Let us retrace our steps. Is it possible for Spirit to appear without recourse to Being or to the Idea, outside of the Concept and of representation? Yes, if we take up an aspect that Derrida highlights in his reading of Heidegger, namely, that Spirit is the initial spark (Frühe) that precedes pneuma and spiritus. Spirit is a spark, what enflames and brings to life, what warms and emanates energy. However, it is also breath that enlivens and ensouls. Thanks to Spirit, in fact, flesh becomes animate, while without Spirit it is dead. What phenomena appear through the event of this spark or breath that animates and gives life? To avoid misunderstandings, Henry, Marion, and Chrétien will be discussed separately. I will show how with each of them, a new, non-Hegelian phenomenology of Spirit leads the appearing of phenomena back to their original source. Furthermore, I will show what Spirit adds to their phenomenologies. Spirit would be, in my view, what precedes and originates all differentiation and, as such, is the originary source that gives itself as tautology—in the sense of what reiterates itself while giving what is other than itself.
5.1. Spirit and Praxis (Michel Henry)
Henry’s phenomenology is widely known as a phenomenology of Life, not of Spirit. Of course, one could always respond that any phenomenon of Life is a manifestation of Spirit, since Spirit and Life, as we saw with Hegel, are inextricably tied. Furthermore, the characteristic that sets apart Hegelian Spirit and the Henry’s Life is the same, namely,
praxis. If, in Hegel’s
Phenomenology, Spirit appears as action and action, more specifically, as a
praxis that is able to shape things through labor,
5 then for Henry, Life itself is
praxis.
We know that
praxis is one of the Aristotelian virtues the end of which is internal to itself.
6 Praxis is productive similar to
poiesis, but the end of the former is not some external product such as an artifact—the end is
acting itself. However, what is the essence of acting? An Aristotelian would have no precise answer here because
praxis is an
ethos, a
habitus that belongs to the human being so intimately that it is nonsense to ask about its essence. Henry, on the other hand, gives an answer to this question in the works that discuss
praxis (
Marx (
Henry 1983) and
Barbarism), as well as in
I am the Truth (
Henry 2002), the first work in which he deals with Christianity. This text begins with an inquiry into the nature of truth, which Henry intends as what explains the difference between those phenomena that appear in the world and phenomena which cannot appear in the world. Life belongs among the latter. Henry writes about Life as a phenomenologist and from a phenomenological point of view, opposing world and Life and their truths. “What is true,” Henry writes, “is what shows itself…. It is this appearance as such…that constitutes the ‘truth’”(
Henry 2002, p. 12). As truth consists of “the pure fact of showing itself, or else of appearing, of manifesting itself, of revealing itself, we can just as well call truth ‘monstration’, ‘apparition’, ‘manifestation’, ‘revelation.’”(
Henry 2002, p. 12).
Henry’s thesis is thus that truth would consist in the
pure act of self-showing involved in all that appears, and the essence of truth would be the pure and simple fact of self-showing: “It is only because the pure act of appearing takes place, and that, in it, the truth deploys its essence beforehand, that everything that appears is susceptible of doing so…. Thus, any truth concerning thing—beings [
étants], as the Greeks said—any ontic truth, refers back to a pure phenomenological truth that it presupposes, refers back to the pure act of self-showing, considered in itself and as such” (
Henry 2002, p. 12). From this thesis will be born Henry’s well-known separation of world and Life, or better put, of
the truth of the world and
the truth of Life. The former then develops in itself another separation between truth and the true because it consists of a centrifugal motion, that is, of a movement of “pushing out” and exposition. Phenomena are
true to the extent that they are exposed within the horizon of the world. Otherwise stated, the world is the background starting from which “objects” are phenomenalized: “A thing exists for us only if it shows itself to us as a phenomenon. And it shows itself to us only in that primordial “outsideness” that is the world. It matters little in the end whether the truth of the world is understood through consciousness or through the world itself, if in either case what constitutes the capacity of self-showing, truth, manifestation, is “ousideness” as such” (
Henry 2002, pp. 15–16).
The world is truth as the horizon of manifestation. However, it is a horizon
extrinsic to the essence of manifestation, the ek-static “outside” within which everything appears, indifferently. It is within this indifference that the doubling of truth and the true occurs: “In the world everything and anything shows itself—children’s faces, clouds, circles—in such a way that what shows itself is never explained by the mode of revealing specific to the world…. What is true in the world’s truth in no way depends on this truth: it is not supported by it, guarded by it, loved by it, saved by it. The world’s truth—that is to say, the world itself, never contains the justification for or the reason behind what it allows to show itself in that truth and thus allows “to be”—inasmuch as to be is to be shown” (
Henry 2002, p. 16).
The truth of the world means, therefore, that truth is both the world manifesting itself and that which becomes manifest, made true by the horizon that makes possible its visibility. The true is simply what is brought to manifestation in the ek-stasis of the world, in the world as outside. Henry does not contest the world, but rather says of it that its way of phenomenalizing, which makes possible the manifesting of things simply because it acts as the outside in which everything appears indifferently, is not the only kind of phenomenality that is capable of truth. If truth is simple self-showing, and if the world is the horizon that makes possible all self-showing, then the truth of the world lies in this pure and simple coming-outside-of-itself to appear in the light of an indifferent “outside”. In order to confirm something as “true”, it suffices simply to confirm its appearing in the light of the world. To this way of construing truth Henry opposes what we can call “living the truth” or the truth of Life.
The truth of Life consists in Life’s manifestation not in the light of the world but
in itself, not in the
outside but as
self-revelation. Life is the phenomenological essence that confirms itself in its own living; it does not manifest itself but “lives itself”, it generates and reveals itself. It is originary revelation. There is no cleavage between truth and the truth here, because the truth of Life is not an “outside” indifferent to what appears (thus, it is not true simply because it appears) but it is self-manifestation in experience, in its own
épreuve. The suspicion that Henry is being tautological here is only illusory because “when it concerns the essence of Life, [self-revelation] means, on the one hand, that it is Life that achieves the revelation, that reveals—but, on the other hand, that
what Life reveals is itself” (
Henry 2002, p. 29, author’s emphasis).
Truth of the world,
truth of Life. The possessive is decisive in both kinds of truth, producing in the former a separation between truth and the true and grasping in the latter the living heart of truth itself. However, it is one and the same way of intending the truth. Truth is the essence of self-manifestation insofar as such manifestation is possible starting only from itself. The truth of the world is therefore truth in an improper sense since it only ensures itself and the appearing of the phenomenon without saying anything about the essence of manifestation as such. By contrast, Life never appears as phenomena do, but rather self-attests; it feels itself and gives itself in such self-feeling and self-experiencing. In Life, truth and the essence of manifestation coincide, and in this way, there is no
indifference between what appears and its self-manifesting. While the world is other than the phenomena that appear within it and that draw from it the possibility of their very appearing, Life is self-revelation. In actuality, it seems that we should only speak of truth in the context of Life, for if Life is manifestation grasped in its phenomenological purity, the pure essence of manifestation, then only in Life can truth and the true coincide: “What, then, is a truth that differs in no way from what is true? If truth is manifestation grasped in its phenomenological purity—phenomenality and not the phenomenon—then what is phenomenalized is phenomenality itself […]. What manifests itself is manifestation itself” (
Henry 2002, p. 25).
The world makes possible manifestation as its horizon but not as its
essence because “the phenomenalization of phenomenality is a pure phenomenological matter, a substance whose whole essence is to appear—phenomenality in its actualization and in its pure phenomenological effectivity”(
Henry 2002, p. 25). In this sense, there is truth in the world only in a secondary and improper sense, one derived from the authentic sense of truth understood as the essence of manifestation. For this reason, the world proceeds by
separating truth and the true while Life
unites them by its self-revelation. The world is not, in itself, the essence of manifestation but rather a horizon, a background that makes revelation possible but which does not reveal itself as Life can.
Once again, then, truth of the world, truth of Life: how should these two truths be understood? Is it a matter of a double truth after the model of parallel lines or of two paths born of the same origin? Henry writes that Life takes place and gives itself in the flesh, which is not a visible body that appears in the world but which is only felt. I, for instance, see and am seen as a body but I feel pleasure, pain, and so on thanks to the flesh that is not seen. A corpse, on the other hand, might have the same characteristics of a living body while not “feeling” anything. Life, therefore, manifests in the flesh that is felt as living, and the First Living is the Christ (see
Henry 2002, p. 79), in whom the Life of every living is enfleshed. However, why are body/flesh and world/Life not simply parallel and untouching manifestations, but rather the manifestation of Life that takes place through
one and the same living? What saves us here from the paradox of a duality that resides in one and the same living, as if the same body were an object on the one hand, and subjective Life on the other? To answer, it is perhaps necessary to go beyond Henry’s inconspicuous Life and flesh, and back to what comes before any distinction and division, as Derrida posited Heidegger’s
Frühe/spark as coming before the distinction between
pneuma and
spiritus. While it may be true that Henry lacks a reflection on Spirit, overcoming Henry and returning to Spirit would allow us to think adequately the origin of different manifestations, since Life manifests itself in flesh, enlivening it and “giving it spirit”. However, there is more.
If we return to Spirit, we might also be able to overcome the opposition between living flesh and the body that appears objectively in the world, for Spirit would be the origin of the two different manifestations of the same body. This would also explain why the objective body is worthy of respect both when living and when dead. Spirit is the origin which, as such, extends into all that it originates, even materiality, and renders the latter worthy of respect regardless of whether it manifests as objective body or as nature more generally. There is no world that is merely objective and material on the one hand, and Life that is worthy of respect on the other, but everything is expression of Spirit insofar as it proceeds from the same spiritual origin. In this sense, we can read the Johannine Prologue along with Henry, who comments it in various places, and say of the “Logos Egeneito”: “The Word was made flesh through the Spirit”.
Spirit, then, is not what is opposed to matter but what makes possible both the materiality of the world and the inconspicuousness of Life. It makes both of these possible if we intend it as their origin by going beyond their opposition. In this way, Life can be Spirit—not in a Hegelian sense that would bind it to the Idea, but in the sense of what enlivens, as a spark that lights a fire that moves and makes everything be what it is. Just as Derrida writes that it is spark and origin that precedes the distinction between pneuma and spiritus, Spirit is at the origin of both conspicuous and inconspicuous manifestation by preceding all materiality and “spirituality”. Spirit is such an origin because it makes things to be born and to take place, thus preceding all subsequent distinctions. As such, Spirit appears not as “something” but by means of its acting and operating, and thus Spirit is if and insofar as it operates. Now, to operate is to act, and acting is praxis. Therefore, praxis is not merely human action but is human action as the acting of Spirit. This is confirmed in the chapter of I am the Truth dedicated to the “second birth”.
Since every living being lives because of Life’s doing, Henry writes, “the relation of a living to Life cannot be broken, and cannot be undone” (
Henry 2002, p. 162). That it cannot be undone implies that the event of Life must be incessantly possible and does not represent merely the moment of biological birth. In fact, a second birth is possible that “only comes about due to a mutation within life itself” (
Henry 2002, p. 164), a self-transformation willed by the single life that leads it to its true essence, to absolute Life.
7 Henry continues: “That this transformation of life, owing nothing to world’s truth or its logos, receives its motivation from this life, that it belongs to this movement and concretely accomplishes it, determines life as an
action.
The self-transformation of life that it wills, consisting of an action and leading it back to its true essence, is the Christian ethic […]. [This] ethic presents itself from the start as a displacement from the realm of the word, meaning also of thought and knowledge, to the realm of action” (
Henry 2002, p. 165).
The action of
praxis, and of all doing, is founded in Life and in the hyper-power that it unleashes in its very acting. It is in works of mercy that the unleashing of the hyper-power of Life in action takes place, since these works are possible only by the event of “something other” in the life of each individual living. This is the sense of the Christian ethic and of the
praxis that it introduces. It shifts the emphasis from the knowledge of God to the life and action that take place because of the Life of God. This is a decisive dislocation because, firstly, the truth of the world is no longer the truth of action. Secondly, in abandoning the paradigm of representative truth (and thus also the Hegelian paradigm), Christianity “unequivocally relates Life’s truth to the process of its self-engendering, to the power of action. Finally, life is no longer about the power, the “I can” of the single ego, because all the living can act through “the process of Absolute Life’s self-engendering” (
Henry 2002, p. 166), which means doing the will of the Father. As such, “the ethic [links] the two lives, the ego’s and God’s, in such a way that it assures the former’s salvation in practice. To do the Father’s will designates the mode of life in which the Self’s life takes place, so that what is henceforth accomplished in it is Absolute Life in its essence and by its requirements” (
Henry 2002, p. 166).
“God is Life” and “access to God is access to Life itself, its self-revelation” (
Henry 2002, p. 166). These are statements of Henry’s that recur often. To clarify the essence of action, he writes that since action “consists in the application of a power”, and since such power is only exercised thanks to Life, then all power is given to itself through Life (see
Henry 2002, pp. 167–68). Salvation is not other than this access to Life, and “doing carries life as its irresistible presupposition, because there is no doing unless given to itself in life’s self-givenness, unless the work of salvation is entrusted to it” (
Henry 2002, p. 167). Not just any kind of doing, that is, but a doing that leads to Life, not to the death that derives from all doing founded on the ego and on oneself.
With the distinction between these two kinds of action, Henry establishes the birth of a
praxis that acts as mercy and as response to the kind of
praxis which, by contrast, is the action that pertains to death and self-enclosedness. Unlike this second kind of
praxis, which focuses only on the power that the ego attributes to itself, Christian action exemplified in the works of mercy is characterized by the forgetting of self. Thus, to the question of what kind of action characterizes the works of mercy, Henry answers that it is “the ego-defining power of the ‘I can.’”(
Henry 2002, p. 167). He writes that in this Ego “there is no power different from its own…except for the hyper-power of Absolute Life that gave [the ego] to itself by giving itself to itself.
“In works of mercy—and this is why they are ‘works’—a decisive transmutation takes place by which the ego’s power is extended to the hyper-power of Absolute Life in which it is given to itself.” (
Henry 2002, p. 169, author’s emphasis). In the final pages of this chapter, Henry specifies this sense of action, because in the Self, Life is in action. The true Self is not the finite self but is rather discovered in the forgetfulness of self in which alone Life’s Self takes place. Simply put, in the forgetfulness of self that removes it from its being as a worldly ego, the living discovers its Self through the Life that enlivens it. The fulfillment of this forgetfulness is the “transmutation of the I” that only the works of mercy, the work in which it acts thanks to another, can bring about. “
Only the work of mercy practices the forgetting of self in which all interest for the Self (right down to the idea of what we call a self or a me) is now removed, no obstacle is now posed to the unfurling of Life in this Self extended to its original essence”(
Henry 2002, p. 170, author’s emphasis). The exceptionality of action carried out as works of mercy is possible only because an Other (God as Life) is operative in our action, thus rendering it forgetful of self and of the belief that it owes its life only to itself: “Whether it involves nourishing those who are hungry, clothing those who are naked, caring for the sick, or another act,
the manner of acting in these various actions has ceased to concern the ego that acts or to relate to it in any fashion; a common trait equally determines them all: forgetting oneself” (
Henry 2002, p. 169). The refusal of this forgetfulness encloses the ego within itself and cuts it off from the “I can” that is the origin of the givenness of each individual life.
The source of praxis is thus Life, which leads the individual living to salvation through the forgetfulness of itself and through the rekindling of originary Life in its life. However, what brings the self to this forgetfulness? Why should the individual living turn to something other than itself? Why should it choose a different praxis that would bring it to salvation? Henry does not give answers to these questions, but nothing prohibits us from retaining the phenomenological model that he proposes (i.e., that each living is such because of Life) without opposing to one another two modes of manifestation (individual living and Life, world and Life, living flesh and objective body) and leading them back to their common root of Spirit as the Beginning-spark of all action.
In fact, the self is not a substance nor a transcendental Ego, but rather the originary acting that Spirit sparks into motion, thus making the self the “I can” of action and self-transformation. In short, Spirit makes possible the self-movement and self-transforming of the I. If the I moves toward Life, then just as we said that the Word is made flesh thanks to Spirit, we can now say that the ego is such through the Spirit that animates its action. This movement back to Spirit as the origin of the self (which, again, is absent in Henry) finally leads us beyond the Phenomenology of the Inconspicuous. This is because it shifts our thinking away from the inconspicuous toward which we are directed (Being, according to Heidegger) and toward what directs us there, i.e., the Spirit that constitutes the living self. In this sense, Spirit appears as the “soul” of praxis and action, Spirit that “is” insofar as it transforms, changes, moves, and animates the living and its praxis—the heart of the ego.
5.2. Spirit and Appel (Marion, Chrétien)
There is another phenomenon that moves beyond the phenomenology of the inconspicuous and beyond another opposition inherited from Jean-Luc Marion and Jean-Louis Chrétien. It is the double phenomenon of “call and response”.
Marion writes about
l’appel, the call or claim, already in 1989 in
Reduction and Givenness, where he proposes it as a paradigm of phenomenological reduction against Husserl’s transcendental reduction and Heidegger’s existential one.
8 While Marion borrows the idea of the call from Heidegger, who writes of the “call of Being” (
Anspruch des Seins), he thinks of the reduction itself as a call because the phenomenon appears for me as making a claim on me, as calling me (see
Marion 1998, pp. 197–98) Call and response, or better,
appel and
répons,
9 become central themes in
Being Given, especially in the well-known analysis of Caravaggio’s work
The Calling of Saint Matthew. In this painting, we do not witness Christ’s call, but we understand from Matthew’s astonished and inquiring expression that there has been a call and that Matthew is responding to it. What is more, his expression is what allows us to experience the call itself. The invisibility of the
appel manifests phenomenologically in the response: “The a priori call awaits the a posteriori of the response in order to begin to have been said and to phenomenalize itself. The response states what the call had continually recalled to it” (
Marion 2002, p. 287). The response is not only the condition of visibility, but it
makes visible the call. It is not simply the response to a call, but
the very form of the call, which appears as the response which makes the call visible in the first place, just as the responsorial belongs to the form of the psalm: “The responsal begins as soon as it has made the call phenomenalized. The call begins to appear as soon as it finds an ear in which to settle, as soon as the first ‘Here I am!’” (
Marion 2002, p. 288).
As we can see from these brief descriptions, the call is not a question that we simply hear and understand. Rather, it is only understood in the response. In and of itself, the call is inconspicuous, while what appears is the response. Nevertheless, we can pose the same challenge to this duality that we posed to Henry’s oppositions of Life and world, Life and individual living, and so on: what keeps together the terms of these oppositions? From where do these terms originate? Before giving an answer, it is necessary to lead the call back to its originary pronouncement and, in this way, to open a dialogue with Chrétien, for whom call and response take the form of the convocation or call to be.
To return to the originary pronouncement, Chrétien reaches back to the Greek term for “call” or “claim”, namely
kalein (to call or call together), which Plato’s
Cratylus joins together with
kalon, the beauty (see
Plato 1997, pp. 101–56).
Kalein, similar to the French
appeler and the Italian
chiamare, means both to give a name and to call upon. The call, which is undefinable because it does not request anything specific and does not ask for anything, nevertheless manifests itself, can appear in the
beauty to which it gives its name (
kalein/kalos).
10 “What is beautiful is what calls out by manifesting itself and manifests itself by calling out. To draw us to itself as such, to put us in motion toward it, to move us, to come and find us where we are so that we will seek it-such is beauty’s call and such is our vocation” (
Chrétien 2004, p. 9).
Beyond this etymological assonance, the call reveals the deepest sense of beauty, allowing the latter to be not seen, but heard. A phrase of Paul Claudel rings insistently like a refrain—“the eyes listen”—and conveys well the sense of beauty. “…Beauty is the very voice of things” (
Chrétien 2004, p. 35), the “visible voice” (
Chrétien 2004, p. 35) through which things “invite us to interrogate them” (
Chrétien 2004, p. 36). The eye listens to the reality that calls upon it: an intertwining of vision and hearing in which the way we encounter reality finds its voice. The beauty that calls upon, that makes an appeal, is not a beautiful
thing, but rather “beauty” is the name that Chrétien gives to reality’s capacity to call upon us. It is due to this capacity that the method of knowledge by which we know is first of all the encounter with reality and with things. We are attracted to know things by the things themselves. The relationship with reality is therefore not a relation to objects, but a bond to which we are called. Reality calls upon us; this is beauty.
In order to clarify further the way in which he understands beauty, Chrétien cites a passage from the
Sermons on the Song of Songs by Bernard of Clairvaux, where the beauty of Christ is invisible to the eye and revealed by faith: “The words he speaks are ‘spirit and life’; the form we see is mortal, subject to death. We see one thing and we believe another. Our senses tell us he is black, our faith declares him fair and beautiful […]. Black in the opinion of Herod, beautiful in the testimony of the penitent thief, in the faith of the centurion” (
Chrétien 2013, p. 105). Beauty is reality according to its true sense and is not revealed only to the exceptional or to mystics. The sense and the truth of things becomes manifest through their call to listen, asking us to go beyond our vision and toward an infinite relation of hearing, to experience them as exceeding our sight. The real lets itself be known by attracting and calling upon us, according to its own truth, but—and here we find the antiphonary form of this relation—this call can be recognized and welcomed as such only “in our unavoidably belated response” (
Chrétien 2004, p. 44).
The response is the way in which this silent call is revealed as such, as a call that calls upon. This call does not ask anything; it is a pure and simple call to the true sense of things. I can recognize beauty as a call “only if I respond in fear, in admiration, in bewilderment”; I recognize the call of the
Logos “when I respond to it with thoughts and words” (
Chrétien 2007, p. 15). Thought, or philosophy, is the response in which the truth that calls upon us reveals itself. However, what is it that appears when we answer to the call? In response to this question, Chrétien cites Saint Paul’s
Letter to the Romans: “Abraham…is the father of all of us…in the presence of the God in whom he believed, who gives life to the dead and
calls into existence the things that do not exist”.
11Chrétien comments on these verses extensively, as he finds them to be the clearest expression of how things come to be what they are. Everything, including the human itself, is called upon to be, and to exist is to respond to this call that reveals and manifests itself
in the response that existing itself is. The beauty that calls upon is first and foremost God, who is beautiful because he calls things into existence. Following Pseudo-Dionysus on the common root of “to call” and “beauty”, Chrétien comments that “the God of [Dionysus’] meditation and invocation is… superessential beauty,
huperousion kalon, beyond being, who “in the manner of light, causes the beauty-producing communications of his initial ray to shine in all things. He calls
(kaloun) all things to himself, and this is why he is called
kallos, beauty” (
Chrétien 2004, p. 15). A beauty which, in God,
is converted into Goodness: “Springing into being, we answer…. It is no longer only the beautiful, but also now the good that
originates in a call” (
Chrétien 2004, p. 17, author’s emphasis).
Thus, God “called all things from non-being into being when he spoke and they were made” (
Chrétien 2004, p. 17). We can come thus far with Chrétien, who maintains the duality of the inconspicuous call and the conspicuous response. However,
how does God call? To this, Chrétien does not give an answer, but nothing keeps us from answering that God calls as Spirit. In fact, there are not many alternatives to this answer: either the call takes place as a “voice” that we hear, or as an urge and solicitation to act. The latter fits the model that Chrétien introduces, since for him the call leads us to be, to be born, to live. To respond to the call is to live.
For Marion as for Chrétien, the response reveals that the call took place. Yet before the response, the call gives itself as a call to movement and to action. Before the response, the call gives itself and nothing prohibits us from understanding its origin as Spirit taking the form of a “call to Life”. In this way, Spirit has its place at the origin prior to the distinction between call and response (or responsal), taking place as the origin from which the two terms must separate themselves in order to come to manifestation.
Once again, Spirit takes place as the possibility of Life, be this the Life described by Henry as the possibility of all living or the Life that is called to being by an inconspicuous origin. Spirit is the breath that precedes all distinctions and duality, the origin that gives origin to them.