Does the Analogy of an Ideal State Disprove God’s Existence? James Sterba’s Argument and a Thomistic Response
Abstract
:1. Introduction
2. The Problem of Horrendous Evils Briefly Explained
- God exists and is omnipotent, omniscient, and perfectly good,and
- Evil exists” (Adams 1999, p. 8).
3. Sterba’s Argument and the Analogy of an Ideal State
3.1. Concept of Freedom
3.2. Argument from Rights and Moral Preference
- MEPR-I: “Prevent, rather than permit, significant and especially horrendous evil consequences of immoral actions without violating anyone’s rights (a good to which we have a right), as needed, when that can be easily done” (Sterba 2019, p. 184).
- MEPR-II: “Do not permit significant and especially horrendous evil consequences of immoral actions simply to provide other rational beings with goods they would morally prefer not to have” (Sterba 2019, p. 184).
- MEPR-III: “Do not permit, rather than prevent, significant and especially horrendous evil consequences of immoral actions on would-be victims (which would violate their rights) in order to provide them with goods to which they do not have a right, when there are countless morally unobjectionable ways of providing these goods” (Sterba 2019, p. 184).
3.3. Ideal State
3.4. Final Logical Argument from Horrendous Evils
- (I): There is an all-good, all-powerful God.
- (II): If there is an all-good, all-powerful God, then necessarily he would be adhering to MEPR I–III.
- (III): If God were adhering to MEPR I–III, then necessarily significant and especially horrendous evil consequences of immoral actions would not be obtained through what would have to be his permission.
- (IV): Significant and especially horrendous evil consequences of immoral actions do obtain all around us.
- Conclusion (C): Therefore, it is not the case that there is an all-good, all-powerful God. (See Sterba 2019, pp. 189–90)
4. Further Analysis: Divine Goodness
- (D): God is good if and only if he acts like an ideal state = insofar as he prevents and does not permit horrendous (moral) evil consequences.
5. Divine Goodness according to Thomas Aquinas
“… (he) begins with Aristotle’s definition: something is “good” insofar as it is “desirable” (appetible). In a first step, Aquinas concludes (1) that every being desires its perfection, (2) that this perfection or form is a similitude of the agent that causes perfection by actualizing a thing’s form, and (3) that therefore the agent cause itself must be something desirable and therefore good as stated in the previous definition. The second premise follows from the axiom that any agent acts or produces something similar to itself. If God is the first efficient cause of all things (as demonstrated in ST I q.2), then the final conclusion follows: God is something desirable, that is, “good””.
- (a): God is perfectly good, the goodness itself; his perfection and goodness are essential; and he cannot improve the goodness he himself is because it would contradict the perfection, he himself is.
- (b): God is the perfect moral agent in the sense that he desires (1) his own perfection, which is goodness itself, (2) he desires it in the perfect way, and (3) he never fails in acting in accordance with his nature which is summum bonum.
- (c): God is not a moral agent like humans because (1) he cannot fail in doing good, and (2) he does not fall upon any moral obligation because he is the eternal law himself.
- (d): the notion of the goodness of God is taken from an analogy that is not anthropomorphic because it starts with what God is not (and he is not a metaphysical composite, he is not physical).
6. Comparison of Sterba’s and Thomistic Notion of Divine Goodness
- An ideal state needs to do good in order to be good, but God is goodness itself.
- An ideal state’s goodness is accidental because even an ideal state has at least a logical possibility to act wrongly, but God’s goodness is essential, and he cannot do evil.
- An ideal state is not the source of goodness, but God is.
- God is not morally obliged to do anything because he is goodness itself, the eternal law, and is not subordinated to anyone or anything; however, an ideal state would still be subject to moral obligations and international law.
- Even in an ideal state, morals and laws are distinct, but in God, they are the same because there is no distinction in God.
- An ideal state is established by people, somehow “created” and “run” by people; these people as individuals do not need to be morally good or perfect; and these individuals are not the state itself. However, God is uncreated; there is no metaphysical distinction in him; and he does not have parts that are either good or not good; he is the goodness himself.
7. The Permission of Horrendous Evils
- Premise II presupposes that God has moral obligations, which has been shown not to be the case in (c).
- Premise III presupposes that God is a moral agent like us because, according to Sterba, God is good if and only if he acts like an ideal state. This has been shown not to be the case in (a), (b), and (c).
- Premise IV presupposes that evil in the world is God’s fault, which has been shown not to be the case in (a), (b), and (c).
- Therefore, it is not the case that V (C) is valid.
8. Some Final Considerations
9. Final Argument
- Sterba claims that the God of theism does not exist because, if he existed, he would have acted as an ideal state.
- Acting as an ideal state is to fulfill moral obligations (MEPR I–III), which means to prevent and not permit horrendous evil consequences.
- However, God is not a moral agent like us. He is the perfect moral agent, which means that he is summum bonum and lex aeterna, the source of every moral obligation and the ultimate performer of the good according to his nature.
- God performs the good on the metaphysical level as the first cause of every good and it makes him essentially different from an ideal state.
- There is no possibility that God would perform evil essentially by not preventing and permitting horrendous evil consequences.
- God’s permission and not prevention of horrendous evil consequences do not happen on the essential level of his divinity.
- Because God is absolutely good, he does not in any sense violate MEPR I–III. Also, there is no point in asking whether he should logically adhere to these because (1) he is the source of morality and (2) MEPR I–III are based on human moral preference.
- Conclusion: God’s permission of horrendous evil consequences does not happen essentially. God does not have any accidental properties and that is why the permission of evil cannot be ascribed to him essentially. God is essentially good and wills good only. Unlike an ideal state, God performs good essentially (perfectly), which does not make him a moral agent like humans. The results of the analogy of an ideal state do not apply to the all-good God of theism, because the analogy is too anthropomorphic. It relies on an idealized physical approach of God. Furthermore, the analogy of an ideal state is non in accordance with some basic theistic beliefs. As a result, it is not a case that the analogy of an ideal state disproves the metaphysical existence of the all-good God of theism.
10. Conclusions
Funding
Acknowledgments
Conflicts of Interest
1 | Authors use either singular or plural form depending on the meaning. The plural form is usually used when speaking of the amount, degrees, and types of pointless and gratuitous evil or its horrendous consequences, e.g., assault and rape are two different horrendous evils, even though they can be metaphysically conceived together as horrendous evil. I will refer to evil, or evils depending on the meaning. |
2 | (Sterba 2019, p. 11). “Never do evil that good may come from it”. Sterba takes this statement from the Bible, Letter to Romans 3:8. |
3 | By theism, Sterba means traditional theism, where, according to Sterba, an all-good, all-powerful God is understood in a more anthropomorphic way; he can act either morally right or wrong and is subject to moral obligations cf. (Sterba 2019, p. 150). Another version of theism is classical where God is understood more as a personal or impersonal first metaphysical cause and the principle of all the created being; he is eternal and cannot change over time, cf. (Rojka 2018, pp. 34, 37). For the importance of an eternal God for the consistency of theism, cf. (Volek 2017, 2018). For another view on the eternity of God, where he is understood as eternal before creation and temporal after creation, cf. (Craig 2001). For a more general approach to theism, cf. (Swinburne 2004, pp. 1–2, 93–96). Sterba argues against classical theism as well (e.g., against Brian Davies), cf. (Sterba 2019, pp. 110–39). In my argument, I will use the classical theist (Thomistic) position in a more moderate form (God as the perfect moral agent). |
4 | (Sterba 2019, p. 6). Hereafter, I will use “ideal state” instead of “ideally just and political state”. |
5 | Cf. (Spišiaková 2012, p. 81). Logical arguments from evil have a similar structure as those arguments that try to prove the consistency of the theistic statements about God and evil. Logical arguments from evil look for a proposition q which is necessarily true and its conjunction with some theistic proposition is a contradiction. The arguments in favor of theism look for a proposition p that is consistent with the statement “God exists” and its conjunction with this statement is consistent with the statement that “Evil exists”. |
6 | Cf. (Schmidt 2008, pp. 356–61). Why is there evil in the world if God exists? |
7 | For more, cf. (Calder 2018). The first one to make a distinction between theodicy and defense was Plantinga. A theodicy tries to explain the place of evil in a world made by God, while a defense tries to show that evil does not disprove the existence of God (See Davies 2011, p. 3). My argument is both a theodicy and a defense. |
8 | I will use “privation” instead of “absence”. Absence is tied up with degrees of the being—e.g., a dog cannot fly. It is, however, a positive absence because it positively determines the essence of the being (a dog is not a flying object like a bird). The term “privation” conveys that evil is some lack of the perfection that a specific being should have according to their essence (See Chignell 2021). Therefore, I will refer to evil as privation. Please note that some authors refer to evil as absence by technically meaning privation, e.g., cf. (Davies 2011, pp. 33–37). |
9 | Scholars debate whether we should refer to God in the masculine, cf. (Radford Ruether 2007). I will refer to God in the masculine for the reason of simplification. |
10 | This “privation theory of evil” was brought about by Neoplatonists and later by Augustine. Thomas Aquinas defines evil as some sort of negation in substance (See Davies 2016, pp. 202–8). |
11 | Here they do not speak of evil as absence but as horrendous consequences of evil/immoral actions. |
12 | (Sterba 2019, pp. 26, 147). Soul-making is the capacity of developing one’s personality and morality. Soul-making theodicy holds that evil is a necessary condition for one’s personal and moral growth, cf. (Spišiaková 2012, pp. 118–25). |
13 | (Van der Vossen 2019). Negative freedom or liberty is the absence of obstacles, barriers, or constraints. Positive freedom is the presence of control on the part of the agent, cf. (Carter 2021). |
14 | For Sterba’s approach on soul-making, cf. (Sterba 2019, pp. 35–45), and on redemptive suffering, cf. (Sterba 2019, pp. 141–53). |
15 | Sterba uses this argument from moral preference on various pages, e.g., cf. (Sterba 2019, p. 184). It is also included in MEPR I–III. |
16 | Cf. (Sterba 2019, p. 51). It is hard to say whether some evil can be “more” or “less” evil; it is simply “evil”. What Sterba means is that there are certain evils that do not have horrendous consequences. Hereafter, I will use “lesser evils” for such a category, having in mind that evil as a metaphysical privation of goodness does not have an amount. |
17 | Cf. (Rojka 2018, pp. 32–39, 121–22). There are different theistic notions of the person. Here I refer to the notion of person that is brought about by some contemporary theists such as Rojka, Swinburne, Plantinga, or Lucas. Their notion of person is different from the classical theistic notion of person. |
18 | See (Davies 2011, p. 114) For more, cf. (Davies 2002, p. 228). |
19 | More precisely, our intellect cannot “see” the essence of God like God “sees” it, because our intellect is not sufficient to essentially understand something that is more intelligible than us, cf. (Aquinas 1948a, I q. 12). The names that our language attributes to God (1) represent his essence but (2) imperfectly—which does not mean that God himself is imperfect, cf. (Aquinas 1948a, I q. 13 a. 1). |
20 | Aquinas holds that in God, there is no composition of (1) substance and accidents, (2) existence and essence, (3) matter and form, and therefore (4) he is pure actuality. These are the basic premises of the doctrine of divine simplicity. God is absolutely simple which means that there is no metaphysical composition in him. By examining what God is not, Aquinas finds a proper way of speaking of God. Cf. (Davies 2002; Aquinas 1948a, I q. 3). |
21 | Cf. (Davies 2002, p. 231). “New York is a city“ and “Paris is a city“ give us univocal uses of “city“ and both statements are literally true. “Baseball players use bats“ and “Bats have wings“ give us equivocal uses of “bats“ and both statements are literally true. “I have a good computer“ and “God is good“ give us analogical uses of “good“ and both are literally true. |
22 | There are three steps in Aquinas’s notion of analogy: (1) via positiva—God is good, (2) via negativa—God is not good like us, (3) via eminentiae—God is the perfect goodness, the goodness itself, cf. (Rojka 2018, pp. 34–35; Aquinas 1948a, I q. 13). |
23 | In his article, Edward Feser agrees with Brian Davies that there is a very different and excessively anthropomorphic conception of God in the recent philosophy of religion, especially linked to the problem of evil. Feser uses the Thomistic concept, but not only. The Thomistic concept, however, is a very important part of the “mainstream” theistic position cf. (Feser 2021, p. 2). This mainstream position can be considered as opposite of anthropomorphic. |
24 | By “better” I mean less anthropomorphic, according to Wildman’s criteria, cf. (Diller 2021; Wildman 2017). |
25 | Cf. (Sterba 2019, pp. 134–35). Sterba argues against the Thomistic interpretation of divine goodness represented by Brian Davies. |
26 | Cf. (Aquinas 2017, p. 45). Aquinas does not think that evil is not real. Evil is a real privation, cf. (Davies 2011, p. 115). |
27 | Cf. (Aquinas 2017, pp. 45–46). Aquinas deals with the problem in a way that evil is privation of some good that is causally connected to God. He solves it by stating that these evil effects are tied to God’s causation only accidentally. |
28 | Cf. (Stump 2003, pp. 109–15). When speaking about various essential properties of God, Stump uses the terminology of Frege. Various properties are like various non-synonymous expressions of one thing they are referred to, such as “the morning star” and “the evening star”, cf. (Stump 2003, p. 100). |
References
- Adams, Marilyn M. 1999. Horrendous Evils and the Goodness of God. New York: Cornell University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Adams, Marilyn M. 2007. Horrendous Evils and the Goodness of God. In Philosophy of Religion: Selected Readings, 3rd ed. Edited by Michael Peterson, William Hasker, Bruce Reichenbach and David Basinger. New York: Oxford University Press, pp. 365–77. [Google Scholar]
- Aquinas, Thomas. 1948a. Summa theologiae, cura et studio Sac. Petri Caramello, cum textu ex recensione Leonina, Prima pars. Turin: Marietti. [Google Scholar]
- Aquinas, Thomas. 1948b. Summa theologiae, De Rubeis, Billuart, P. Fauchter O. P., cum textu ex recensione Leonina, Pars Prima Secundae. Turin: Marietti. [Google Scholar]
- Aquinas, Thomas. 2017. No Evil Comes from God. In The Problem of Evil, 2nd ed. Edited by Michael Peterson. Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press, pp. 42–49. [Google Scholar]
- Beaty, Michael Douglas. 2021. A Compensatory Response to the Problem of Evil. Religions 12: 347. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Betenson, Toby. 2021. The Problem of Evil Remains Logically Binding. Religions 12: 154. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Calder, Todd. 2018. The Concept of Evil, rev. ed. Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. August 21. Available online: https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/concept-evil (accessed on 27 May 2022).
- Carter, Ian. 2021. Positive and Negative Liberty, rev. ed. Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. November 19. Available online: https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/liberty-positive-negative (accessed on 27 May 2022).
- Chignell, Andrew. 2021. Kinds and Origins of Evil. Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. December 10. Available online: https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/evil-kinds-origins (accessed on 27 May 2022).
- Craig, William Lane. 2001. Time and Eternity: Exploring God’s Relationship to Time. Wheaton: Crossway Books. [Google Scholar]
- Davies, Brian. 2002. Aquinas on What God is not. In Thomas Aquinas: Contemporary Philosophical Perspectives. Edited by Brian Davies. Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 227–42. [Google Scholar]
- Davies, Brian. 2011. Thomas Aquinas on God and Evil. Oxford: Oxford University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Davies, Brian. 2014. Thomas Aquinas’s Summa Theologiae: A Guide and Commentary. New York: Oxford University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Davies, Brian. 2016. Thomas Aquinas’s Summa Contra Gentiles: A Guide and Commentary. New York: Oxford University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Diller, Jeanine. 2021. God and Other Ultimates. Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Available online: https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/god-ultimates (accessed on 27 May 2022).
- Feser, Edward. 2021. The Thomistic Dissolution of the Logical Problem of Evil. Religions 12: 268. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Honnefelder, Ludger. 2012. God’s Goodness. In The Oxford Handbook of Aquinas. Edited by Brian Davies and Eleonore Stump. New York: Oxford University Press, pp. 147–57. [Google Scholar]
- Huffling, Joseph Brian. 2021. Is God Morally Obligated to Prevent Evil? A Response to James Sterba. Religions 12: 312. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Radford Ruether, Rosemary. 2007. Sexism and God-Talk. In Philosophy of Religion: Selected Readings, 3rd ed. Edited by Michael Peterson, William Hasker, Bruce Reichenbach and David Basinger. New York: Oxford University Press, pp. 441–46. [Google Scholar]
- Rojka, Ľuboš. 2018. Kto je Boh? Pojem Boha v súčasnej analytickej filozofii. Trnava: Dobrá Kniha. [Google Scholar]
- Schmidt, Josef. 2008. Filozofická teológia. Translated by Rastislav Nemec. Bratislava: Serafín. [Google Scholar]
- Spišiaková, Mária. 2012. Zlo v Božom stvorení. Riešenie problému zla v analytickej filozofii náboženstva. Warsaw: Rhetos. [Google Scholar]
- Sterba, James P. 2019. Is a Good God Logically Possible? Cham: Palgrave Macmillan. [Google Scholar]
- Sterba, James P. 2021. Sixteen Contributors: A Response. Religions 12: 536. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Stump, Eleonore. 2003. Aquinas. London: Routledge. [Google Scholar]
- Swinburne, Richard. 2004. The Existence of God, 2nd ed. Oxford: Clarendon Press. [Google Scholar]
- Van der Vossen, Bas. 2019. Libertarianism, rev. ed. Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. January 28. Available online: https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/libertarianism (accessed on 27 May 2022).
- Vitale, Vince R. 2020. Non-Identity Theodicy: A Grace-Based Response to the Problem of Evil. Oxford: Oxford University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Volek, Peter. 2017. Justification of God’s Timelessness. Studia Aloisiana 8: 5–17. Available online: https://www.academia.edu/35782418/Opodstatnenos%C5%A5_bez%C4%8Dasov%C3%A9ho_ch%C3%A1pania_Boha_pdf (accessed on 27 May 2022).
- Volek, Peter. 2018. How is it Possible the Understanding of Timeless God. Studia Aloisiana 9: 39–50. Available online: https://www.academia.edu/37674861/Ako_mo%C5%BEno_ch%C3%A1pa%C5%A5_bez%C4%8Dasov%C3%A9ho_Boha (accessed on 8 June 2022).
- Wildman, Wesley J. 2017. In Our Own Image: Anthropomorphism, Apophaticism, and Ultimacy. Oxford: Oxford University Press. [Google Scholar]
Publisher’s Note: MDPI stays neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations. |
© 2022 by the author. Licensee MDPI, Basel, Switzerland. This article is an open access article distributed under the terms and conditions of the Creative Commons Attribution (CC BY) license (https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/).
Share and Cite
Hrmo, P. Does the Analogy of an Ideal State Disprove God’s Existence? James Sterba’s Argument and a Thomistic Response. Religions 2022, 13, 931. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel13100931
Hrmo P. Does the Analogy of an Ideal State Disprove God’s Existence? James Sterba’s Argument and a Thomistic Response. Religions. 2022; 13(10):931. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel13100931
Chicago/Turabian StyleHrmo, Patrik. 2022. "Does the Analogy of an Ideal State Disprove God’s Existence? James Sterba’s Argument and a Thomistic Response" Religions 13, no. 10: 931. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel13100931
APA StyleHrmo, P. (2022). Does the Analogy of an Ideal State Disprove God’s Existence? James Sterba’s Argument and a Thomistic Response. Religions, 13(10), 931. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel13100931