber, 1976. [Google Scholar]
- Joseph Jastrow. “The mind’s eye.” Appleton’s Popular Science Monthly 54 (1899): 299–312. [Google Scholar]
- C. Wade Savage. “The continuity of perceptual and cognitive experiences.” In Hallucinations: Behavior, Experience, and Theory. Edited by Ronald K. Siegel and Louis J. West. New York, NY: Wiley, 1975, pp. 257–86. [Google Scholar]
- Peter E. Morris, and Peter J. Hampson. Imagery and Consciousness. London: Academic Press, 1983. [Google Scholar]
- Nigel J.T. Thomas. “Are theories of imagery theories of imagination? An active perception approach to conscious mental content.” Cognitive Science 23, no. 2 (1999): 207–45. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Luigi F. Agnati, Diego Guidolin, L. Battistin, G. Pagnoni, and K. Fuxe. “The neurobiology of imagination: Possible role of interaction-dominant dynamics and default mode network.” Frontiers in Psychology 4, no. 296 (2013). [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed]
- Emily T. Troscianko. “Reading imaginatively: The imagination in cognitive science and cognitive literary studies.” Journal of Literary Semantics 42, no. 2 (2013): 181–98. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Nigel J.T. Thomas. “Visual imagery and consciousness.” In Encyclopedia of Consciousness. Edited by William P. Banks. Oxford: Academic Press, 2009, vol. 2, pp. 445–57. An expanded version is available online: http://www.imagery-imagination.com/viac.htm (accessed on 28 March 2014).
- Nigel J.T. Thomas. “Mental imagery.” In The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Edited by Edward N. Zalta. Stanford, CA: Center for the Study of Language and Information, 2013, Available online: http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/mental-imagery/ (accessed on 12 October 2013).
- Stephen M. Kosslyn. “Information representation in visual images.” Cognitive Psychology 7, no. 3 (1975): 341–70. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Stephen M. Kosslyn. Image and Mind. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1980. [Google Scholar]
- Stephen M. Kosslyn. Image and Brain. Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press, 1994. [Google Scholar]
- Stephen M. Kosslyn, William L. Thompson, and Giorgio Ganis. The Case for Mental Imagery. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2006. [Google Scholar]
- Zenon W. Pylyshyn. “What the mind’s eye tells the mind’s brain: A critique of mental imagery.” Psychological Bulletin 80, no. 1 (1973): 1–25. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Zenon W. Pylyshyn. “Imagery and artificial intelligence.” Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Science 9 (1978): 19–55. [Google Scholar]
- Zenon W. Pylyshyn. “The imagery debate: Analogue media versus tacit knowledge.” Psychological Review 88, no.1 (1981): 16–45. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Zenon W. Pylyshyn. “Mental imagery: In search of a theory.” Behavioral and Brain Sciences 25, no. 2 (2002): 157–237. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Zenon W. Pylyshyn. Seeing and Visualizing: It’s Not What You Think. Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press, 2003. [Google Scholar]
- Zenon W. Pylyshyn. “Return of the mental image: Are there really pictures in the brain? ” Trends in Cognitive Sciences 7, no. 3 (2003): 113–18. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Geoffrey Hinton. “Some demonstrations of the effects of structural descriptions in mental imagery.” Cognitive Science 3, no. 3 (1979): 231–50. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Jerry A. Fodor. The Language of Thought. New York, NY: Thomas Crowell, 1975. [Google Scholar]
- James J. Gibson. The Senses Considered as Perceptual Systems. Boston, MA: Houghton Mifflin, 1966. [Google Scholar]
- Ruzena Bajcsy. “Active perception.” Proceedings of the IEEE 76, no. 8 (1988): 996–1005. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Dana H. Ballard. “Animate vision.” Artificial Intelligence 48, no. 1 (1991): 57–86. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Yiannis Aloimonos. Active Perception. Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum, 1993. [Google Scholar]
- Arun Katkere, and Ramesh Jain. “A framework for information assimilation.” In Exploratory Vision: The Active Eye. Edited by Michael S. Landy, Laurence T. Maloney and Misha Pavel. New York, NY: Springer-Verlag, 1996, pp. 241–56. [Google Scholar]
- J. Kevin O’Regan, and Alva Noë. “A sensorimotor account of vision and visual consciousness.” Behavioral and Brain Sciences 24, no. 5 (2001): 939–1031. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- John M. Findlay, and Iain D. Gilchrist. Active Vision: The Psychology of Looking and Seeing. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2003. [Google Scholar]
- Alva Noë. Action in Perception. Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press, 2004. [Google Scholar]
- Mototaka Suzuki, and Dario Floreano. “Enactive robot vision.” Adaptive Behavior 16, no. 2–3 (2008): 122–28. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Monica S. Castelhano, Michael L. Mack, and John M. Henderson. “Viewing task influences eye movement control during active scene perception.” Journal of Vision 9, no. 3 (2009): 1–15. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Dimitri Ognibene, Giovanni Pezzulo, and Gianluca Baldassare. “Learning to look in different environments: An active-vision model which learns and readapts visual routines.” In From Animals to Animats 11, Proceedings 11th International Conference on Simulation of Adaptive Behavior, Paris-Clos Lucé, France, August 2010; Edited by Stéphane Doncieux, Benoît Girard, Agnès Guillot, John Hallam, Jean-Arcady Meyer and Jean-Baptiste Mouret. Berlin and Heidelberg: Springer, 2010, pp. 199–210. [Google Scholar]
- Shengyong Chen, Youfu Li, and Ngai Ming Kwok. “Active vision in robotic systems: A survey of recent developments.” International Journal of Robotics Research 30, no. 11 (2011): 1343–77. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- J. Kevin O’Regan. Why Red Doesn’t Sound like a Bell: Understanding the Feel of Consciousness. New York, NY: Oxford University Press, 2011. [Google Scholar]
- Shimon Ullman. “Visual routines.” Cognition 18, no. 1–3 (1984): 97–159. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed]
- Pieter R. Roelfsema, Victor A.F. Lamme, and Henk Spekreijse. “The implementation of visual routines.” Vision Research 40, no. 10–12 (2000): 1385–1411. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Mary Hayhoe. “Vision using routines: A functional account of vision.” Visual Cognition 7, no. 1–3 (2000): 43–64. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Pieter R. Roelfsema. “Elemental operations in vision.” Trends in Cognitive Sciences 9, no. 5 (2005): 226–33. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed]
- Sancho I. Moro, Michiel Tolboom, Paul S. Khayat, and Pieter R. Roelfsema. “Neuronal activity in the visual cortex reveals the temporal order of cognitive operations.” Journal of Neuroscience 30, no. 48 (2010): 16293–303. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed]
- Ulric Neisser. Cognition and Reality. San Francisco, CA: Freeman, 1976. [Google Scholar]
- Ulric Neisser. “Perceiving, anticipating and imagining.” Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Science 9 (1978): 89–106. [Google Scholar]
- Paolo Bartolomeo. “The relationship between visual perception and visual mental imagery: A reappraisal of the neuropsychological evidence.” Cortex 38, no. 3 (2002): 357–78. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Paolo Bartolomeo, and Sylvie Chokron. “Can we change our vantage point to explore imaginal neglect? ” Behavioral and Brain Sciences 25, no. 5 (2002): 184–85. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Peter J. Blain. “A Computer Model of Creativity Based on Perceptual Activity Theory.” Unpublished doctoral dissertation, Griffith University, Queensland, Australia, 2006. [Google Scholar]
- Helena De Preester. “The sensory component of imagination: The motor theory of imagination as a present-day solution to Sartre’s critique.” Philosophical Psychology 25, no. 4 (2012): 503–20. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Jan F. Sima, and Christian Freksa. “Towards computational cognitive modeling of mental imagery: The attention-based quantification theory.” KI-Künstliche Intelligenz 26, no, 3 (2012): 261–67. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Nigel J.T. Thomas. “New support for the perceptual activity theory of mental imagery: An ongoing bibliographic essay.” Available online: http://www.imagery-imagination.com/newsupa.htm (accessed on 16 March 2014).
- Peter Slezak. “The ‘philosophical’ case against visual imagery.” In Perspectives on Cognitive Science: Theories, Experiments and Foundations. Edited by Peter Slezak, Terry Caelli and Richard Clark. Norwood, NJ: Ablex Publishing, 1995, pp. 237–71. [Google Scholar]
- Thomas Reid. An Inquiry into the Human Mind on the Principles of Common Sense. Edited by Derek R. Brookes. University Park, PA: Pennsylvania State University Press, 1997, Original work published in 1764. [Google Scholar]
- Jean-Paul Sartre. The Psychology of Imagination. Translated by B. Frechtman. New York, NY: Philosophical Library, 1948. [Google Scholar]
- Ludwig Wittgenstein. Zettel. Edited by G.E.M. Anscombe and G.H. von Wright. Translated by G.E.M. Anscombe. Oxford: Blackwell, 1967. [Google Scholar]
- John W. Yolton. Perception and Reality: A History from Descartes to Kant. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press, 1996. [Google Scholar]
- Dorthe Berntsen. Involuntary Autobiographical Memories: An Introduction to the Unbidden Past. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2009. [Google Scholar]
- C. Philip Beaman, and Tim I. Williams. “Earworms (‘stuck song syndrome’): Towards a natural history of intrusive thoughts.” British Journal of Psychology 101, no. 4 (2010): 637–53. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed]
- Jonathan Ichikawa. “Dreaming and imagination.” Mind and Language 24, no. 1 (2009): 103–21. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Michael I. Posner. “Orienting of attention.” Quarterly Journal of Experimental Psychology 32, no. 1 (1980): 3–25. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Arien Mack, and Irvin Rock. Inattentional Blindness. Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press, 1998. [Google Scholar]
- Yehoshua Tsal, and Lori Kolbet. “Disambiguating ambiguous figures by selective attention.” Quarterly Journal of Experimental Psychology A37, no. 1 (1985): 25–37. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Stephan A. Brandt, and Lawrence W. Stark. “Spontaneous eye movements during visual imagery reflect the content of the visual scene.” Journal of Cognitive Neuroscience 9, no. 1 (1997): 27–38. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed]
- Michael J. Spivey, and Joy J. Geng. “Oculomotor mechanisms activated by imagery and memory: Eye movements to absent objects.” Psychological Research 65, no. 4 (2001): 235–41. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Joystone Gbadamosi, and Wolfgang H. Zangemeister. “Visual imagery in hemianopic patients.” Journal of Cognitive Neuroscience 13, no. 7 (2001): 45–56. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed]
- Bruno Laeng, and Dinu-Stefan Teodorescu. “Eye scanpaths during visual imagery reenact those of perception of the same visual scene.” Cognitive Science 26, no. 2 (2002): 207–31. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Roger Johansson, Jana Holšánová, and Kenneth Holmqvist. “Pictures and spoken descriptions elicit similar eye movements during mental imagery, both in light and in complete darkness.” Cognitive Science 30, no. 6 (2006): 1053–79. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Katherine Humphrey, and Geoffrey Underwood. “Fixation sequences in imagery and in recognition during the processing of pictures of real-world scenes.” Journal of Eye Movement Research 2, no. 2 (2008): article 3, 1–15. http://www.jemr.org/online/2/2/3. [Google Scholar]
- Jana Holšánová, Richard Andersson, Roger Johansson, Kenneth Holmqvist, and Sven Strömqvist. “Lund eye tracking studies in research on language and cognition.” Slovo a Slovesnost 71, no. 4 (2010): 317–28. [Google Scholar]
- Jan F. Sima, Maren Lindner, Holger Schultheis, and Thomas Barkowsky. “Eye movements reflect reasoning with mental images but not with mental models in orientation knowledge tasks.” In Spatial Cognition VII. Edited by Christoph Hölscher, Thomas F. Shipley, Marta O. Belardinelli, John A. Bateman and Nora S. Newcombe. Berlin and Heidelberg: Springer, 2010, pp. 248–61. [Google Scholar]
- Clémence Bourlon, Bastien Oliviero, Nicolas Wattiez, Pierre Pouget, and Paolo Bartolomeo. “Visual mental imagery: What the head’s eye tells the mind’s eye.” Brain Research 1367, no. 7 (2011): 287–97. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed]
- Roger Johansson, Jana Holšánová, Richard Dewhurst, and Kenneth Holmqvist. “Eye movements during pictorial recall have a functional role, but they are not reinstatements of those from encoding.” Journal of Experimental Psychology: Human Perception and Performance 38, no. 5 (2012): 1289–314. [Google Scholar]
- Maryam Fourtassi, Abderrazak Hajjioui, Christian Urquizar, Yves Rossetti, Gilles Rode, and Laure Pisella. “Iterative fragmentation of cognitive maps in a visual imagery task.” PLoS One 8, no. 7 (2013): e68560, 1–8. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed]
- Daniel M. Wegner, David J. Schneider, Samuel R. Carter III, and Teri L. White. “Paradoxical effects of thought suppression.” Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 53, no. 1 (1987): 5–13. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Richard M. Wenzlaff, and Daniel M. Wegner. “Thought suppression.” Annual Review of Psychology 51 (2000): 59–91. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed]
- Chris R. Brewin, James D. Gregory, Michelle Lipton, and Neil Burgess. “Intrusive images in psychological disorders: Characteristics, neural mechanisms, and treatment implications.” Psychological Review 117, no. 1 (2010): 210–32. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed]
- John S. Antrobus, Judith S. Antrobus, and Jerome L. Singer. “Eye movements accompanying daydreaming, visual imagery, and thought suppression.” Journal of Abnormal and Social Psychology 69, no. 3 (1964): 244–52. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Jerome L. Singer, and John S. Antrobus. “Eye movements during fantasies: Imagining and suppressing fantasies.” Archives of General Psychiatry 12, no. 1 (1965): 71–76. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Christopher F. Sharpley, Jain M. Montgomery, and Lina A. Scalzo. “Comparative efficacy of EMDR and alternative procedures in reducing the vividness of mental images.” Scandinavian Journal of Behaviour Therapy 25, no. 1 (1996): 37–42. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Jackie Andrade, David Kavanagh, and Alan Baddeley. “Eye-movements and visual imagery: A working memory approach to the treatment of post-traumatic stress disorder.” British Journal of Clinical Psychology 36, no. 2 (1997): 209–23. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Alastair L. Barrowcliff, Nicola S. Gray, Tom C.A. Freeman, and Malcolm J. MacCulloch. “Eye-movements reduce the vividness, emotional valence and electrodermal arousal associated with negative autobiographical memories.” Journal of Forensic Psychiatry & Psychology 15, no. 2 (2004): 325–45. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Bradley R. Postle, Christopher Idzikowski, Sergio Della Sala, Robert H. Logie, and Alan D. Baddeley. “The selective disruption of spatial working memory by eye movements.” Quarterly Journal of Experimental Psychology 59, no. 1 (2006): 100–20. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed]
- Donatas Jonikaitis, Heiner Deubel, and Claudio de’Sperati. “Time gaps in mental imagery introduced by competing saccadic tasks.” Vision Research 49, no. 17 (2009): 2164–75. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed]
- Ad de Jongh, Robert Ernst, Lisa Marques, and Hellen Hornsveld. “The impact of eye movements and tones on disturbing memories involving PTSD and other mental disorders.” Journal of Behavior Therapy and Experimental Psychiatry 44, no. 4 (2013): 477–83. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed]
- Marcel A. van den Hout, Nicola Bartelski, and Iris M. Engelhard. “On EMDR: Eye movements during retrieval reduce subjective vividness and objective memory accessibility during future recall.” Cognition and Emotion 27, no. 1 (2013): 177–83. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed]
- Bruce Bridgeman. “Conscious vs unconscious processes: The case of vision.” Theory and Psychology 2, no. 1 (1992): 73–88. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Susana Martinez-Conde, Stephen L. Macknik, and David H. Hubel. “The role of fixational eye movements in visual perception.” Nature Reviews: Neuroscience 5, no. 3 (2004): 229–40. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed]
- David Coppola, and Dale Purves. “The extraordinarily rapid disappearance of entoptic images.” Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences of the USA 93, no. 15 (1996): 8001–04. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- James J. Gibson. The Ecological Approach to Visual Perception. Boston, MA: Houghton Mifflin, 1979. [Google Scholar]
- Kenneth Holmqvist, Marcus Nyström, Richard Andersson, Richard Dewhurst, Halszka Jarodzka, and Joost van de Weijer. Eye Tracking: A Comprehensive Guide to Methods and Measures. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2011. [Google Scholar]
- Daniel C. Richardson, and Michael J. Spivey. “Eye tracking.” In Encyclopedia of Biomaterials and Biomedical Engineering. Edited by Gary E. Wnek and Gary L. Bowlin. New York: Marcel Dekker, 2004, vol. 1, pp. 568–82. [Google Scholar]
- Nicholas J. Wade, and Benjamin W. Tatler. The Moving Tablet of the Eye: The Origins of Modern Eye Movement Research. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2005. [Google Scholar]
- Al’fred L. Yarbus. Eye Movements and Vision (translated from the Russian by Basil Haigh). New York: Plenum Press, 1967. [Google Scholar]
- Michael F. Land. “Motion and vision: Why animals move their eyes.” Journal of Comparative Physiology A 185, no. 4 (1999): 341–52. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Benjamin W. Tatler, Nicholas J. Wade, Hoi Kwan, John M. Findlay, and Boris M. Velichkovsky. “Yarbus, eye movements, and vision.” i-Perception 1, no. 1 (2010): 7–27. http://i-perception.perceptionweb.com/journal/I/article/i0382. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed]
- Mary Hayhoe, and Dana Ballard. “Eye movements in natural behavior.” Trends in Cognitive Sciences 9, no. 4 (2005): 188–94. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed]
- Michael F. Land. “Eye movements and the control of actions in everyday life.” Progress in Retinal & Eye Research 25, no. 3 (2006): 296–24. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed]
- Lawrence Stark, and S.R. Ellis. “Scanpaths revisited: Cognitive models direct active looking.” In Eye Movements: Cognition and Visual Perception. Edited by Dennis F. Fisher, Richard A. Monty and John W. Senders. Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum, 1981, pp. 193–226. [Google Scholar]
- Susana Martinez-Conde, and Stephen L. Macknik. “Windows on the mind.” Scientific American 297 (August 2007): 56–63. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed]
- Constantin A. Rothkopf, Dana H. Ballard, and Mary M. Hayhoe. “Task and context determine where you look.” Journal of Vision 7, no. 14 (2007): article 16, 1–20. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed]
- Susana Martinez-Conde. “Eye movements during fixation.” In Encyclopedia of Perception. Edited by E. Bruce Goldstein. Thousand Oaks, CA: Sage Press, 2009, vol. 1, pp. 438–39. [Google Scholar]
- Martin Rolfs. “Microsaccades: Small steps on a long way.” Vision Research 49, no. 20 (2009): 2415–41. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed]
- P.E. Hallett. “Eye movements.” In Handbook of Perception and Human Performance. Edited by Kenneth R. Boff, Lloyd Kaufman and James P. Thomas. New York: Wiley-Interscience, 1986, vol. 1, pp. 10.1–10.112. [Google Scholar]
- Alexander Spauschus, Jon Marsden, David M. Halliday, Jay R. Rosenberg, and Peter Brown. “The origin of ocular microtremor in man.” Experimental Brain Research 126, no. 4 (1999): 556–62. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Matthias H. Hennig, Nicolas J. Kerscher, Klaus Funke, and Florentin Wörgötter. “Stochastic resonance in visual cortical neurons: Does the eye-tremor actually improve visual acuity? ” Neurocomputing 44 (2002): 115–20. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Igor Kagan, Moshe Gur, and D. Max Snodderly. “Saccades and drifts differentially modulate neuronal activity in V1: Effects of retinal image motion, position, and extraretinal influences.” Journal of Vision 8, no. 14, Article 19 (2008): 1–25. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed]
- András Róka, Ádám Csapó, Barna Reskó, and Péter Baranyi. “Edge detection model based on involuntary tremors and drifts of the eye.” Journal of Advanced Computational Intelligence and Intelligent Informatics 11, no. 6 (2007): 648–54. [Google Scholar]
- András Róka, Ádám Csapó, Barna Reskó, and Péter Baranyi. “Edge detection model based on involuntary eye movements of the eye-retina system.” Acta Polytechnica Hungarica 4, no. 1 (2007): 31–46. [Google Scholar]
- Igor Kagan. “Active vision: Fixational eye movements help seeing space in time.” Current Biology 22, no. 6 (2012): R186–R188. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed]
- Xutao Kuang, Martina Poletti, Jonathan D. Victor, and Michele Rucci. “Temporal encoding of spatial information during active visual fixation.” Current Biology 22, no. 6 (2012): 510–14. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed]
- David H. Hubel. Eye, Brain, and Vision, 2nd ed. San Francisco: W.H. Freeman, 1995. [Google Scholar]
- Kenneth Gaarder. “Transmission of edge information in the human visual system.” Nature 212, no. 1 (1966): 321–23. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Michele Rucci, and Gaëlle Desbordes. “Contributions of fixational eye movements to the discrimination of briefly presented stimuli.” Journal of Vision 3, no. 11 (2003): Article 18, 852–64. http://www.journalofvision.org/content/3/11/18. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed]
- Michele Rucci, Ramon Iovin, Martina Poletti, and Fabrizio Santini. “Miniature eye movements enhance fine spatial detail.” Nature 447, no. 7146 (2007): 851–54. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed]
- Kristian Donner, and Simo Hemilä. “Modelling the effect of microsaccades on retinal responses to stationary contrast patterns.” Vision Research 47, no. 9 (2007): 1166–77. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed]
- Xoana G. Troncoso, Stephen L. Macknik, and Susana Martinez-Conde. “Microsaccades counteract perceptual filling-in.” Journal of Vision 8, no. 14, Article 15 (2008): 1–9. http://journalofvision.org/8/14/15/. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Bevil R. Conway. “Color vision, cones, and color-coding in the cortex.” The Neuroscientist 15, no. 3 (2009): 247–90. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed]
- Austin Roorda, and David R. Williams. “The arrangement of the three cone classes in the living human eye.” Nature 397, no. 6719 (1999): 520–22. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed]
- Christine A. Curcio, Kimberly A. Allen, Kenneth R. Sloan, Connie L. Lerea, James B. Hurley, Ingrid B. Klock, and Ann H. Milam. “Distribution and morphology of human cone photoreceptors stained with anti-blue opsin.” Journal of Comparative Neurology 312, no. 4 (1991): 610–24. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed]
- B.R. Wooten, and George Wald. “Color-vision mechanisms in the peripheral retinas of normal and dichromatic observers.” Journal of General Physiology 61, no. 2 (1973): 125–42. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Daniel C. Dennett. Consciousness Explained. Boston, MA: Little, Brown, 1991. [Google Scholar]
- M.F. Land, J.N. Marshall, D. Brownless, and T.W. Cronin. “The eye-movements of the mantis shrimp Odontodactylus scyllarus (Crustacea: Stomatopoda).” Journal of Comparative Physiology A 167, no. 2 (1990): 155–66. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- N.J. Marshall, M.F. Land, and T.W. Cronin. “Shrimps that pay attention: Saccadic eye movements in stomatopod crustaceans.” Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society B: Biological Sciences 369, no. 1636 (2014): 1–8. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed]
- Jerome Y. Lettvin, Humberto R. Maturana, Warren S. McCulloch, and Walter H. Pitts. “What the frog’s eye tells the frog’s brain.” Proceedings of the Institute of Radio Engineers 47, no. 11 (1959): 1940–51. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Gáspár Jékely, Julien Colombelli, Harald Hausen, Keren Guy, Ernst Stelzer, François Nédélec, and Detlev Arendt. “Mechanism of phototaxis in marine zooplankton.” Nature 456, no. 7220 (2008): 395–99. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed]
- Adrian Horridge. “Pattern and 3D vision of insects.” In Visual Navigation: From Biological Systems to Unmanned Ground Vehicles. Edited by Yiannis Aloimonos. Mahwah, NJ: Erlbaum, 1996, pp. 26–59. [Google Scholar]
- Björn Brembs. “The importance of being active.” Journal of Neurogenetics 23, nos. 1–2 (2009): 120–26. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- G.A. Horridge. “The evolution of visual processing and the construction of seeing systems.” Proceedings of the Royal Society of London B: Biological Sciences 230, no. 1260 (1987): 279–92. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Karl Kral. “Behavioural–analytical studies of the role of head movements in depth perception in insects, birds and mammals.” Behavioural Processes 64, no. 1 (2003): 1–12. [Google Scholar]
- Wen-Sung Chung, and Justin Marshall. “Range-finding in squid using retinal deformation and image blur.” Current Biology 24, no. 2 (2014): R64–R65. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed]
- Iain D. Gilchrist, Valerie Brown, and John M. Findlay. “Saccades without eye movements.” Nature 390, no. 6656 (1997): 130–31. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed]
- Iain D. Gilchrist, Valerie Brown, John M. Findlay, and Michael P. Clarke. “Using the eye–movement system to control the head.” Proceedings of the Royal Society of London. Series B: Biological Sciences 265, no. 1408 (1998): 1831–36. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed]
- Denis N. Lee. “The optic flow field: The foundation of vision.” Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society of London B: Biological Sciences 290, no. 1038 (1980): 169–78. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Florian Raudies, Stefan Ringbauer, and Heiko Neumann. “A bio-inspired, computational model suggests velocity gradients of optic flow locally encode ordinal depth at surface borders and globally they encode self-motion.” Neural Computation 25, no. 9 (2013): 2421–49. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed]
- Hanne H. Thoen, Martin J. How, Tsyr-Huei Chiou, and Justin Marshall. “A different form of color vision in mantis shrimp.” Science 343, no. 6169 (2014): 411–13. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed]
- Aline Bompas, and J. Kevin O’Regan. “Evidence for a role of action in colour perception.” Perception 35, no. 1 (2006): 65–78. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Aline Bompas, and J. Kevin O’Regan. “More evidence for sensorimotor adaptation in color perception.” Journal of Vision 6, no. 2 (2006): 145–53. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed]
- John P. Frisby, and James V. Stone. Seeing: The Computational Approach to Biological Vision. Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press, 2010. [Google Scholar]
- James V. Stone. Vision and Brain: How We Perceive the World. Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press, 2012. [Google Scholar]
- George Mather. Essentials of Sensation and Perception. Hove, UK: Routledge, 2011. [Google Scholar]
- Robert Snowden, Peter Thompson, and Tom Troscianko. Basic Vision: An Introduction to Visual Perception, 2nd ed. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2012. [Google Scholar]
- Nicholas Wade, and Mike Swanston. Visual Perception: An Introduction, 3rd ed. Hove, UK: Psychology Press, 2013. [Google Scholar]
- John M. Ross, Concetta Morrone, Michael E. Goldberg, and David C. Burr. “Changes in visual perception at the time of saccades.” Trends in Neurosciences 24, no. 2 (2001): 113–21. [Google Scholar]
- Ignacio Vallines, and Mark W. Greenlee. “Saccadic suppression of retinotopically localized blood oxygen level-dependent responses in human primary visual area V1.” Journal of Neuroscience 26, no. 22 (2006): 5965–69. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed]
- J. Kevin O’Regan. “Solving the ‘real’ mysteries of visual perception: the world as an outside memory.” Canadian Journal of Psychology/Revue Canadienne de Psychologie 46, no. 3 (1992): 461–88. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Bruce Bridgeman, A.H.C. Van der Heijden, and Boris M. Velichkovsky. “A theory of visual stability across saccadic eye movements.” Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17, no. 2 (1994): 247–92. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Bruce Bridgeman. “How the brain makes the world appear stable.” i-Perception 1, no. 2 (2010): 69–72. http://i-perception.perceptionweb.com/journal/I/article/i0387. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed]
- Thomas S. Kuhn. The Structure of Scientific Revolutions, 2nd ed. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1970. [Google Scholar]
- David C. Lindberg. Theories of Vision from Al-Kindi to Kepler. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1976. [Google Scholar]
- Izet Masic. “Ibn al-Haitham—father of optics and describer of vision theory.” Medicinski Arhiv 62, no. 3 (2008): 183–88. [Google Scholar]
- David C. Lindberg. Roger Bacon and the Origins of Perspectiva in the Middle Ages. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1996. [Google Scholar]
- Peter H. Lindsay, and Donald A. Norman. Human Information Processing: An Introduction to Psychology. New York: Academic Press, 1972. [Google Scholar]
- Ralph N. Haber. “Information Processing.” In Handbook of Perception. Edited by Edward C. Carterette and Morton P. Friedman. New York and London: Academic Press, 1974, vol. 1, pp. 313–33. [Google Scholar]
- John P. Frisby. Seeing: Illusion, Brain and Mind. Oxford University Press, 1979. [Google Scholar]
- David Marr. Vision. San Francisco: Freeman, 1982. [Google Scholar]
- Ronald G. Boothe. Perception of the Visual Environment. New York: Springer, 2002. [Google Scholar]
- Hanspeter A. Mallot. Computational Vision: Information Processing in Perception and Visual Behavior. Translated by John S. Allen. Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press, 2000. [Google Scholar]
- Vicki Bruce, Patrick R. Green, and Mark A. Georgeson. Visual Perception: Physiology, Psychology and Ecology, 4th ed. Hove, UK: Psychology Press, 2003. [Google Scholar]
- Stephen E. Palmer. Vision Science: Photons to Phenomenology. Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press, 1999. [Google Scholar]
- Ian E. Gordon. Theories of Visual Perception, 3rd ed. Hove, UK: Psychology Press, 2004. [Google Scholar]
- Richard L. Gregory. Eye and Brain, 5th ed. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1997. [Google Scholar]
- Michael F. Land, and Benjamin W. Tatler. Looking and Acting: Vision and Eye Movements in Natural Behaviour. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2009. [Google Scholar]
- Steven Pinker. How the Mind Works. New York: Norton, 1997. [Google Scholar]
- Donald D. Hoffman. Visual Intelligence: How We Create What We See. New York: Norton, 1998. [Google Scholar]
- Laurence P. Pringle. Explore Your Senses: Sight. Tarrytown, NY: Marshall Cavendish, 2000. [Google Scholar]
- Laurence P. Pringle. Explore Your Senses: Hearing. Tarrytown, NY: Marshall Cavendish, 2000. [Google Scholar]
- Laurence P. Pringle. Explore Your Senses: Smell. Tarrytown, NY: Marshall Cavendish, 2000. [Google Scholar]
- Laurence P. Pringle. Explore Your Senses: Taste. Tarrytown, NY: Marshall Cavendish, 2000. [Google Scholar]
- Laurence P. Pringle. Explore Your Senses: Touch. Tarrytown, NY: Marshall Cavendish, 2000. [Google Scholar]
- Howard Gardner. The Mind’s New Science: A History of the Cognitive Revolution, 2nd ed. New York: Basic Books, 1987. [Google Scholar]
- George Sperling. “The magical number seven: Information processing then and now.” In The Making of Cognitive Science. Edited by William Hirst. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1988, pp. 71–80. [Google Scholar]
- George M. Stratton. Theophrastus and Greek Physiological Psychology before Aristotle. London: Allen & Unwin, 1917. [Google Scholar]
- Edith Hamilton, and Huntington Cairns. Plato: The Collected Dialogues, Including the Letters. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1961. [Google Scholar]
- Jonathan Barnes. The Complete Works of Aristotle: The Revised Oxford Translation. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1984, vol. 2. [Google Scholar]
- Richard W. Baldes. “Democritus on visual perception: Two theories or one? ” Phronesis 20, no. 2 (1975): 93–105. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Arthur Koestler. The Watershed: A Biography of Johannes Kepler. Garden City, NY: Anchor Books, 1960. [Google Scholar]
- René Descartes. The Philosophical Writings of Descartes, Vol. 1. John Cottingham, Robert Stoothoff, and Dugald Murdoch, trans. and ed. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1985. [Google Scholar]
- René Descartes. Descartes’ Conversation with Burman. John Cottingham, trans. and ed. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1976. [Google Scholar]
- John Hyman. “The Cartesian theory of vision.” Ratio 28, no. 2 (1986): 149–67. [Google Scholar]
- A. Mark Smith. “Saving the appearances of the appearances: The foundations of classical geometrical optics.” Archive for History of Exact Sciences 24, no. 2 (1981): 73–99. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Otto-Joachim Grüsser, and Michael Hagner. “On the history of deformation phosphenes and the idea of internal light generated in the eye for the purpose of vision.” Documenta Ophthalmologica 74, no. 1–2 (1990): 57–85. [Google Scholar]
- Gerald A. Winer, and Jane E. Cottrell. “Does anything leave the eye when we see? Extramission beliefs of children and adults.” Current Directions in Psychological Science 5, no. 5 (1996): 137–42. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Gerald A. Winer, Jane E. Cottrell, Virginia Gregg, Jody S. Fournier, and Lori A. Bica. “Fundamentally misunderstanding visual perception: Adults’ belief in visual emissions.” American Psychologist 57, no. 6–7 (2002): 417–24. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- John H. Reynolds, and Leonardo Chelazzi. “Attentional modulation of visual processing.” Annual Review of Neuroscience 27 (2004): 611–47. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed]
- Wu Li, Valentin Piëch, and Charles D. Gilbert. “Perceptual learning and top-down influences in primary visual cortex.” Nature Neuroscience 7, no. 6 (2004): 651–57. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed]
- Taosheng Liu, Jonas Larsson, and Marisa Carrasco. “Feature-based attention modulates orientation-selective responses in human visual cortex.” Neuron 55, no. 2 (2007): 313–23. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed]
- Steven L. Bressler, Wei Tang, Chad M. Sylvester, Gordon L. Shulman, and Maurizio Corbetta. “Top-down control of human visual cortex by frontal and parietal cortex in anticipatory visual spatial attention.” Journal of Neuroscience 28, no. 40 (2008): 10056–61. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed]
- Kerry McAlonan, James Cavanaugh, and Robert H. Wurtz. “Guarding the gateway to cortex with attention in visual thalamus.” Nature 456, no. 7220 (2008): 391–94. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed]
- Ulric Neisser, and Robert Becklen. “Selective looking: Attending to visually specified events.” Cognitive Psychology 7, no. 4 (1975): 480–94. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Daniel J. Simons, and Christopher F. Chabris. “Gorillas in our midst: Sustained inattentional blindness for dynamic events.” Perception 28, no. 9 (1999): 1059–74. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Daniel J. Simons. “Monkeying around with the gorillas in our midst: Familiarity with an inattentional-blindness task does not improve the detection of unexpected events.” i-Perception 1, no. 1 (2010): 3–6. http://i-perception.perceptionweb.com/journal/I/article/i0386. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed]
- Paola Bressan, and Silvia Pizzighello. “The attentional cost of inattentional blindness.” Cognition 106, no. 1 (2008): 370–83. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed]
- Victor AF. Lamme. “Why visual attention and awareness are different.” Trends in Cognitive Sciences 7, no. 1 (2003): 12–18. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Felipe De Brigard, and Jesse Prinz. “Attention and consciousness.” Wiley Interdisciplinary Reviews: Cognitive Science 1, no. 1 (2010): 51–59. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed]
- Stephen M. Kosslyn. “Measuring the visual angle of the mind’s eye.” Cognitive Psychology 10, no. 3 (1978): 356–89. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Ronald A. Finke, and Stephen M. Kosslyn. “Mental imagery acuity in the peripheral visual field.” Journal of Experimental Psychology: Human Perception and Performance 6, no. 1 (1980): 126–39. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Ronald A. Finke, and Howard S. Kurtzman. “Mapping the visual field in mental imagery.” Journal of Experimental Psychology: General 110, no. 4 (1981): 501–17. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Martin T. Orne. “On the social psychology of the psychological experiment: With particular reference to demand characteristics and their implications.” American Psychologist 17, no. 11 (1962): 776–83. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Margaret J. Intons-Peterson. “Imagery paradigms: How vulnerable are they to experimenters’ expectations? ” Journal of Experimental Psychology: Human Perception and Performance 9, no. 3 (1983): 394–412. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Ralph L. Rosnow. “The nature and role of demand characteristics in scientific inquiry.” Prevention & Treatment 5, no. 1 (2002): article pre0050037c, 1–7. [Google Scholar] [PubMed]
- Peter Kivy. “Mozart and monotheism: An essay in spurious aesthetics.” Journal of Musicology 2, no. 3 (1983): 322–28. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Francis Galton. “Statistics of mental imagery.” Mind 19 (1880): 301–18. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- James J. Gibson. “Visualizing conceived as visual apprehending without any particular point of observation.” Leonardo 7, no. 1 (1974): 41–42. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Ulric Neisser, and Nancy Kerr. “Spatial and mnemonic properties of visual images.” Cognitive Psychology 5, no. 2 (1973): 138–50. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Roger N. Shepard, and Lynn A. Cooper. Mental Images and Their Transformations. Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press, 1982. [Google Scholar]
- Peter McKellar. Imagination and Thinking. London: Cohen & West, 1957. [Google Scholar]
- Alan Richardson. Mental Imagery. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul, 1969. [Google Scholar]
- Ronald A. Finke. Principles of Mental Imagery. Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press, 1989. [Google Scholar]
- Nigel J.T. Thomas. “Mental Imagery, Philosophical Issues About.” Encyclopedia of Cognitive Science; Edited by Lynn Nadel. London/Hoboken, NJ: Nature Publishing/John Wiley, 2003/2005, vol. 2, pp. 1147–53. Online preprint: http://www.imagery-imagination.com/mipia.htm (accessed on 17 November 2013).
- Alex Byrne, and David R. Hilbert. “Color realism and color science.” Behavioral and Brain Sciences 26, no. 1 (2003): 3–59. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Nigel J.T. Thomas. “Color realism: Toward a solution to the ‘hard problem’.” Consciousness and Cognition 10, no. 1 (2001): 140–45. [Google Scholar]
- Morton Schatzman. The Story of Ruth: One Woman’s Haunting Psychiatric Odyssey. London: Duckworth, 1980. [Google Scholar]
- John Harris, and Richard L. Gregory. “Tests of the hallucinations of ‘Ruth’.” Perception 10, no. 3 (1981): 351–54. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Sydney J. Segal, and Vincent Fusella. “Influence of imaged pictures and sounds on detection of visual and auditory signals.” Journal of Experimental Psychology 83, no. 3 (1970): 458–64. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Catherine Craver-Lemley, and Adam Reeves. “How visual imagery interferes with vision.” Psychological Review 99, no. 4 (1992): 633–49. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Catherine Craver-Lemley, and Martha E. Arterberry. “Imagery-induced interference on a visual detection task.” Spatial Vision 14, no. 2 (2001): 101–20. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Paul Taylor. “Imagination and information.” Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 42, no. 2 (1981): 205–23. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Stephen M. Kosslyn, and (with John Brockman and Zenon W. Pylyshyn). “What shape are a German Shepherd’s ears? ” Edge.org. 13 July 2002. http://www.edge.org/conversation/what-shape-are-a-german-shepherd-39s-ears.
- Stephen M. Kosslyn. “Using imagery to retrieve semantic information: A developmental study.” Child Development 47, no. 2 (1976): 434–44. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Stephen M. Kosslyn. “Can imagery be distinguished from other forms of internal representation? Evidence from studies of information retrieval times.” Memory & Cognition 4, no. 3 (1976): 291–97. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed]
- Nigel J.T. Thomas. “Imagination.” Dictionary of Philosophy of Mind. Edited by Chris Eliasmith and Eric Hochstein. 1999. Available online: https://sites.google.com/site/minddict/imagination (accessed on 3 April 2013).
- Jennifer M. Windt. “The immersive spatiotemporal hallucination model of dreaming.” Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences 9, no. 2 (2010): 295–316. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- J. Allan Hobson. Dreaming as Delirium: How the Brain Goes Out of its Mind. Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press, 1999. [Google Scholar]
- David F. Marks. “Consciousness, mental imagery and action.” British Journal of Psychology 90, no. 4 (1999): 567–85. [Google Scholar]
- Peter D. Slade, and Richard P. Bentall. Sensory Deception: A Scientific Analysis of Hallucination. Baltimore, MD: Johns Hopkins University Press, 1988. [Google Scholar]
- Ghazi Asaad, and Bruce Shapiro. “Hallucinations: Theoretical and clinical overview.” American Journal of Psychiatry 143, no. 9 (1986): 1088–97. [Google Scholar]
- Ghazi Assad. Hallucinations in Clinical Psychiatry: A Guide for the Mental Health Professional. New York: Brunner/Mazel, 1990. [Google Scholar]
- Mark Manford, and F. Andermann. “Complex visual hallucinations: Clinical and neurobiological insights.” Brain 121, no. 10 (1998): 1819–40. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- James R. Brasić. “Hallucinations.” Perceptual and Motor Skills 86, no. 3 (1998): 851–77. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed]
- André Aleman, and Frank Larøi. Hallucinations: The Science of Idiosyncratic Perception. Washington DC: American Psychological Association, 2008. [Google Scholar]
- Jean-Étienne D. Esquirol. “Sur les illusions des sens chez les aliénés.” Archives Générales de Médecine 2 (1832): 5–23. (in French). [Google Scholar]
- Sanford Mintz, and Murray Alpert. “Imagery vividness, reality testing, and schizophrenic hallucinations.” Journal of Abnormal Psychology 79, no. 3 (1972): 310–16. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Mardi J. Horowitz. “Hallucinations: An information processing approach.” In Hallucinations: Behavior, Experience, and Theory. Edited by Ronald K. Siegel and Louis J. West. New York: Wiley, 1975, pp. 163–95. [Google Scholar]
- Richard P. Bentall. “The illusion of reality: A review and integration of psychological research on hallucinations.” Psychological Bulletin 107, no. 1 (1990): 82–95. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Koen B.E. Böker, Ron Hijman, René S. Kahn, and Edward H.F. Haan. “Perception, mental imagery and reality discrimination in hallucinating and non-hallucinating schizophrenic patients.” British Journal of Clinical Psychology 39, no. 4 (2000): 397–406. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- André Aleman, Edward H.F. de Haan, Koen B.E. Böcker, Ron Hijman, and René S. Kahn. “Hallucinations in schizophrenia: Imbalance between imagery and perception? ” Schizophrenia Research 57, no. 2 (2002): 315–16. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Gildas Brébion, Ruth I. Ohlsen, Lyn S. Pilowsky, and Anthony S. David. “Visual hallucinations in schizophrenia: Confusion between imagination and perception.” Neuropsychology 22, no. 3 (2008): 383–89. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed]
- Ernest Hartmann. “Dreams and other hallucinations: An approach to the underlying mechanisms.” In Hallucinations: Behavior, Experience, and Theory. Edited by Ronald K. Siegel and Louis J. West. New York: Wiley, 1975, pp. 71–80. [Google Scholar]
- Maria G. Vita, Anna P. Batocchi, Serena Dittoni, Anna Losurdo, Alessandro Cianfoni, Maria C. Stefanini, Catello Vollono, Giacomo Della Marca, and Paolo Mariotti. “Visual hallucinations and pontine demyelination in a child: Possible REM dissociation? ” Journal of Clinical Sleep Medicine 4, no. 6 (2008): 588–90. [Google Scholar]
- Lawrence G. Fischman. “Dreams, hallucinogenic drug states, and schizophrenia: A psychological and biological comparison.” Schizophrenia Bulletin 9, no. 1 (1983): 73–94. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Steven J. Novak. “LSD before Leary: Sidney Cohen’s critique of 1950s psychedelic drug research.” Isis 88, no. 1 (1997): 87–110. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Anna Marsh. “Visual hallucinations during hallucinogenic experience and schizophrenia.” Schizophrenia Bulletin 5, no. 4 (1979): 627–30. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Heinrich Klüver. “Mescal visions and eidetic vision.” American Journal of Psychology 37, no. 4 (1926): 502–15. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Aldous Huxley. The Doors of Perception—Heaven and Hell. New York: Harper & Row, 1956. [Google Scholar]
- Ronald K. Siegel, and Murray E. Jarvik. “Drug induced hallucinations in animals and man.” In Hallucinations: Behavior, Experience, and Theory. Edited by Ronald K. Siegel and Louis J. West. New York: Wiley, 1975, pp. 81–161. [Google Scholar]
- Albert Hofmann. LSD, My Problem Child. New York: McGraw-Hill, 1980. [Google Scholar]
- Ronald K. Siegel. Fire in the Brain: Clinical Tales of Hallucinations. New York: Dutton, 1992. [Google Scholar]
- Benny Shanon. “Hallucinations.” Journal of Consciousness Studies 10, no. 2 (2003): 3–31. [Google Scholar]
- Hilary Putnam. Reason, Truth and History. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1981. [Google Scholar]
- Diego Cosmelli, and Evan Thompson. “Embodiment or envatment? Reflections on the bodily basis of consciousness.” In Enaction: Towards a New Paradigm for Cognitive Science. Edited by John Stewart, Olivier Gapenne and Ezequiel di Paolo. Cambridge MA: The MIT Press, 2010, pp. 361–86. [Google Scholar]
- Tony Brueckner. “Brains in a vat.” In The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, Winter 2011 Ed. Edited by Edward N. Zalta. Stanford, CA: Center for the Study of Language and Information, 2011, Available online: http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2011/entries/brain-vat/ (accessed on 1 April 2014).
- Peter Dallos. “The active cochlea.” Journal of Neuroscience 2, no. 12 (1992): 4575–85. [Google Scholar]
- Stéphane Maison, Christophe Micheyl, and Lionel Collet. “Influence of focused auditory attention on cochlear activity in humans.” Psychophysiology 38, no. 1 (2001): 35–40. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Susan J. Lederman, and Roberta L. Klatzky. “Haptic exploration and object representation.” In Vision and Action: The Control of Grasping. Edited by Melvyn A. Goodale. Norwood, NJ: Ablex, 1990, pp. 98–109. [Google Scholar]
- Allan M. Smith, Geneviéve Gosselin, and Bryan Houde. “Deployment of fingertip forces in tactile exploration.” Experimental Brain Research 147, no. 2 (2002): 209–18. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed]
- Robert Teghtsoonian, Martha Teghtsoonian, Birgitta Berglund, and Ulf Berglund. “Invariance of odor strength with sniff vigor: An olfactory analogue to size constancy.” Journal of Experimental Psychology: Human Perception and Performance 4, no. 1 (1978): 144–52. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Moustafa Bensafi, Jessica Porter, Sandra Pouliot, Joel Mainland, Bradley Johnson, Christina Zelano, Natasha Young, Elizabeth Bremner, Danny Aframian, Rehan Khan, and Noam Sobel. “Olfactomotor activity during imagery mimics that during perception.” Nature Neuroscience 6, no. 11 (2003): 1142–44. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed]
- Joel Mainland, and Noam Sobel. “The sniff is part of the olfactory percept.” Chemical Senses 31, no. 2 (2006): 181–96. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed]
- Bruce P. Halpern. “Tasting and smelling as active, exploratory sensory processes.” American Journal of Otolaryngology 4, no. 4 (1983): 246–49. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Ranier Gutierrez, Sidney A. Simon, and Miguel A.L. Nicolelis. “Licking-induced synchrony in the taste–reward circuit improves cue discrimination during learning.” Journal of Neuroscience 30, no. 1 (2010): 287–303. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed]
- Geoffrey Schultz, and Ronald Melzack. “The Charles Bonnet syndrome: ‘Phantom visual images’.” Perception 20, no. 6 (1991): 809–25. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Jayakrishna G. Menon, Imran Rahman, Sharmila J. Menon, and Gordon N. Dutton. “Complex visual hallucinations in the visually impaired: The Charles Bonnet Syndrome.” Survey of Ophthalmology 48, no. 1 (2003): 58–72. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Pammal T. Ashwin, and Marie D. Tsaloumas. “Complex visual hallucinations (Charles Bonnet syndrome) in the hemianopic visual field following occipital infarction.” Journal of the Neurological Sciences 263, no. 1 (2007): 184–86. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed]
- Theodore R. Sarbin, and Joseph B. Juhasz. “The social context of hallucinations.” In Hallucinations: Behavior, Experience, and Theory. Edited by Ronald K. Siegel and Louis J. West. New York: Wiley, 1975, pp. 241–56. [Google Scholar]
- Otto-Joachim Grüsser, and Theodor Landis. Visual Agnosias and Other Disturbances of Visual Perception and Cognition. London: Macmillan, 1991. [Google Scholar]
- Malcolm Schofield. “Aristotle on the imagination.” In Aristotle on the Mind and the Senses. Edited by G.E.R. Lloyd and G.E.L. Owen. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1978, pp. 99–140. [Google Scholar]
- Joseph B. Juhasz. “Greek Theories of Imagination.” Journal of the History of the Behavioral Sciences 7 no. 1 (1971): 39–58. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Gerard Watson. Phantasia in Classical Thought. Galway, Ireland: Galway University Press, 1988. [Google Scholar]
- John M. Cocking. Imagination: A Study in the History of Ideas. London: Routledge, 1991. [Google Scholar]
- Dominic M. Lopes. “Out of sight, out of mind.” In Imagination, Philosophy, and the Arts. Edited by Matthew Kieran and Dominic M. Lopes. London: Routledge, 2003, pp. 208–24. [Google Scholar]
- Bertrand Russell. “On propositions: What they are and how they mean.” Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, Supplementary Volumes 2 (1919): 1–43. [Google Scholar]
- Henry H. Price. Thinking and Experience. London: Hutchinson, 1953. [Google Scholar]
- Natika Newton. “Experience and imagery.” Southern Journal of Philosophy 20, no. 4 (1982): 475–87. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Ralph D. Ellis. Questioning Consciousness: The Interplay of Imagery, Cognition, and Emotion in the Human Brain. Amsterdam: John Benjamins, 1995. [Google Scholar]
- J.C. Nyíri. “The picture theory of reason.” In Rationality and Irrationality: Proceedings of the 23rd International Wittgenstein Symposium, Kirchberg am Wechsel, Austria, 13–19 August, 2000; Edited by Berit Brogaard and Barry Smith. Vienna: Öbv & Hpt Verlagsgesellschaft, 2001, pp. 242–66. Available online: http://www.hunfi.hu/nyiri/krb2000.htm (accessed on 26 March 2014). [Google Scholar]
- Jesse Prinz. Furnishing the Mind: Concepts and their Perceptual Basis. Boston, MA: The MIT Press, 2002. [Google Scholar]
- Robert Arp. Scenario Visualization: An Evolutionary Account of Creative Problem Solving. Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press, 2008. [Google Scholar]
- Robert R. Holt. “Imagery: The return of the ostracized.” American Psychologist 19, no. 4 (1964): 254–66. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Nigel J.T. Thomas. “Experience and theory as determinants of attitudes toward mental representation: The case of Knight Dunlap and the vanishing images of J.B. Watson.” American Journal of Psychology 102, no. 3 (1989): 395–412. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Martin Jay. Downcast Eyes: The Denigration of Vision in Twentieth-Century French Thought. Berkeley, CA: University of California Press, 1993. [Google Scholar]
- Shaun Nichols, ed. The Architecture of the Imagination: New Essays on Pretence, Possibility, and Fiction. New York: Oxford University Press, 2006.
- Robin Barrow. “Some observations on the concept of imagination.” In Imagination and Education. Edited by Kieran Egan and Dan Nadaner. Milton Keynes, UK: Open University Press, 1988, pp. 79–90. [Google Scholar]
- 1Gianfrancesco, whose De Imaginatione was written, in Latin, in about 1500 A.D., should not be confused with his uncle, also a philosopher, Giovanni Pico della Mirandola.
- 2The Shelley is from his A Defense of Poetry ([26], originally written in 1821 and first published in 1840), the Wordsworth is from The Prelude ([27], book 14, 1845–6 version, lines 167–70; 1850 version, lines 189–92), the Blake is from his Milton ([28], §32, lines 19–20) (written c.1804–1808), and the Coleridge, complete with capitalization, is from chapter 13, “On the Imagination, or Esemplastic Power”, of his Biographia Literaria [29].
- 3Henceforth, unless otherwise indicated, references to McGinn’s views will be alluding to this work.
- 4Sima and Freksa [81] distinguish between their own view and what they call “enactive theory”. However, they appear to be using that expression to refer specifically to the imagery theory that I proposed in 1999 [40] (actually under the name “perceptual activity theory”), and which they criticize for not being formulated in computational terms. (Blain, however, has since shown that it can be modeled computationally [79].) As I intend the expression “enactive theory” here, however, it does not refer specifically to my own view, but to a broad class of theoretical positions (including mine) that, although they may differ in various ways, are alike in that they all reject the identification of mental imagery with inner pictures or descriptions, and, instead, see it as arising from the offline functioning of active, exploratory mechanisms of perception and attention. On that basis, I think it is justifiable and appropriate to classify the Sima and Freksa [81] theory as a form of enactive theory. Certainly they explicitly reject both quasi-pictorial and description theories.
- 6It has been put to me, by a referee, that Hume did not hold that all ideas are necessarily less vivacious than all impressions, only that any particular idea will be less vivacious than the impression from which it derived. I do not think that this consideration will rescue Hume’s version of continuum theory from vacuity, however. In Hume’s system, no idea can ever be compared in point of vivacity to the impression from which it derived, because, by the time it has become an idea, the impression qua impression no longer exists. We can only ever compare current impressions to current ideas derived from past impressions. If it is then admitted that sometimes a current impression may be less vivacious than certain current ideas, then vivacity is rendered useless as a criterion for distinguishing these two classes of mental content (yet Hume seems to offer us no other). In any case, this is all rather beside the point. My concern is not to criticize (or defend) Hume, but to defend continuum theory. If McGinn’s objection to Hume’s version of continuum theory is unsound, then so much the better for continuum theory. If the objection is sound (as I and others [36,38,84] are inclined to believe) well then, I am going to argue that there is nevertheless a version of continuum theory that remains plausible and defensible.
- 7A closely related argument, that I think has been made more often (and has also been repeatedly refuted), is that mental images cannot be inner pictures, because the former can be indeterminate in ways that the latter cannot. Both these arguments fail for similar reasons. See [44] (§4.4.1, and particularly note 31) for a brief account of the argument as applied to the notion of inner pictures, of why it fails, and for a brief bibliography both of attempts to press the argument, and of refutations of it.
- 8As we shall see in what follows, it may be that just three dimensions will be enough. If so, such a map should be relatively easy to visualize and to grasp intuitively. Anything beyond very rough quantification along the dimensions may prove difficult, however.
- 10Emphasis added. Of course, this raises questions about the countability of behaviors, but the mere prima facie plausibility of the claim brings home the fact that we do make an awful lot of eye movements, and suggests that there must be some very good reasons for them.
- 11It does not follow, however, that the avoidance of receptor fatigue is the only, or even main, function of eye movements, as we shall shortly see.
- 12Apart from saccades and the three types of “fixational” eye movements just discussed, there are also a number of other types of largely involuntary eye movement. These include the smooth pursuit or tracking movements by which our eyes follow the path of a moving object, and the vergence movements whereby the two eyes converge to fixate objects at different distances ([134], §2.1.1).
- 13There are circumstances in which it is useful for some animals (not humans) to keep their eyes truly static, but that is when they have no interest in the scene in front of them unless something moves in it, and when they want to be able to very quickly and reliably detect such movement (usually of other animals: prey or predator) within an otherwise static visual field. A frog waiting to catch a fly is in this situation, and keeps very still until a fly crosses its visual field, seeing nothing but the fly ([155], see also [125], p. 346). However, if humans or other animals want to be able to see the world around them, which is usually mostly static, they must move their eyes.
- 14Actually, the “eye-spots” of the animals in question (Platynereis larvae—but the article’s authors appear to believe that their results are likely to generalize to other animals of similar type) consist of two cells, a single light-sensitive receptor and a pigmented cell, which shades the receptor from light coming from one side. This shading plays an important role, together with the animal’s movement, in its ability to sense the direction from which light is coming [156].
- 15It is true that there is a neural mechanism known as saccadic suppression that appears to suppress aspects of visual processing during the saccade itself [175]. The issue of current concern, however, is not what happens during saccades, but the fact that from one saccade to the next the images of each feature of the visual scene will have changed position on the retina. Also, of course, during the brief periods of (relative) fixation between saccades, when this suppression is lifted, other forms of eye movement such as drift and tremor are continuing.
- 16Abū ʿAlī al-Ḥasan ibn al-Ḥasan ibn al-Haytham (d. c. 1039 A.D.), known in the West as Alhacen or Alhazen, was a Muslim scientist who appears to have been the first to establish that human vision involves the focusing of light into an image within the eye. His work had considerable influence on European optical theorists through the later Middle Ages and the era of the Scientific Revolution [180,181,182].
- 17Please note that, in criticizing VIPT as a theory of the overarching architecture of perceptual cognition, I do not thereby mean to imply that the concepts of information, of processing, and the closely associated notion of computation, do not have legitimate uses in cognitive science, and even in the theory of vision.
- 18Amongst current editions of texts still in print, I have been able to find just three clear exceptions to this rule. One is the 1997 fifth edition (still by the original author) of Eye and Brain, a text first published in 1966, before VIPT became the dominant theory [192]. It discusses Marr, and VIPT in general, only briefly and quite skeptically. It also devotes a few pages (distinctly more than most of the other current textbooks) to eye movements and their physiology, and acknowledges, but does not greatly elaborate upon, their functional role in vision. The other two exceptions were both first published relatively recently, and both give eye movements a prominent and central role in their accounts of human vision, explicitly or implicitly rejecting VIPT [63,193]. These represent the newer, alternative, paradigm for visual science.
- 19This last remark does not apply to Democritus, who appears to have held that an impression was made, quite literally, upon the air between the perceiver and the perceived object, after which the impression, made of, as-it-were, compressed solidified air, presumably entered the eye [206]. Aristotle and Plato, however, clearly think of the impression (or something analogous to one) as being formed within the subject, impressed (perhaps metaphorically) into the substance of the soul.
- 20Descartes was not the first to describe such an experiment. He was anticipated by some seven years by the Jesuit, Christoph Scheiner [123].
- 21This physiological theory remains in the background of the more “philosophical” works of Descartes, such as the Meditations, for which he is best known today, but is spelled out in detail in his now lesser known “scientific” works, such as the Optics and, especially, the Treatise on Man (both, abridged, in [208]). In their time, these works were widely read and very influential. Although the Treatise on Man was written relatively early in Descartes’ career, and was not published until after his death, there is ample evidence in late material such as the Passions of the Soul [208] and the Conversation with Burman [209], that the ideas therein continued to shape his thinking to the end.
- 22To put it just a little less gnomically, I hold that mental imagery is (or supervenes upon) the (generally covert and partial) enactment of those specific acts of directed attention that would be necessary for the perceiving of the imagined object, if it were actually present to the senses.
- 23For further relevant citations, see [82].
- 24Other, related experiments have found similar results [227,228], but are vulnerable to essentially same objection. The theoretical preconceptions of the experimenters—in particular, the notion that the mind’s eye should have some reasonably well defined visual angle—are built into the very structure of the experiment and the instructions given to the subjects. More generally, experiments of this sort, that rely crucially upon introspective reports that cannot be independently checked, are particularly likely to be vulnerable to having their results distorted by what psychologists call experimental demand characteristics ([229,230,231]; and see [44], §4.3 supplement 2), a serious pitfall for many forms of psychological experimentation on humans. Demand characteristics are formal and informal features of the experimental design, situation, and context that may enable the subjects to infer or guess something about the experimenters’ preconceptions, intentions, and/or expectations, and to adjust their performance accordingly (usually by doing their best to provide the results they think the experimenters want).
- 25I doubt whether it is even possible to get a clear sense of the contents of one’s imaginative experience at an instantaneous “snapshot” moment (the story that Mozart could imaginatively grasp a whole symphony in an atemporal moment is a myth [232]). However, I doubt even more whether, if I actually could isolate such an imaginative snapshot, it would prove to have an unrestricted visual field. If visual experience actually consisted of a series of visual snapshots, like photographic stills, (it does not: see [64], chapter 2), and if mental images were like reproductions of such snapshots, then we would surely find that the visual field of an image would be quite as restricted as that of the fixated eyes. This, indeed, is what Kosslyn, and Finke, did find when they built such assumptions about the nature of vision and imagery into the demand structures of their experiments [226,227,228]. McGinn’s claim about the spatially unrestricted field of the imagination is plausible only if we take it (as it is natural to do) as a claim about what we are capable of imagining over some (possibly quite brief) interval of time. It is true that there have very occasionally been reports in the literature on imagery that, at first blush, seem to suggest that some people may be capable of visualizing a scene “from no particular point of view” or of visualizing things as being concealed behind or inside other (opaque) things, or of visualizing all sides of an opaque object, such as a dice, at once [233,234,235]. However, I think such reports are best understood as misleadingly phrased expressions of the great fluidity and rapidity with which “the mind’s eye” can move to new points of view (perhaps coupled with the common enough abilities to mentally rotate visualized objects [236], and to imagine opaque things as if they were transparent). I very much doubt that McGinn truly intends to affirm that it is possible to visualize a scene in a 360° panorama, all at once, or to visualize an object as it would appear from two or more directions at once. Not only has there never been anything like this in my imaginative experience (to the extent that I cannot really even conceive what it might be like) but, beyond the three citations just given, there is also virtually no suggestion of it in all the rest of the voluminous scientific literature on mental imagery. It would also be an experience so radically phenomenologically unlike normal visual perception that it would violate standard definitions of what mental imagery is [40,43,44,237,238,239,240]. For a defense of such definitions, see ([44], §1).
- 26I incline toward a realist or physicalist view of color, whereby colors are (for the most part) to be identified with spectral reflectance properties of object surfaces [241,242]. However, the present argument does not depend upon that controversial theory. If you have some objection to my saying that some “color quality” is manifested at every visible point in the external world, please feel free to substitute “some property disposed to cause a certain sort of color experience in normally sighted humans”, or whatever your preferred theory of color would dictate. Of course, I am using “color” in the broad sense that includes black, white, and grays.
- 27Schatzman [243] claims to have discovered a woman with fully occlusive imagery. He describes experiments in which her vivid mental images appeared to completely block her visual cortex’s response to real stimuli that were “behind” them. However, after studying the same individual (although not repeating the most directly relevant experiment), Harris & Gregory [244] were skeptical about her alleged powers.
- 28Vividness, inasmuch as something so subjective can be quantified in a meaningful way [43], may well vary markedly from dream to dream and from person to person, as seems to be the case with waking imagery [255]. As Windt [253] notes, however, dreams do seem to differ from typical examples of waking imaginative experience in their degree of “immersiveness”. Possibly this represents another dimension along which imaginative experiences may be mapped, or perhaps it merely reflects the combination of very low stimulus constrainedness with the low amenability to voluntary control that is typical of (non-lucid) dreams. I will not pursue this issue further here, except to point out that Windt ([250], p. 296 note 1) seems to be sympathetic to some form of continuum theory.
- 30The following sketch of a phenomenology of psychedelic experience is synthesized from several sources: my own memories of a number of LSD “trips”; anecdotal accounts from hallucinogenic drug users, gathered from various informal sources (including conversation and the internet); and formally published, first or second hand accounts of the effects of various hallucinogens, mostly from the scientific literature [38,271,272,273,274,275,276,277,278,279]. The systematization, such as it is, is my own, and I make no great claims for the account’s comprehensiveness or scientific standing. My aim is merely to show that actual psychedelic experience comes nowhere near fitting McGinn’s idiosyncratic conception of hallucination.
- 31Putnam’s argument [277] is well known amongst philosophers, but both its soundness and its significance are controversial [282]. It is sometimes taken to establish the conceptual impossibility of brains in vats (as philosophers have traditionally thought of them). As I read it, however, even if sound, it does not so much establish that brains in vats cannot exist, but, rather, that the brain-in-a-vat thought experiment fails to provide the sort of support for radical skepticism that it is designed to provide. On that interpretation, Putnam’s argument is not relevant to our current concerns. However, Dennett [152] and (in much more detail) Cosmelli and Thompson [278] make a quite different, biologically based case for the nomological impossibility of the brain-in-a-vat scenario. If they are right, hallucinations as conceived by McGinn do not and cannot occur.
- 33Not all hallucinations are particularly vivid ([256], p. 121), but then, (as McGinn is aware) neither are all percepts.
- 34The word appears to have been given its modern meaning in the early 19th century, by the French psychiatrist Esquirol [262]; the Latin root from which it came had nothing particularly to do with seeing, or otherwise perceiving, things that are not there, but, rather, meant wandering of the mind, or idle, foolish talk and behavior [295].
- 35Some phenomena that may occasionally get called hallucinations, such as afterimages, phosphenes and migraine auras [296], probably owe little or nothing to the imagination, and much more to the anatomy of the visual system. Probably these should be classed as percepts. However, they are clearly not what McGinn has in mind.
- 36Schofield [297] says that Aristotle may fairly be said to have invented the concept of imagination (see also [298]), but, of course, it is more accurate to say that he initiated philosophical (and psychological) discussion of it. The very fact that he felt the need to distinguish between literal and metaphorical senses of the term implies that it was already in vernacular use, in both senses, in his time. Of course, Aristotle was not actually discussing the English word “imagination” but the Greek “phantasia”, and the word translated here as “image” is “phantasma”. For a defense of these standard, but occasionally questioned, translations, see ([44], §2.2); for accounts of how the Aristotelian phantasia developed into the richer Latin concept of imaginatio, and eventually into our imagination, see [299,300].
- 37White [19] takes some delight in catching out the great philosophers of past centuries writing of “imagining that” X (where X is an abstract notion of which we cannot form an image), even though their “official” view is that imagination has to do with imagery and perception. For White, this is evidence that their relevant views were incoherent. I would suggest, instead, that it is no more than evidence that they sometimes employed dead metaphors in their writing (as do we all).
- 38It is also not difficult to see how, in a similar way, the meaning of “imaginary” might come to be extended from “apprehended via imagery” to “apprehended only via imagery” to “not apprehensible via the senses” to “non-existent”.
- 39In the end, in Mindsight [30], McGinn officially follows the analytical herd in ascribing a greater importance to propositional imagination, imagining that. However, this is somewhat belied by the fact that he devotes much more space (and, it seems to me, despite my disagreements with him, much more care) to imagery and the other phenomena of the spectrum.
- 40And see Section 2, above. For much of the 20th century, this attitude was also validated by (and, no doubt, reciprocally helped to validate) the pervasive “iconophobia” of the Behaviorist movement that dominated scientific psychology until the 1960s ([44], §3.2 supplement 2; [309,310]), and I certainly do not mean to imply that the widespread iconophobia amongst intellectuals in the first half of the 20th century was solely, or even mainly, a consequence of the analytical philosophy movement. Indeed, something closely related also seems to have taken hold of the “continental philosophy” tradition during roughly the same era [311]. Some of the (doubtless unconscious) roots of this attitude may have lain in racist theories (from the colonial era, but later embraced by Nazis) about a contrast between the supposedly image-based thinking of “primitive” peoples (and children) and the supposedly verbal thinking of “civilized” adults ([44], §3.2 supplement 1).
© 2014 by the author; licensee MDPI, Basel, Switzerland. This article is an open access article distributed under the terms and conditions of the Creative Commons Attribution license (http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/3.0/).
Share and Cite
Thomas, N.J.T. The Multidimensional Spectrum of Imagination: Images, Dreams, Hallucinations, and Active, Imaginative Perception. Humanities 2014, 3, 132-184. https://doi.org/10.3390/h3020132
Thomas NJT. The Multidimensional Spectrum of Imagination: Images, Dreams, Hallucinations, and Active, Imaginative Perception. Humanities. 2014; 3(2):132-184. https://doi.org/10.3390/h3020132
Chicago/Turabian StyleThomas, Nigel J.T. 2014. "The Multidimensional Spectrum of Imagination: Images, Dreams, Hallucinations, and Active, Imaginative Perception" Humanities 3, no. 2: 132-184. https://doi.org/10.3390/h3020132
APA StyleThomas, N. J. T. (2014). The Multidimensional Spectrum of Imagination: Images, Dreams, Hallucinations, and Active, Imaginative Perception. Humanities, 3(2), 132-184. https://doi.org/10.3390/h3020132