1. Introduction
“[T]here is only a difference in the mode of conceiving one and the same thought, whether we refer the hidden impulse of our actions to a transcendental Ego, or to Schopenhauer’s Will, or to Hartmann’s Unconscious, or to the Christian God. We may be of this opinion or that, yet since the impulse to action does not always lie in our sense and brain consciousness, we may agree with [Georg Christoph] Lichtenberg, that ‘On this globe we serve an end, the attainment of which cannot be hindered, though all mankind conspired against it.’”
“a transcendental philosophy is the more genuine, and better fulfills its vocation as philosophy, the more radical it is”
A discussion of “theism” in light of “humanism” and “secularism” might quickly lose itself in using unwarranted concepts and implicit assumptions. Already, the notion of “God” itself might lead the academic author astray:
mentioning this notion all too often passes into
using it, thereby taking a complete mastery of conceptual language for granted. What if “God” were a notion that neither designates nor means anything? What if the
intended referent (
God) were ultimately intractable and a limit case of language? What if
God could not be intended, properly speaking, at all? Unless (pace Husserl) pre- or even post-intentionality were considered, it would be a challenge for any academic author who pretends to shed some light on resurfacing theism in the secular subject to not succumb to illicit reifications that make hitherto achieved philosophical insights undone.
1 Such inferences would occur in naïve conclusions in the form of S = P (e.g., “the transcendent God of pre-Modernity
equals the modern subject’s conscience, rationality, unconscious, etc.”).
Not only the notion of “God” but also the concept of “secularity” is difficult to use unreflectively. How one defines these concepts somewhat already implies one’s attitude towards them. For example, if one defines secularisation—as Hans Blumenberg does
2—as the Modern movement of dissociating oneself from Judaeo-Christian affinities or as the emancipatory quest for moral self-legitimisation, one cannot avoid presupposing, in one way or another, that (a) this movement and the quest are a concrete possibility, (b) a self-contained morality exists, and (c) Judaeo-Christian conceptuality is particularistic and nonuniversal. On the contrary, if one takes secularisation—as Hegel does
3—to be the necessary outcome of a historical process leading from a contingent, locally determined (“religious”) conceptuality towards its obtaining universal validity and commonness, one presupposes that (a) this conceptuality is universally, though first secretly, valid, (b) the radical opposition between a transcendent and a purely mundane (“secular”) sphere makes sense, and (c) actual global developments related to human rights and cosmopolitan ideals of worldwide justice have some final significance.
In this article, I will not only defend the claim that the notion of the unconscious can be a legitimate inheritor of a more traditional discourse on God’s transcendence. I will also argue that Carl du Prel’s discussion of the unconscious (“transcendental consciousness”) is sufficiently self-reflective to embrace the methodological difficulties mentioned above. It can encompass the requirements of ultimacy and normativity—traditionally attributed to the transcendent God—without, for that matter, necessarily infringing transcendence. Also, it refrains enough from reifying so as to prevent including God in a simplistic referential scheme.
3. Double Nature of the I and Psychophysical Threshold
The main ingredients of Schopenhauer’s thinking return as the key elements of Du Prel’s philosophy. In
Philosophy of Mysticism, Du Prel critically elaborates on the implied
duality of the subject: its conscious and its unconscious parts. He claims that research on stimulus transmission through the human nervous system confirms Schopenhauer’s basic ideas. Such research was mainly conducted by the psychologist–philosopher Gustav Theodor Fechner (1801–1887) in his
Elements of Psychophysics. Its outcome showed that a time-lapse is implied for a nerve stimulus to arrive at the brain centre and be adequately processed. “The functions of the nervous system”, Du Prel states, “are […] associated with a definite measure of time”. (
Du Prel 1889, p. 89;
1885, p. 74f). And he continues by saying that “the phenomenal world would undergo a powerful transformation, were our measure of time in perception altered”. (
Du Prel 1889, p. 90;
1885, p. 75) Such transformations may occur during exceptional human experiences, for example, after using narcotics, during the dying process, in our deepest dreams, in a somnambulist state, or under hypnosis. It may become manifest, then, that our I is stratified. Whereas our
empirical I conforms to a physiological time frame, our (“unconscious”)
transcendental I obeys a wholly idiosyncratic time. Any confusion must result from an erroneous application of physiological temporal units to the time frame that governs exceptional experiences. “Thus we carry over into dream”, Du Prel writes, “the waking habit of estimating duration according to the number of perceptions upon the physiological scale of time, while our consciousness is, in fact, then subject to the transcendental scale”. (
Du Prel 1889, p. 94;
1885, p. 79) And, “the physiological scale of time is not essential to the human mind”; “its connection with the organic body is
no necessary relation” (
Du Prel 1889, p. 112;
1885, p. 94).
Du Prel not only distinguishes multiple simultaneous time frames (physiological and transcendental). He further claims that our physiological time cannot originate in transcendental consciousness itself and must therefore be relative; our nervous system only retards the cognitive content of consciousness. As everyone can see who has ever woken up from a dream because of an outward stimulus that produced the complete dream content retrospectively (the sudden ringing of a bell), this dream content must be located in the (infinitely short) time-lapse needed for the stimulus to reach consciousness and be processed by it, as if consciousness were already aware of what remains to be transmitted to it through the nervous system, and as if “its connection with the organic body is no necessary relation”. We can hardly avoid assuming the existence of a transcendental consciousness beyond the physiology of the nervous system. This transcendental consciousness might be unconscious for the waking mind; it will be conscious for itself. Let us see how this should be understood and how it can be connected—if at all—to the transcendent God’s resurfacing in the human unconscious.
Beyond the coincidental retro-causality of dream production, Du Prel suggests, dreams—let alone somnambulist states—provide evidence for the simultaneity of two forms of consciousness (of two
I’s) more directly. They
split the dreaming (or hallucinating) I. What is eventually a monologue is
distributed over a
scene and an
audience. This splitting takes place on the fault line of a
psychophysical threshold. “In dream, somnambulism, and all ecstatic conditions, an interior waking takes the place of the external sense-consciousness, but, being itself limited, likewise borders on the Unconscious”. (
Du Prel 1889, p. 115;
1885, p. 96) External and internal stimuli are
dramatised in our dream lives. The latter consists of a “projection of interior states” or a “symbolical representation of the internal condition”. (
Du Prel 1889, p. 117;
1885, p. 98) “[H]e conceives as non-Ego all that oversteps the threshold from the unconscious. Consequently, the dualism of the Conscious and the unconscious, the psychophysical partition, is the common cause, as well of the dramatic sundering, as of deception which makes dreams seem real” (
Du Prel 1889, p. 120f;
1885, p. 101).
Consciousness seems to be divided over two I’s, which are separated by a psychophysical threshold. This threshold does not separate a waking from a dreaming state; it is instead displaced when dreaming. Insofar as displacement (or another altered state of consciousness) occurs within the dream itself, it testifies to an increased susceptibility to content thus far concealed. Dreams exteriorise such unconscious content by immediately converting each flash of insight into an image and putting each word into another person’s mouth. They poignantly enhance the dramatic splitting.
Suppose that a psychophysical threshold is at work in our minds. In that case, Du Prel concludes, it is psychologically possible that the subject consists of two persons
ignorant of their mutual unity and connection with the subject. This doubleness may be permanent, although it will only manifest in dreams and other exceptional states of mind. Our second I, then, can contact us without us realising its identity with ourselves.
9 4. The Unconscious and God
The question becomes urgent as to whether such a more profound, “transcendental” I may be rightfully identified with a transcendent God and under which conditions. These two questions cannot be isolated.
It is already noteworthy that Du Prel appropriates Kant’s term “transcendental consciousness” to designate an unconscious level in the human mind beyond waking consciousness. In Kant, this term refers to an unalterable structure of thinking and perceiving (i.e., the two forms of perception, space and time, and the twelve categories of thinking). While Hegel and the neo-Kantians in his wake historicise transcendental consciousness by letting it unfold over time, they nevertheless capitalise, as a point of no return, the transcendental gain that history procures. In contrast, one could remark that Husserl’s phenomenology resists any form of reification while maintaining the concept of the transcendental consciousness itself.
In light of Du Prel, however, one might highlight three different shortcomings concerning transcendental consciousness. Kant sets strict limits to it, paralysing experience and forcing it into a spatiotemporal and categorical framework.
10 Hegel and neo-Kantianism historicise it, but that hardly improves anything: once developed, the transcendental creates an ontological
fait accompli. Husserl—posterior to Du Prel—threw out the baby with the bathwater since he did not allow for the
inner self-transcendence of transcendental consciousness. In Husserl, consciousness is intentional, and that excludes any form of stratification. In this respect, it is highly significant that Husserl could only interpret Descartes’ ontological argument for the existence of God as vicious instead of taking it as a
rupture of intentionality: “
Descartes had […] had not noticed the circle in which he was involved when he presupposed, in his proof of the existence of God, the possibility of inferences transcending the ego, when this possibility, after all, was supposed to be established only through this proof” (
Husserl 1962, p. 11;
1970, p. 92). And yet, Husserl acknowledged the necessity for the philosopher to “penetrate[…] to a clear
understanding of himself as the subjectivity functioning as primal source [urquellend]”.
11 I claim in this article that Carl du Prel, even before Husserl’s call and doubtlessly overstating its immediate concern, tried to take this necessity seriously and reinterpret the self as a generating source of transcendence, thereby contributing to the alleged “secularisation” of the transcendent God. Let us take a closer look.
In the final chapter of his
Philosophy of Mysticism, Du Prel addresses the question of transcendental consciousness and its relation to God. This question cannot be avoided in light of transcendental consciousness’
ultimacy and
normativity—characteristics commonly associated with God. Transcendental consciousness is first accessed at the “dusk” of waking consciousness. Du Prel does not hesitate to link the apostle Paul, the mythical seer Tiresias, Socrates/Plato, Philo, Christian mysticism, and Kant. To start with the latter: “[T]he greatest passivity of the sensible man”, Du Prel states, “brings the highest ecstasy, that is, the clearest inward awakening of the transcendental—or in Kant’s expression, the intelligible—man, while in the energetic abandonment of the personality to the phenomenal world, the inward man is reduced to silence” (
Du Prel 1889, p. 170;
1885, p. 423f). Du Prel corroborates this Kantian insight by associating “intelligible man” (who experiences “respect” for the law) with essential notions from the authors just mentioned. In his
Second Letter to the Corinthians (4, 16), Paul writes, “The more our outward man dies away, the more living is the inward”. Philo, in his turn, claims that “[w]hen the divine light shows itself, the light of man is hidden, not appearing again till the divine is hidden, as the prophets said: ‘Your spirit departs, as it were, when the spirit of God comes, and only returns when this withdraws’”. Plato writes in the
Phaedo that “if we would have pure knowledge of anything, we must be quit of the body—the soul in herself must behold all things in themselves: and then we shall attain the wisdom which we desire, and of which we say that we are lovers; not while we live, but after death”. Du Prel concludes that Christian mysticism’s fundamental notion can be found in the adage
sensuum occasus veritatis exortus est (“the decline of the senses constitutes the birth of truth”). “[A]ll are but different expressions of one and the same knowledge, confirmed also by somnambulism, that the inward sense of man is only manifested when the outward senses are suppressed; that the higher powers of the soul rise in proportion as the life of sense is depressed” (
Du Prel 1889, p. 171;
1885, p. 424).
True, Du Prel’s literary “evidence” in support of his claim can be interpreted otherwise. One might, for example, be surprised about the implicit identification of Kant’s intelligible man with “the highest ecstasy” or about the association of Paul’s encouragements to the senescent with somnambulism. My intention here is neither to justify nor to refute this “evidence”. I am interested in how the transcendental self can be identified with the transcendent God. Du Prel claims that such identification is possible, or at least that a clear distinction makes no sense. “Now if between man and the thing-in-itself”, Du Prel contends, “call we that God, or Pan, or Nature, there must be interposed the transcendental Subject, then the problem of our existence appears in a completely new light” (
Du Prel 1889, p. 202;
1885, p. 452).
12 When, I would ask, would a distinction between the transcendental self and God make sense? It would make sense if both differed in their degree of ultimacy or normativity. Such is not the case in Du Prel’s account. The latter does not imply celestial hierarchies in the sense of either pseudo-Dionysius or Swedenborgian theosophy. It restricts its scope to a threshold of consciousness that can be displaced under certain conditions.
Let us take a step further and see which role the transcendental subject fulfils in Du Prel’s philosophy and how it assumes ultimacy and normativity. I take “ultimacy” and “normativity” as unalienable qualities of transcendence. The “act” of transcending already implies limits imposed on what is transcended. These limits make it relative as regards the transcending and are proportionate to the latter’s
binding or
normative nature—in whatever form. At the same time, they confront it with its
beyond, with what is inexorably and irreducibly out of reach. Transcendence introduces normativity (it binds) and ultimacy (it cannot be superseded in turn).
13The role of the transcendental subject in Du Prel is at least threefold. It inaugurates birth (1), generates moral injunctions (2), and directs our lives (3). Especially the latter two are closely related, although, in the end, the first is involved in both. These three roles have traditionally been attributed to the transcendent God. God has always counted as the creator, issuing moral injunctions and governing our lives, albeit invisibly.
In Du Prel, however, these roles are attributed to the transcendental subject. Its first role (1) is to inaugurate birth, in other words, to become incarnate. Du Prel draws here on a longstanding spiritual tradition, which spanned at least from Plato (
Gorgias) and Plotinus to Schelling and Schopenhauer. This tradition entails that we choose our incarnation. A secularised version of this belief can be found in Fichte and Sartre. The latter two only differ from the former in that they have minimised, if not eliminated, the interstices between choosing the transcendental subject and its elective environment: I am my own act. In the Platonic tradition, however, the choice of our incarnation antedates it. “My transcendental Subject may be cause of my earthly personality;” Du Prel writes, “it is thus not the individuality that begins at birth, but only the sensuous, the earthly-conditional Ego”. (
Du Prel 1889, p. 204;
1885, p. 453). The transcendental “causality” of my empirical existence is further enhanced by parental love. Rather than attribute birth to the (coincidental) intercourse of parents, Du Prel goes as far as interpreting the sexual desire in parents to the drive of the (pre-existent) child to become incarnate: “if between man and the world-substance there is the transcendental Subject, then obviously the metaphysical Will is to be placed in such a Subject, and the love of the parents coincides with the incarnation-impulse of a transcendental, pre-existing Subject”. (
Du Prel 1889, p. 216;
1885, p. 463). (Note that Du Prel draws on Schopenhauer’s metaphysics of sexual love here, except for Schopenhauer’s conception of the Will to incarnate as
impersonal.)
The second role (2) of the transcendental subject reminiscent of the transcendent God concerns the moral injunctions it issues. Morality is ultimately rooted in the incentives that the transcendental subject generates and reveals—in whichever way—to the empirical person. The latter may have hitherto identified morality with law or tradition. But the empirical person may be wrong on this. “For the monistic doctrine of the soul”, Du Prel argues, “the moral imperative comes ultimately from the transcendental subject. Thus the authority ceases to be foreign, but as authority remains; and even though proceeding from our own subject, it is still not to be presupposed as petitio principii”.
Consequently, a confrontation with one’s innermost being, e.g., in crisis experiences or other meaningful life events, may lead to reconsidering what is morally incumbent on us or even
supererogatory. In light of ground-breaking, supererogating demands, common moral conceptions are likely to appear as mere tradition or convention without being
ultimately decisive. “The whole content of Ethic may be comprehended therein”, Du Prel summarises, “that the person should be serviceable to the Subject; every revolt of the person, in its own favour, against the Subject is immoral”. (
Du Prel 1889, p. 294;
1885, p. 530). What is more, such revolt cannot be made intelligible, for it runs contrary to our deepest
motivations: “The motive force of a moral principle depends on how
near me is the nature for whose redemption I am called to co-operate, and
from which the moral authority proceeds—and
this proximity is the greatest possible, if a transcendental Subject is supposed; it depends, further, on the
nearness of the aim to be reached by moral action, and this
nearness also is the greatest possible, when I already experience the transcendental results of my acts by discarding my earthly phenomenal form through death”. (
Du Prel 1889, p. 300;
1885, p. 535; my italics, RS). The transcendent God—one might retort here—
to the precise extent that he is transcendent, lacks motivational force; at best, he might
deter the trespassing of his commandments, but such deterrence would immediately annul ethics
as ethics (for my moral agency would be based on fear of divine punishment). Du Prel invites us to reconsider transcendence by
conflating command and the commander.
14Du Prel is undoubtedly not the only one to associate ethics with self-encounter. Existentialism, for example, likewise based proper ethics on critical human experiences calling one back to one’s own-most self—without, for that matter, implying a particularly
transcendental subject. Similarly, Henri Bergson argued that there are two sources of morality and religion: tradition and intuition. The latter, Bergson contended, tends to disrupt commonly held moral views and dynamise petrified ethical systems (
Bergson 1934). In 20th-century psychological thinking, we find this radical morality of selfhood in C.G. Jung; in many respects, Jung was inspired by Du Prel, not in the least regarding his conceptions of morality.
The third role (3), which Du Prel attributes to the transcendental subject and which reminds us of the transcendent God, is closely linked to the former. It regards the steering of our empirical lives. Many things may happen in our lives that we would have preferred not to happen: misfortune, suffering, or tragedy. Yet, rather than ascribe these to blind fate or sheer coincidence, Du Prel argues that they are connected to transcendental leadership: “the transcendental being considers the personality of sense in a purely objective relation, in an attitude of as much indifference to its fate as to that of a stranger—as it must be, since the two halves of the being lie this side and that side of a threshold of sensibility”. (
Du Prel 1889, p. 178;
1885, p. 430f). And he continues, stating that “[s]ince, moreover, we now know that the fruits of this life are not lost for the comprehensive consciousness of the transcendental being, it looks as if this being itself had chosen this lot, not being moved by the sufferings of our earthly life, but yet enjoying the fruits of it. Should we in this way conceive the earthly life, notwithstanding its preponderant suffering, as a transcendental prescription, then—and only then—disappear at once the contradictions encountered by theistic and pantheistic systems between the miseries of existence and providence; and the complaints of man against nature, which no philosophical system can seriously contend to be groundless, are silenced”. (
Du Prel 1889, p. 179;
1885, p. 431).
It would be easy to trace these ideas back to the ancient tradition of the Stoa. Prior to any philosophy of the transcendental subject, Seneca spoke of the indwelling God. We owe this God our gratefulness despite misfortunes.
15 In modern days, a thinker like Simone Weil perpetuates the Stoic tradition of divine immanence. In her
Waiting for God, she writes, “All that man vainly desires here below is perfectly realised in God. We have all those impossible desires within us as
a mark of our destination, and they are good for us when we no longer hope to accomplish them”.
16 In this quotation, Weil shows that suffering is limited to the perspective of our empirical existence and represents our challenge. It might be a gateway to a higher form of consciousness that merges with the divine.
5. Conclusions
In this article, I have tried to argue that the notion of the unconscious (“transcendental consciousness”) developed by Carl du Prel perpetuates the classical idea of a transcendent God. It does so by its ultimacy and its normativity. I have taken “ultimacy” and “normativity” as notions that irreducibly belong to “transcendence”. Transcendence, by virtue of transcending, limits and binds the transcended and confronts it with its beyond. Transcendence introduces normativity (it binds) and ultimacy (it cannot be superseded in turn).
To this, we can add the intractability of the unconscious regarding linguistic referentiality: as the unconscious is not an object, it cannot be “designated”; any form of reification of the unconscious will likely draw on the limitations proper to “waking” consciousness. The predicament of philosophy and language is that concepts tend to be conceived as signifiers that refer to univocal “meanings” susceptible to “definition”. The history of philosophy can partly be seen as a growing awareness of this predicament. Could it be that what is called “secularisation” or “Modernity”—at least to some extent—ties in with this growing awareness to the point of “reallocating” transcendence elsewhere, for example, in an unconscious issuing ultimately binding injunctions? Is it not highly telling and most significant, therefore, that Du Prel insists on the
proximity of moral authority and transcendental subjectivity, a proximity that almost
conflates the “distance” of a transcendent God and the “nearness” of my unconscious (“The motive force of a moral principle depends on how
near me is the nature for whose redemption I am called to co-operate, and
from which the moral authority proceeds—and
this proximity is the greatest possible, if a transcendental Subject is supposed; it depends, further, on the
nearness of the aim to be reached by moral action, and this
nearness also is the greatest possible, when I already experience the transcendental results of my acts by discarding my earthly phenomenal form through death”) (
Du Prel 1889, p. 300;
1885, p. 535. My italics, RS)? This proximity need not be conceived as identity, for that might unjustifiably divinise the unconscious and reify both God and the unconscious. What is gained by the notion of an unconscious lies precisely in its blurring of the boundaries between clear-cut entities (“God”, “consciousness”, “unconscious”).
17Carl du Prel’s philosophy of the unconscious (or “transcendental subjectivity”) and its 20th- and 21st-century concomitants can help rethink transcendence precisely by (1) its embracing of experience (true, not the manipulated, randomised version often substituted for experience, i.e., the
sense data or
evidence of science) and (2) its more comprehensive conception of consciousness as a form endowed with a
mobile inner threshold.
“If, therefore, the question of the prophet: ‘Leavest thou men as the fishes of the sea, as the creeping things, that have no ruler ?’ (Habakkuk 1, 14) must, as regards human history, be answered in the negative, it only remains to ask to whom this question is to be addressed: to the personal God, to the single Universal Will, or to the plurality of transcendental subjects, whose consciousness of their solidarity, however, must, with the continual development of the purpose of history on a large scale and in the whole, have grown into antagonism to the Will of the earthly individual”.
And Du Prel meaningfully continues, saying that,
“[p]ractically, it is indifferent which address we suppose for this question of the prophet, and if only we do not, like the materialists, deny that it has any address, we should join hands over all other differences of opinion, with a common faith in human solidarity, instead of contending, as unhappily those do who have nevertheless still a belief in metaphysics generally—the religious and the philosophical. It is not really a question of the form of metaphysic, be it this or that religion or philosophy, at a time when a common danger has to be encountered in the total rejection of metaphysic, with the already alarming consequences of that rejection”.
If, and only if, neither the unconscious nor the transcendent God is reified, it is indeed “practically indifferent which address we suppose for this question of the prophet”. Transcendental consciousness (or just the unconscious) remains a limit case for “ordinary” consciousness. Ultimately, and at a more profound level of reflection, it would make no sense to ask if God “exists”, or whether God’s transcendence disappears in the (alleged) immanence of the unconscious. Such questions draw on tacit reifications that distort the basic intractability and fertility of the unconscious.
It cannot be my aim in this article to suggest that any
alleged claim to unconscious contents is irrefutably valid. The unconscious is equally liable to be misunderstood, if not abused, as was the notion of God’s transcendence throughout history. The secular age has not profoundly eliminated such possible abuse. I wonder, however, whether
no forms of abuse (i.e., deceitful truth claims) ultimately draw on transcendence. Is it not finally the transcendent God who “permits”—in a highly ambiguous sense—truth abuse?
18