From Theism to Spirit Beliefs
Abstract
:1. Introduction
2. Defining Non-Theistic Supernatural Agents
2.1. Agent
2.2. Supernatural
- (i)
- Non-physical;
- (ii)
- Capable of being invisible;
- (iii)
- Able to exist outside of space and time.
2.3. Non-Theistic
- Less elevated status;
- Less powerful. and
- Not creator.
3. The Initial Outlook: Arguing for God Alone
4. From Theism to Spirit Beliefs
- An omnibenevolent God wants to make himself known through messengers.
- The existence of NTSAs is more likely if there is a supernatural realm.
- The existence of NTSAs is more probable if sacred scriptures are reliable.
4.1. The Existence of NTSAs Is More Likely If There Is a Supernatural Realm
4.2. An Omnibenevolent God Wants to Make Himself Known through Messengers
- The most elevated beings are too far removed from the human sphere to interact with humans.
- The most elevated beings are moved by human pleas.
You have, then, in the meantime, two kinds of animated beings, Gods entirely differing from men, in the sublimity of their abode, in the eternity of their existence, in the perfection of their nature, and having no proximate communication with them; since those that are supreme are separated from the lowest habitations by such a vast interval of distance; and life is there eternal and never-failing, but here decaying and interrupted, and the natures are there sublimated to beatitude, while those below are depressed to wretchedness. What then? Has nature connected itself by no bond, but allowed itself to be separated into the divine and human parts, and to be thus split and crippled, as it were? For, as the same Plato remarks, “No God mingles with men.” But this is the principal mark of their sublime nature, that they are not contaminated by any contact with us.
No God, you say, interferes in human affairs. To whom, then, shall I address my prayers? To whom shall I make my vows? To whom shall I immolate victims? Whom shall I invoke throughout my whole life, as the helper of the unfortunate, the favorer of the good, and the adversary of the wicked? And whom, in fine, (a thing for which necessity most frequently occurs) shall I adduce as a witness to my oath?
4.3. The Existence of NTSAs Is More Probable If Sacred Scriptures Are Reliable
- P(RST|God) > P(RST|~ God)
- P(NTSA|RST) > P(NTSA|~ RST)
- P(NTSA|God) > P(NTSA|~ God)
5. Concluding Remarks
Funding
Data Availability Statement
Conflicts of Interest
1 | I thank three anonymous reviewers for exceptionally helpful comments on earlier drafts. |
2 | |
3 | As noted by an anonymous reviewer, this does not hold for non-theistic religions such as some forms of animism and Theravada Buddhism. |
4 | Although this account of agency is dominant, alternative accounts have been defended (see (Schlosser 2015) for an overview). Discussing these in detail lies beyond the scope of this chapter. The same holds for account of what counts as a ‘reason’. For an overview of the discussion on ‘reason’, see: (Alvarez 2016). |
5 | The discussion on defining ‘supernatural’ is drawn from (Van Eyghen 2018). |
6 | This also holds for views on God. Adherents of the Church of Latter Day Saints tend to believe that God is a material being. Most adherents of Christianity believe that God took on human flesh when incarnated as Jesus of Nazareth. In both examples, God cannot be regarded as non-physical. |
7 | See, for example, Luke 1: 26–28, Exodus 23: 20–23. |
8 | I thank an anonymous reviewer for this suggestion. |
9 | E.g., Hebrews 11: 1. I noted above that a large number of Christians believe that God became visible when incarnated in Jesus of Nazareth. This, however, attests to the claim that the Christian God has the capacity to remain invisible even though he showed himself at some times. |
10 | Perfect being theology has its roots in the works of the 12th-century philosopher Anselm of Canterbury. |
11 | For an in-depth discussion, see: (Peterson et al. 2008, chp. 4). |
12 | Some authors distinguish the Christian God from ‘limited deities’ (Baker-Hytch 2018). |
13 | For a discussion of Barth’s view on divine attributes, see: (Titus 2010). |
14 | For a critique of this view, see: (Stump 2018). |
15 | It seems logically possible that there be two or more beings that are equally perfect, sharing omniscience, omnibenevolence, and other perfections. |
16 | A majority of religious traditions only appear to accept one god and regard all other supernatural agents as inferior. A few notable exceptions are Hinduism and ancient polytheisms. Hinduism, however, also accepts one primordial supernatural agent called Brahman, which is the source of everything (see below). |
17 | Some argue that (most) Hindus are monotheistic. Ian Kesarcodi-Watson notes that Hindus commonly accept that Brahman is the supreme being manifested in personalized form as Isvara (Kesarcodi-Watson 1976). |
18 | See, for example, (Dasa 2012). |
19 | See: 2 Corinthians 4.4. |
20 | For overviews, see: (Craig and Moreland 2009; Manning et al. 2013). |
21 | There is a subtle difference between being a designer and a creator. Concluding to a designer merely concludes to a being that brought order to the universe. The designer could have operated on pre-existing material or chaos. Concluding to a creator usually means that the creator was the cause or origin of the universe. In most discussions, however, the distinction between designer and creator is not drawn sharply. |
22 | As an anonymous reviewer noted, a similar argument can be made relying on pantheism. Establishing the (likely) truth of pantheism would also imply the denial of naturalism and leave more room for NTSAs. |
23 | Adherents of naturalism usually also deny the existence of other entities or things besides supernatural agents. They also deny the existence of supernatural forces such as karma or Dao and immaterial souls. |
24 | Epistemic defeaters are distinguished by rebutting and undercutting defeaters (cf. Pollock 1986). Learning of an argument for naturalism provides evidence for a proposition opposed to the existence of NTSAs and therefore constitutes a rebutting defeater. |
25 | I thank an anonymous reviewer for this suggestion. |
26 | Apuleius appears to use the term ‘god’ as interchangeable with ‘supernatural agent’. |
27 | This is less clear for the practice of making offerings. However, making offerings is a way of showing reverence or respect and addressing the gods in this regard. Therefore, subjects who make offerings are also addressing the gods in some respect and therefore also communicating with the gods. |
28 | Apuleius calls these intermediary beings ‘daemons’. As Benjamin McCraw and Robert Arp note, the term ‘daemon’ did not have an intrinsic connection to evil according to the ancient Greeks (McCraw and Arp 2017). |
29 | The monotheistic worldview discussed in the remainder of this section is common among adherents of Abrahamic faiths. Most of the examples are drawn from these faiths. |
30 | See, for example, Matthew 7: 8, Job 22: 27. |
31 | See, for example, Genesis 16: 7–14, Numbers 20: 16. |
32 | See: Luke 1: 26–28. |
33 | An anonymous reviewer argued that using messengers to avoid inducing fear foregoes the fact that some intermediary beings, such as demons or fallen angels, induce a lot of fear in humans. While some NTSAs can surely induce fear, a defender could respond that this was never the intention of an omnibenevolent God. NTSAs causing fear may be the result of God allowing NTSAs freedom, or they may have some other purpose. |
34 | Peter Williams made a similar argument in favor of the existence of angels. He argues that the authority of Jesus and the Bible provide positive reasons to accept the existence of angels (Williams 2006). Unlike the argument defended here, his argument relies on the faith-based authority of the Christian Bible. |
35 | See, for example, Sura 72. |
36 | E.g., Ramayana. Book 3, chp. 31. |
37 | The last two examples may be problematic, as not all strands of Shinto and Buddhism have clear beliefs in God. It is also not clear whether both can be regarded as reports of revelations. |
38 | Bultmann defended his claim as applied to the Bible. The idea can, however, be expanded to other sacred scriptures as well. |
References
- Alvarez, Maria. 2016. Reasons for Action: Justification, Motivation, Explanation. In The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Edited by Edward Zalta. Available online: https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/reasons-just-vs-expl/ (accessed on 24 April 2022).
- Apuleius. 2001. On the God of Socrates. Available online: https://trisagionseraph.tripod.com/Texts/Daemon.html (accessed on 15 January 2022).
- Baker-Hytch, Max. 2018. Testimony amidst Diversity. In Knowledge, Belief, and God: New Insights in Religious Epistemology. Edited by Matthew Benton, John Hawthorne and Dani Rabinowitz. Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 183–202. [Google Scholar]
- Bewaji, John AI. 1998. Olodumare: God in Yoruba Belief and the Theistic Problem of Evil. African Studies Quarterly 2: 1–17. [Google Scholar]
- Boudry, Maarten, Stefaan Blancke, and Johan Braeckman. 2010. How Not to Attack Intelligent Design Creationism: Philosophical Misconceptions About Methodological Naturalism. Foundations of Science 15: 227–44. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
- Braude, Stephen E. 2003. Immortal Remains: The Evidence for Life after Death. Lanham: Rowman & Littlefield Publishers. [Google Scholar]
- Bultmann, Rudolf. 1984. New Testament and Mythology and Other Basic Writings. Translated by Schubert M. Ogden. Philadelphia: Fortress. [Google Scholar]
- Collins, Robin. 2003. Evidence for Fine-Tuning. In God and Design: The Teleological Argument and Modern Science. Edited by Neil A. Manson. London and New York: Routledge, pp. 80–178. [Google Scholar]
- Craig, William Lane, and James Porter Moreland. 2009. The Blackwell Companion to Natural Theology. Companion to Natural Theology. Malden: Wiley-Blackwell. [Google Scholar]
- d’Costa, Gavin. 1996. The Impossibility of a Pluralist View of Religions. Religious Studies 32: 223–32. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Dasa, Pandit. 2012. The 33 Million Gods of Hinduism. Huffington Post. June 8. Available online: https://www.huffpost.com/entry/the-33-million-demigods-o_b_1737207 (accessed on 5 February 2022).
- Douven, Igor. 2011. Peirce on Abduction. In The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Edited by Edward Zalta. Available online: https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/abduction/ (accessed on 25 January 2022).
- Fossum, Jarl. 2005. The Origin of the Gnostic Concept of the Demiurge. Ephemerides Theologicae Lovanienses 61: 142–52. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Guthrie, Shandon L. 2017. Christian Demonology. In Philosophical Approaches to Demonology. Edited by Benjamin W. McCraw and Robert Arp. New York and London: Routledge. [Google Scholar]
- Guthrie, Shandon L. 2018. Gods of This World: A Philosophical Discussion and Defense of Christian Demonology. Eugene Oregon: Wipf and Stock Publishers. [Google Scholar]
- Heiser, Michael S. 2015. The Unseen Realm: Recovering the Supernatural Worldview of the Bible. Eugene: Lexham Press. [Google Scholar]
- Hick, John. 1997. The Epistemological Challenge of Religius Pluralism. Faith and Philosophy 14: 277–86. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
- Hume, David. 1970. Dialogues Concerning Natural Religion. Edited by Nelson Pike. Indianopolis: Bobbs-Merrill. [Google Scholar]
- Johnson, David Kyle. 2017. Justified Belief in the Existence of Demons Is Impossible. In Philosophical Approaches to Demonology. Edited by Benjamin W. McCraw and Robert Arp. New York and London: Routledge. [Google Scholar]
- Kesarcodi-Watson, Ian. 1976. Devas. Religious Studies 12: 467–72. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Lane, Nick. 2015. The Unseen World: Reflections on Leeuwenhoek (1677) ‘Concerning Little Animals’. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society B: Biological Sciences 370: 20140344. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed]
- Lund, David H. 2009. Persons, Souls, and Death: A Philosophical Investigation of an Afterlife. Ashe County: McFarland & Company. [Google Scholar]
- Malcolm, Norman. 1960. Anselm’s Ontological Arguments. The Philosophical Review 69: 41–62. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Manning, Russell Re, John Hedley Brooke, and Fraser Watts. 2013. The Oxford Handbook of Natural Theology. Oxford: Oxford University Press. [Google Scholar]
- McCall, Thomas. 2009. On Understanding Scripture as the Word of God. In Analytic Theology: New Essays in the Philosophy of Theology. Oxford: Oxford Up. [Google Scholar]
- McCraw, Benjamin W. 2017. Augustine and Aquinas on the Demonic. In Philosophical Approaches to Demonology. Edited by Benjamin W. McCraw and Robert Arp. New York and London: Routledge. [Google Scholar]
- McCraw, Benjamin W., and Robert Arp. 2017. Introduction. In Philosophical Approaches to Demonology. Edited by Benjamin W. McCraw and Robert Arp. New York and London: Routledge. [Google Scholar]
- McGrath, Alister E. 2009. A Fine-Tuned Universe: The Quest For God in Science and Theology. Gifford Lectures 2009. Louisville: Westminster/John Knox Press. [Google Scholar]
- Miller, Tracy. 2008. US Religious Landscape Survey Religious Beliefs and Practices: Diverse and Politically Relevant. Available online: https://www.pewresearch.org/religion/2008/06/01/u-s-religious-landscape-survey-religious-beliefs-and-practices/ (accessed on 14 April 2022).
- Moad, Edward. 2017. The Jinn and the Shaytan. In Philosophical Approaches to Demonology. Edited by Benjamin W. McCraw and Robert Arp. New York and London: Routledge. [Google Scholar]
- Mortley, Raoul. 1972. Apuleius and Platonic Theology. The American Journal of Philology 93: 584–90. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Oppy, Graham. 2020. Naturalism. Think 19: 7–20. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Papineau, David. 2009. The Causal Closure of the Physical and Naturalism. In The Oxford Handbook of Philosophy of Mind. Edited by Brian McLaughlin, Ansgar Beckermann and Sven Walter. Oxford: Oxford University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Peterson, Michael, William Hasker, Bruce Reichenbach, and David Basinger. 2008. Reason and Religious Belief: An Introduction to the Philosophy of Religion. New York: Oxford University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Plantinga, Alvin. 1968. The Ontological Argument From St. Anselm to Contemporary Philosophers. London: Macmillan. [Google Scholar]
- Pollock, John Leslie. 1986. Contemporary Theories of Knowledge. Rowman & Littlefield Texts in Philosophy. Totowa: Rowman and Littlefield. [Google Scholar]
- Schlosser, Markus. 2015. Agency. In The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Edited by Edward Zalta. Available online: https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/agency/ (accessed on 3 April 2022).
- Stump, Eleonore. 2018. The Personal God of Classical Theism. In The Question of God’s Perfection. Leiden: Brill, pp. 65–81. [Google Scholar]
- Swinburne, Richard. 2004. The Existence of God, 2nd ed. Oxford: Clarendon Press. [Google Scholar]
- Swinburne, Richard. 2007. Revelation: From Metaphor to Analogy. Oxford: Clarendon Press. [Google Scholar]
- Titus, Eric Titus. 2010. The Perfections of God in the Theology of Karl Barth: A Consideration of the Formal Structure. Kairos: Evangelical Journal of Theology 4: 203–22. [Google Scholar]
- Van Eyghen, Hans. 2018. The Retreat Argument. The Heythrop Journal 3: 497–508. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Wiebe, Phillip H. 2004. God and Other Spirits: Intimations of Transcendence in Christian Experience. New York: Oxford University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Williams, Peter. 2006. The Case for Angels. Paternoster: London. [Google Scholar]
Publisher’s Note: MDPI stays neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations. |
© 2022 by the author. Licensee MDPI, Basel, Switzerland. This article is an open access article distributed under the terms and conditions of the Creative Commons Attribution (CC BY) license (https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/).
Share and Cite
Van Eyghen, H. From Theism to Spirit Beliefs. Religions 2022, 13, 460. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel13050460
Van Eyghen H. From Theism to Spirit Beliefs. Religions. 2022; 13(5):460. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel13050460
Chicago/Turabian StyleVan Eyghen, Hans. 2022. "From Theism to Spirit Beliefs" Religions 13, no. 5: 460. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel13050460
APA StyleVan Eyghen, H. (2022). From Theism to Spirit Beliefs. Religions, 13(5), 460. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel13050460