Controlling the State in the Political Theory of Hamas and Palestinian Islamic Jihad
Abstract
:1. Introduction
2. The Necessity of Removing the Fangs of the State
al-Shiqaqi’s Conception of Just Society
The state is repressive by nature, or a tool of repression against the government classes as defined by Lenin. It is the most dangerous instrument of power created by human society, so Islam worked to sort out a mode of human society depriving this state of its power and domination, and thus making it weaker than, and accountable to, society even if the most powerful caliphs and sultans controlled it.
It is in the nature of the state always to become despotic. A strong civil society prevents the state from controlling more power. What is the state? The definition of the state is the monopoly of force; it holds legitimate force. The power of any state, any society, must be distributed. If the economy, such as money, is distributed, then power is distributed—and it is not as if the state has its hands on everything. The state then becomes weaker and a servant for society, and not society as a servant for the state. Today, the university administration [should] serve the students, and not the students who [should] serve the university administration. The state [should] serve the people, and not the people serve the state.(interview with author, 19 March 2018, Beirut)
The state controls everything today from legislation to jurisdiction and executive power. There is thus no legislative authority independent from the state preventing the latter from infringement, particularly since unlimited security apparatuses support this state. Take Press Law no. 93 of 1995 in Egypt, for example. The state imposed the law on the Egyptian parliament [majlis al-shaʿb], despite the comprehensive opposition. The legislation has today become subjected to the state or the executive power, whilst it under Islam was subjected to the class of scholars and judges [li-ṭabaqat al-ʿulamāʾ wa-l-quḍāh], and those qualified to appoint or depose a ruler on behalf of the Muslim community [ahl al-ḥall wa-l-ʿaqd].
3. Preventing the Descent into the State of Nature
Mansur’s Conception of Just Society
the president accepts, rejects, or freezes whatever laws he wants by virtue of the [existing peace] agreements, the rule of the historical [Palestinian] leadership and the status quo, and the weak role of the legislative council … The evidence of this is the deteriorating state of freedoms, human rights, and legal and judicial status [in the Occupied Palestinian Territories] … The absence of law and its rule will pave the way for the rule of chaos, the rule of centers of power, and the rule of the security and customary spirit [siyādat al-rūḥ al-amaniyya wa-l-ʿurfiyya] in public life.
In order to ensure the creation of a political entity and a modern state, a commitment to an effective balance and equilibrium between the three authorities must be found, as this is one of the important general concepts, which the world has known for civilization as a basis for a normal rule, but it is the defining boundary that distinguishes the modern state from the clan and the most important guarantee of public liberties.
The constitution is, in this way, considered a contract between the pillars of society or its parts, and it represents the most important principle of social cohesion at the societal or group level. This is because leaving matters to coincidences or good intentions will lead to problems, unrest, and even conflicts. The clearer and more reliable our contractual rules are, the fewer errors there are and the easier the correction process is.
4. The Democratic Limits of al-Shiqaqi and Mansur’s Future Societies
the problem that some Islamists have with democracy is with the term and not with the principle of consultation [shūra] and political participation. Nor do they have a problem with the mechanisms, means, systems, institutions, and experiences achieving the purposes and objectives of democracy.
Today, in some states, there are people’s councils or councils of lords, one council, or several councils; this is not a problem. The issue is always to have a state that represents society, which emanates from the parliament, the president or government, and that they represent the people, and [not emanate] from corruption or acquisition.(interview with author, 19 March 2018, Beirut)
It is true that the Islamic political system is not static. However, from the time when it was set up in the era of the Prophet, it is possible to rely on [its] foundations, principles, and fixed assets to develop our Islamic political system according to any new reality and according to the facts that arise.
I believe that Islam forms the umma’s identity and its civilizational heritage, which cannot be abandoned, and which simultaneously is its reference [marjiʿiyyatuhā]. With the recognition of this reference, then there is no problem with pluralism. Islam does not mean this party or that movement. All of these Islamic movements and organizations do not equate Islam but are only a part of it. All currents that recognize one reference for the umma is a part of it and has the right to express itself in the appropriate manner. We therefore believe in pluralism and the rotation of power within the framework of all recognizing the reference of the one umma and the constitution on which the umma agrees. After that, if there are a number of independent reasonings [ijtihādāt] and interpretations [tafsīrāt], even in the understanding of the constitution and religion itself, there is still no problem.
For the Qur’an is the constitution in the sense that it is the reference and supreme legitimacy, and the constitution of an Islamic entity will never deviate from the requirements of the Qur’an and its legal provisions (Mansur 1999, pp. 13, 20) … As for the written constitution, it is a modern necessity and has legal and structural foundations. It has been accepted in Islam, provided that the constitution is guided above all by the rules and purposes of Islamic law [bi-qawāʿid al-sharīʿa wa maqāṣiduhā].
5. Conclusions
Funding
Institutional Review Board Statement
Informed Consent Statement
Acknowledgments
Conflicts of Interest
1 | The original sentence is: “When the legislative and executive powers are united in the same person, or in the same body of magistrates, there can be no liberty … Again, there is no liberty, if the judiciary power be not separated from the legislative and executive [emphasis added]” (de Montesquieu 1766, p. 222). |
References
- al-Hadaf. 1995. Al-Ḥarakāt al-islāmiyya wa taṭawwurāt al-qaḍiya al-filasṭīniyya. In Riḥlat al-dam Alladhī Hazam al-sayf. Al-Aʿmāl al-Kāmila li-l-Shahīd al-Duktūr Fatḥī al-Shiqāqī. Edited by Ahmad Rif’at Sayyid. Cairo: Markaz Yāfā li-l-Dirāsāt wa-l-Abḥāth, pp. 1212–23. [Google Scholar]
- al-Raya. 1994. Al-Ittifāq Ḥall Mashākil allatī yuʿānī minhā al-kayān al-ṣahyūnī mundhu al-iḥtilāl 1967 ḥattā alān. In Riḥlat Al-dam Alladhī Hazam Al-sayf. Al-Aʿmāl al-Kāmila li-l-Shahīd al-Duktūr Fatḥī al-Shiqāqī. Edited by Ahmad Rif’at Sayyid. Cairo: Markaz Yāfā li-l-Dirāsāt wa-l-Abḥāth, pp. 909–13. [Google Scholar]
- al-Shiqaqi, Fathi. 1980. Īrān al-thawra wa-l-dawla. In Riḥlat al-Dam alladhī Hazam al-Sayf. Al-Aʿmāl al-Kāmila li-l-Shahīd al-Duktūr Fatḥī al-Shiqāqī. Edited by Ahmad Rif’at Sayyid. Cairo: Markaz Yāfā li-l-Dirāsāt wa-l-Abḥāth, pp. 190–99. [Google Scholar]
- al-Shiqaqi, Fathi. 1990. Muqābala: ʿan ḥarakat al-jihād wa qaḍāyāhā. In Riḥlat al-Dam alladhī Hazam al-Sayf. Al-Aʿmāl al-Kāmila li-l-Shahīd al-Duktūr Fatḥī al-Shiqāqī. Edited by Ahmad Rif’at Sayyid. Cairo: Markaz Yāfā li-l-Dirāsāt wa-l-Abḥāth, pp. 722–30. [Google Scholar]
- al-Shiqaqi, Fathi. 1995. al-Uṣūliyya wa-l-ʿilmāniyya. In Riḥlat al-dam alladhī hazam al-sayf. Al-Aʿmāl al-kāmila li-l-shahīd al-duktūr Fatḥī al-Shiqāqī. Edited by Ahmad Rif’at Sayyid. Cairo: Markaz Yāfā li-l-Dirāsāt wa-l-Abḥāth, pp. 588–96. [Google Scholar]
- Burgat, François. 2003. Face to Face with Political Islam. London: I.B. Tauris. [Google Scholar]
- de Montesquieu, Baron. 1766. The Spirit of the Laws Vol. I, 4th ed. Translated by Nugent Thomas. London: I. B. Bosanquets. [Google Scholar]
- Eagleton, Terry. 2007. Ideology. An Introduction. New York: Verso Books. [Google Scholar]
- Frantzman, Seth J. 2019. Iran Plays Its “Palestinian Islamic Jihad” Card in Tehran Meetings. Available online: https://www.jpost.com/arab-israeli-conflict/iran-plays-its-palestinian-islamic-jihad-card-in-tehran-meetings-575989 (accessed on 16 October 2021).
- Gunning, Jeroen. 2009. Hamas in Politics: Democracy, Religion, Violence. London: Hurst & Company. [Google Scholar]
- Gupta, Dipak K., and Kusum Mundra. 2005. Suicide Bombing as a Strategic Weapon: An Empirical Investigation of Hamas and Islamic Jihad. Terrorism and Political Violence 17: 573–98. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Hamas Communique. 1992. Hadhā al-Bilāgh li-l-Nās wa li-yandhurū bihi. Available online: http://hamas.ps/ar/post/164/ (accessed on 25 June 2021).
- Hegghammer, Thomas. 2013. Jihadi-Salafis or Revolutionaries? On Religion and Politics in the Study of Militant Islamism. In Global Salafism. Islam’s New Religious Movement. Edited by Meijer Roel. Oxford: Oxford University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Hroub, Khaled. 2000. Hamas: Political Thought and Practice. Washington, DC: Institute for Palestine Studies. [Google Scholar]
- Hroub, Khaled. 2010. Introduction. In Political Islam. Context versus Ideology. Edited by Khaled Hroub. London: Saqi, pp. 9, 19. [Google Scholar]
- Kelsay, John. 2002. Civil Society and Government in Islam. In Islamic Political Ethics. Edited by Hashmi Sohail H. Oxford: Princeton University Press, pp. 3–37. [Google Scholar]
- Kimmerling, Baruch, and Joel S. Migdal. 2003. The Palestinian People. A History. Cambridge: Harvard University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Lomasky, Loren E. 2002. Classical Liberalism and Civil Society. In Alternative Conceptions of Civil Society. Edited by Chambers Simone and Will Kymlicka. Oxford: Princeton University Press, pp. 50–67. [Google Scholar]
- Mansur, Jamal. 1999. al-Taḥawwul al-dīmuqrātī al-filasṭīnī. Nablus: Markaz al-Buḥūth wa-l-Dirāsāt al-Filasṭīniyya. [Google Scholar]
- Milton-Edwards, Beverley, and Stephen Farrell. 2010. Hamas. The Islamic Resistance Movement. Cambridge: Polity Press. [Google Scholar]
- Mishal, Shaul, and Avraham Sela. 2006. The Palestinian Hamas. Vision, Violence, and Coexistence. New York: Columbia University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Pearlman, Wendy. 2009. Spoiling Inside and Out: Internal Political Contestation and the Middle East Peace Process. International Security 33: 79–109. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Rizqa, Yusuf. 2017. Al-Ruʾya al-siyāsiyya li-Ḥamās. Beirut: Markaz al-Zaytūna li-l-dirāsāt wa-l-istishārāt. [Google Scholar]
- Skare, Erik. 2021. A History of Palestinian Islamic Jihad: Faith, Awareness, and Revolution in the Middle East. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Utvik, Bjørn Olav. 2020. Islamismen, 3rd ed. Oslo: Universitetsforlaget. [Google Scholar]
- Wood, Ellen Meiksins. 2012. Liberty & Property. A Social History of Western Political Thought from Renaissance to Enlightenment. New York: Verso Books. [Google Scholar]
Publisher’s Note: MDPI stays neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations. |
© 2021 by the author. Licensee MDPI, Basel, Switzerland. This article is an open access article distributed under the terms and conditions of the Creative Commons Attribution (CC BY) license (https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/).
Share and Cite
Skare, E. Controlling the State in the Political Theory of Hamas and Palestinian Islamic Jihad. Religions 2021, 12, 1010. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel12111010
Skare E. Controlling the State in the Political Theory of Hamas and Palestinian Islamic Jihad. Religions. 2021; 12(11):1010. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel12111010
Chicago/Turabian StyleSkare, Erik. 2021. "Controlling the State in the Political Theory of Hamas and Palestinian Islamic Jihad" Religions 12, no. 11: 1010. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel12111010
APA StyleSkare, E. (2021). Controlling the State in the Political Theory of Hamas and Palestinian Islamic Jihad. Religions, 12(11), 1010. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel12111010