John Damascene’s Arguments about the Existence of God: A Logico-Philosophical and Religio-Hermeneutic Approach
Abstract
:Introduction: Aim, Scope, and Methodology
1. John Damascene’s Prelude
2. The Ontological Argument
(i) created beings = things that have been made ⇒ the Maker,so (ii) the Maker = uncreated (Being),but because (iii) changeable beings = sensible and intelligible/created beings,and because (iv) the Maker (as uncreated) ≠ sensible and intelligible,(v) the Maker = unchanging (Being) ⇒(vi) unchanging (Being) = God (for “God” does not belong to the set “sensible & intelligible”).32
(1a) created beings = things that have been made,and (1b) things that have been made ≠ the Maker,so (2) the Maker ≠ created beings.
3. The Cosmological Argument
3.1. Syllogism I
3.2. Syllogism II
(i) nature involves order, that is, synthesis, distinction, movement, and regularity,but (ii) nature does not produce these by itself,meaning (iii) that they come from another source ⇒(iv) that this other source is the creator of nature.51
(i) “the artisan” is the creator,but (ii) let us say that it is not the creator,then (iii) who could it be? ⇒ the only option is to say that “the artisan” is “to automaton” (=mere chance”).56
Let us concede (iv) that the production of nature can be ascribed to mere chance,(v) that the order of nature can be ascribed to mere chance, and(vi) that the maintenance of nature within “logos” can be ascribed to mere chance.But the last proposition constitutes a contradictio in adjecto, since “logos” and “to automaton” are incompatible to one another.57
4. An Argument about the Impossibility of Arguments: The Case of “According to Essence and Nature”
4.1. Sequence of Notions
4.2. Evidence from the Holy Scriptures
4.3. Special Use of the Cosmological Argument
(i) the fifth element moves,so (ii) it is subject to a principle of motion,which (iii) is subject to another principle, and so forth, until one gets to the ultimate principle,which (iv) is unmoving by being the ultimate (principle of motion) (for the entire phrasing of the syllogism, see SJD II, 12:14–19).
(i) “kinoumenon” (“something being moved”) = “en topôi perigrapton” (“something described as being in place”) ⇒ body,and if (ii) “akinêton” (“something that does not move”) = “asômaton”,and (iii) “theion” (“the Divine”) = “akinêton”,then (iv) “theion” = “asômaton”.69
Conclusions
Funding
Data Availability Statement
Conflicts of Interest
1 | |
2 | The first section or “book” of the Exact Exposition comprises Chapters 1–14 and goes back to the division of the work carried out by Burgundio de Pisa in the twelfth century. The relevant arguments actually cover Chapters 5–7 as well, but the material therein refers mostly to the existence of God as Trinity. The present study will not deal with this specific topic but will limit itself to the more general arguments about the existence of God. |
3 | |
4 | Criticism is especially the case with modern Orthodox theologians, at least from the 1960s onwards. This is not limited to John Damascene’s arguments but involves the arguments about the existence of God in general. A concomitant trend is the virtual absence of monographs on the subject in modern Greek Orthodox theology. For a conspicuous exception, see Adrahtas (2001a). |
5 | |
6 | |
7 | |
8 | In Chapter 1 [SJD II, 7:14–15 (hereafter SJD, standing for Die Schriften des Johannes von Damaskos vol. 2 [where in find Exdosis Akribês tês orthodoxou Pisteôs], first number indicating page(s) and the other(s) indicating lines), he writes: “pasi gar ê gnosis tou einai theon hyp’autou physikôs egkatespartai” (“for in everyone the knowledge that God exists has been planted naturally by Him”). In Chapter 3 (SJD II, 10:4–5), he writes with a slight variation: “ê gnosis tou einai theon physikôs hêmin egkatespartai” (“the knowledge that God exists has been planted naturally in us”). Both assertions point towards the so-called “natural revelation”, which in turn constitutes the basis for the formulation of natural theology. For the latter in general, see Manning et al. (2013), and for its presence in Eastern Orthodox theology, see Bradshaw and Swinburne (2021), wherein one can find substantial information on the patristic argumentation regarding the existence of God (see, for example, Fokin (2021)). |
9 | John Damascene refers to Judaism and Christianity when he writes (SJD II, 10:2–3) “tois men tas hagias graphas dehomenois, tên te palaian kai kainên diathêkên” (“to those who accept the Holy Scriptures, the Old and the New Testament”), and to the so-called “polytheistic religions” when he writes (JD II, 10:3–4) “tois tôn hellênôn pleistois” (“to most of the Hellenes”). Here, we have a version of the so-called “historico-religious argument” (or e consensu omnium), which is presented indirectly as an aspect of “natural revelation”. |
10 | The very fact that the Damascene starts (in Chapter 3 of the Exact Exposition) his reference to theology proper by dealing with the problem of atheism exemplifies that for him, the negation of the existence of God constitutes a major theological problem. Furthermore, the logical approach to atheism on his part and even more so, the placing of this kind of approach at the beginning of his systematic theological work, seem to imply that theology constitutes an inherently rational activity. In other words, whenever God talk begins with the reasonable refutation of the negation of the existence of God, that is, by exemplifying the rationality of the God question, then such talk is presented in its entirety as an activity that is conditioned by rational aspects. From a different perspective, if one were to regard the God question as the major question of the philosophy of religion, then it could be maintained that this question constitutes a kind of prolegomena to all theological systems. For the latter remark, see Nissiotis (1986). |
11 | At this point, we can see at work the methodology of logical distinctions/divisions. To be sure, both this distinction and numerous others that we find in John Damascene’s opus magnum “The Fountain of Knowledge” (Pêgê Gnôseôs), of which the Exact Exposition is the third and last part, constitutes specific distinctions which are different from the fundamental theological distinctions in Chapter 2 of the Exact Exposition. This particular distinction follows the Aristotelian tradition on causality, though without using the relevant terminology. One could say that the Damascene does not limit himself to the efficient and formal causes, but also hints at the material cause, inasmuch as he mentions “to automaton” (“mere chance”) further on in Chapter 3, and also that for him, “apôleia” (“perdition”) constitutes the final cause of atheism. |
12 | Herein the formal cause is presented by the Damascene as a complex set, something that in practise is a further application of the logical process of division. It is worth noting that the gnoseological, moral, and religious dimensions of the formal cause of atheism are understood by John Damascene as different aspects of a single phenomenon. Especially, the words used in the case of the religious aspect, such as “katagagein” (“descending”), “barathron”, “phôs” (“light”), “bythos” (“the depth”), “anêgon” (“lifted”), and “eskotismenous” (“those being in darkness”), utilize the ancient and widely known hierophanic symbolism of light versus darkness and ascent versus descent. For this symbolism, see Eliade (1959). |
13 | |
14 | |
15 | For the distinction between reason as an ontological condition (also known traditionally as intellect) and reason as instrumental/technical rationality, in a theological context, especially as formulated in the thought of Paul Tillich, see Smith (2017, pp. 29–107). |
16 | For the term, see the magisterial Otto (2014). The Damascene’s ontological, i.e., metaphysical, as well as axiological and deontological, understanding of reason continues a great part of ancient Greek logical theory—with the exception, most likely, of the Sophist movement. Regarding Plato, it has been noted that “he is undoubtedly the first great thinker in the field of the philosophy of logic. He treats at some length… important questions, which arise as soon as we begin to reflect on the nature of logic… It must be understood, however, that Plato does not address himself directly to these questions… They have emerged clearly only after centuries of reflection; and as we read Plato, it seems to us that they are still obscured for him by the metaphysical and epistemological questions with which they are inextricably interwoven” (Kneale and Kneale 1971, p. 17; my emphasis). Furthermore, regarding Aristotle, one should have in mind that “much of the doctrine of the Categories must be regarded as metaphysical rather than logical” (ibid., p. 25; my emphasis). Lastly, the axiological/deontological dimensions of reason have been tellingly put forward by Neo-Kantianism (see, e.g., Heis (2018)). |
17 | In this connection, I find quite pertinent the following: “Without God reason is not, in a superficial sense, simply ‘atheistic’. By negating God truly, in whatever manner, reason subverts itself. ‘Atheistic reason’ is not simply ‘atheistic’. It ceases being reason as well… Without God reason is not” (Papapetros 1979, pp. 263–64; my translation; author’s emphasis). |
18 | Ultimately, the notion of what is logically true/correct is produced socio-historically. Thus, even if the ontological/metaphysical presuppositions of reason may not be accepted, the socially and historically conditional character of reason is a given. In this sense, rationality does not constitute an independent feature. On the other hand, however, rationalism is constructed as an absolutization at the level of theory; it defines what is logically true/correct in an ideocratic way, thus overlooking its socio-historical relativity. Phrased differently, whereas rationality comes under the major hierophany of a given culture, rationalism constitutes itself the major hierophany of a given culture. For the difference between rationality and rationalism, see Begzos (1990). |
19 | For a long-time standard anthology regarding the ontological argument, see Plantinga (1965). For interesting and rigorous discussions, see Leftow (2005) and Lowe (2007). This particular argument in the work of John Damascene could be regarded as a precursor of the classic ontological argument by Anselm of Canterbury (1033/4-1109). |
20 | That it does constitute a genuine ontological argument can be ascertained (1) from the fact that it is based on the multifaceted semantics of the definitions involved (cf. Kneale and Kneale (1971, p. 358)) and (2) because other known arguments about the existence of God do not seem to satisfy the manner in which the reasoning in Chapter 2 is structured. Nevertheless, to be sure, in comparison to Anselm, the Damascene’s argument presents a much less adequate logical structure. |
21 | At this point, the Damascene’s reasoning presupposes an exclusive disjunction (p ⊻ q). This means that p and q must be mutually exclusive. Of course, for the Damascene, no issue of verifying such a mutual exclusivity is posed therein, since it is already a given within the notions involved. Thus, the true significance of his premise consists of being a specific answer to the question of Being. |
22 | The exclusive disjunction seen above corresponds more to (∃x): p(x) and (∃x): q(x) rather than to (∃p): x(p) and (∃q): x(q). The former denotes that logically x = Being comes under p = created and q = uncreated, whereas the latter denotes that p and q come under x. The fact that the Damascene opts for the former can be seen indirectly from the way in which he defines “Being” in his Dialectica. “Being is a self-existing reality, not in need of something else in order to be constituted, or a reality that is unable to be in itself but has its existence in something else” (SJD I [ed. Kotter], 77:100–104). This definition, I believe, would not have been possible if the Damascene did not have in mind the Creator (“aktiston”) and the created (“ktiston”). Although from a logical point of view, the “the self-existing” (“authyparkton”) and what is “unable to be in itself” (“mê kath’ heauto dynamenon einai”) refer, respectively, to essence and attribute (cf. SJD I, 57:3–58:13; 59:55–60; 77:104–107, 117–120), the Damascene regards them as different orders of Being. It might be that “‘Being’ is a common name for all beings” (SJD I, 57:3–4), but the latter do not come under the former as if they were genus and species, respectively (cf. SJD I, 77:109–115). In effect, the latter (i.e., beings) are simply related to the former (i.e., Being). I believe that this construction of the logical order corresponds perfectly well to the theological distinction “aktiston”–“ktiston”. In other words, John Damascene’s logic is the logic of his theology. |
23 | For the entire line of reasoning, see the passage in SJD II, 22–34. |
24 | In light of this, “tropê” is logically equivalent to “ktiston” (cf. SJD II, 46:16). But here, it is worth asking whether such a conceptualization is akin to ancient Greek ontology. In my view, the answer must be negative; although ancient Greek metaphysics is quite familiar with the notion of “tropê”, the special meaning reserved for the latter is that of “gignesthai” (“Becoming”). But “gignesthai” is the other and at the same time the inadequate side of “Being”; its aspect is in terms of sensory experience. This means that ancient Greek “Being” is firstly and basically determined in light of the intelligible (the “noêton”); something is to the degree that it is an object of the intellect to the degree that it is represented noetically. Termed differently, the significance of the term “tropê” in John Damascene’s text consists of its peculiar theological function. It points to the dynamics/linearity of Christian historical consciousness against the static-ness/circularity of ancient Greek ontology. For the latter dichotomy, see Eliade (1965). |
25 | The distinction decay (“phtheiromena”) and corruption (“alloioumena”) comes first and the distinction corruption (“alloiousthai”), movement (“kinêsthai”), and alteration (“mataballesthai”) follow. In this manner, John Damascene seems to semantically treat “tropê” as a genus with two partially different species. But why does he do something like this, instead of dividing one “tropê” into a number of species? I think that at this point, the dialectics of John Damascene unwittingly reflect the history of “gignesthai” in ancient Greek thought, and how it developed from the Presocratics to Plato to Aristotle. |
26 | This is a term derived from Aristotelian ethics (Steiger 2014). This is noteworthy for at this point, the Damascene puts forward once again the co-functionality of ethics and logic. In particular, in the light of ethics, he suggests criteria of logical modality. For an introduction to the modal logic of Aristotle, see Patterson (1995). For the modal logic of the Megarian School, see Hartmann et al. (2017); for the Stoics in this connection, see Bobzien (1986). To be sure, in ancient Greek logical theory, modality is not determined by ethics, while clearly it does in the case for the Damascene. The modal understanding put forward by the latter has axiological preconditions that stem from the experience of divine revelation. It does not refer—simply or primarily—to the necessary, the contingent, the possible, or the impossible, for these belong to the onto-gnoseo-logical range that moves between (absolute) possibility and (circumstantial) impossibility. On the contrary, the onto-THEO-logical range is constituted beyond possibility and impossibility; it emerges when the latter is experienced as fullness thanks to “das ganz Andere”. Thus, in this context, the criterion for determining the modality of premises is the degree (cf. SJD II, 11:31) to which one realizes the fullness of the ontological. |
27 | The mentioning of quality and spatiality is an indirect yet clear reference to Aristotle’s categories in his works Categories and On Interpretation (Aristotelis Categoriae et Liber de Interpretatione (ed. Minio-Paluello [Oxf. Class. Texts]) 25:5–33:38 and 14:8–14). |
28 | In this connection, John Damascene definitely has in mind what he writes in Chapter 14 of his Dialectica (SJD I, 84:16–17): “idion esti, ho panti kai monôi tôi eidei kai aei hyparchei” (“a characteristic feature is what exists only and always in the entire species”). In this sense, the follownig is also true (SJD I, 85:28–29): “katêgorountai gar ta idia tôn eidôn, ôn idia esti, alla kai ta eidê katêgorountai tôn idiôn autôn” (“for the characteristic features are predicated to the species of which they are characteristic features, but then also the species are predicated to their characteristic features”). |
29 | Much has been written on the ontological primacy or not of essence in the context of theology. In my view, the entire issue is misplaced inasmuch as the primacy or not of essence remains at the onto-gnoseo-logical level. If theology constitutes the linguistic and logical mediation of onto-THEO-logical experience, then the primacy under discussion belongs neither to essence nor to hypostasis, but to “das ganz Andere”, which dialectically synthesizes essence and hypostasis. |
30 | This is what has been aptly dubbed “patristic paradigm shift”. On this, see the pertinent remarks in Plexidas (2001, pp. 59–91). |
31 | It should be noted that in this connection, “necessarily” is arbitrary; it is only true in the case of a particular Weltanschauung, namely the Christian one. But then the logical inference is undermined. It is also worth noting that the Damascene has already maintained (SJD II, 11:22–23) the reverse as well, i.e., that “ei men oun ktista, pantôs kai trepta” (“if they are created, then necessarily they will be subject to change”). This means that for him, there is a logical semantic equivalence between “trepton” (t) and “ktiston” (k): t ≡ k. However, in ancient Greek philosophy “trepton” might be, or is not necessarily, “ktiston”: ∼□ (t ⊃ k). This peculiar necessity is posited as such only within onto-THEO-logical experience. Thus, from a formal logic perspective, there is a discrepancy here; the Damascene starts and finishes his “tropê” digression in a logically inadequate manner, or better yet, by putting forward a different logic. But in any case, this position of John Damascene demonstrates the intrinsic logical problems that emerge when different worldviews get to be synthesized. |
32 | For the actual wording in John Damascene’s text, see SJD II, 1134–37. |
33 | In particular, proposition (i) represents a synthesis between “ktiston” as understood in ancient Greek thought, that is, what is in a general sense produced, and “ktiston” as understood in Christianity, that is, what has been produced ex nihilo. To be sure, the problem in this connection lies in the idea of nothingness. While ancient Greek philosophy does know this idea (cf. Niarchos 1985), which could function as a basis for a synthesis with Christianity, it is an idea totally different from the one we find in Christianity. The former is gnoseological, whereas the latter constitutes the negative of the idea of a God who is transcendent over the world. For a comparison between the Christian and the non-Christian idea of nothingness, see Matsoukas (1986, pp. 35–58). |
34 | And this is precisely the meaning of the Christian “trepton”, hence the need to have a digression on changeability before the proper argument. For a detailed presentation of the Christian teaching on “trepton”, see Matsoukas (1994, pp. 209–20). |
35 | This particular logical method pertains—at least, historically—to the cosmological argument and not to the ontological. Thus, one could maintain that in his line of reasoning, the Damascene combines elements of the former with elements of the latter; in other words, the famous “chain of causes” with the semantic coherence of notions. |
36 | The cryptic character of the final stage of the argument runs against the need for clarity from a logical point of view, a fact that indirectly shows that this stage of the Damascene’s argument constitutes a logical leap. In practise, the Damascene’s “God” is not inferred from the premises of the syllogism, but is identical with the notion of “atrepton” (“unchanging”) that is used within the syllogism. |
37 | At this point, one could reasonably pose the following question: writing in the eighth century, which adherents of polytheism could John Damascene possibly have in mind? If he is not just aspiring to render his text as encyclopedic as possible, then I would dare say that indirectly, he refers to Manichaeism, which in a syncreti(sti)c manner that accommodated both polytheism (for instance, the dualism of good and evil) and aspects of ancient Greek philosophizing (for instance, aeons as a transmutation of Platonic onto-gnoseo-logy). Moreover, Manichaeism constitutes a constant adversary in the Damascene’s polemical works. For the latter remark, see Ables (2022a). |
38 | For the cosmological argument in general, see Rowe (1975) and Craig (1980). Aristotle is the first to have put forward this argument in full-fledged form, whereas Thomas Aquinas is the one who gave it its classic standing. The relationship of the Damascene’s cosmological argument to that of Aristotle’s seems to be an eclectic one, that the Damascene’s Christian self-consciousness requires him to make certain modifications, such as dispensing with the ancient Greek understanding of eternity, cosmic circularity, and the causal inherent unity between the Divine and the world. Furthermore, one could dare say that in some ways, John Damascene constitutes an in-between moment in the development of the cosmological argument from Aristotle to Thomas Aquinas—albeit in a rather simple and compact fashion compared to them. |
39 | More specifically, at Heb 3:4 and Rom 1:19–20, admittedly in a very compact fashion in the former and rather indirectly in the latter. |
40 | The fact that initially Christianity adopted (and, by extension, adapted) only the cosmological argument and not other types of arguments about the existence of God must be due to some special reason. The historical dialogue that was by necessity inaugurated between Christianity and Hellenism could not but lead to the former appropriating elements of the strong cultural legacy of the latter. Thus, it seems that the cosmos/world came forward as the most familiar such element, and this is because within the context of the onto-THEO-logical experience, Being emerges as a creation of the Divine. In other words, the “God” of Christianity is primarily and mainly a Creator, which means that any argument about God’s existence must be constructed in relation to the existence of the cosmos/world. In light of this, one could say that Christianity did not just adopt the cosmological argument and it did not just make certain modifications to its structure, but all the more rendered it the Christian argument about the existence of God par excellence. |
41 | Here, one can trace the clear and substantial influence of Stoicism. To be sure, the entire third paragraph could be endorsed by a Stoic, if the mentioning of “ktisis” was excluded and the much-cherished-by-the-Stoics theory about the telos of nature was included. This is all the more noteworthy, given the pantheistic character of Stoicism. What I want to emphasize here is the fact that John Damascene makes his own an onto-logical schema that presupposes and entails a self-consciousness totally different from that of the Christian experience of revelation. Nevertheless, theology as the mediation of onto-THEO-logical experience can accommodate the Stoic onto-logical schema by re-interpreting it via a rupture, firstly, and a re-constitution afterwards. The rupture is effected through the negation of nature as the Divine and a logos in itself, whereas the re-constitution is realized through the notion of “ktisis” and hence the Divine as a principle beyond nature. Termed differently, paragraph 3 of Chapter 3 of the Exact Exposition could be said to exemplify, from a history of philosophy perspective, the intrinsically dialectic manner in which logic is re-constituted within the context and in the light of onto-THEO-logical experience. |
42 | According to the text (SJD II, 11:41), “eis enos kosmou symplêrôsin” (“to the completion of a single world”). In my view, both “kosmos” (=harmony) and “symplêrôsis” (=movement towards fullness) imply the idea of totality, comprising harmony and fullness in the world that are unthinkable at the level of parts, since the Damascene designates the latter as “enantia” (opposed) to one another. On the other hand, order is denoted via the questions “ti to taxan?” (“which is the one that imposed order?”) and “tinos to taxai?” (“to which does the imposition of order belong?”) [SJD II, 11:44; 12:51], as well as through “kybernêsis”, “logon entheis pasi” (“having placed logos in everything”) and “kath’ hous hypestê logous” (“according to the logoi in which things originally came to exist”) [SJD II, 11:48; 12:52]. |
43 | The first who mentioned them was Empedocles (see Kingsley and Parry (2020)). In his philosophy, they are called “rizomata” (“rootings”) and they are understood as the foundational elements that are irreducible to one another and from which everything comes via the appropriate combination. |
44 | The most important among those conceptualizations are the following: “hen” (“one”), “tauton” (“same”), “koinon” (“common”), “monas” (“singularity”), “homoion” (“similar”), “teleion” (“perfect”), “syntheton” (“synthetic”), and “periechon” (“that which includes”). |
45 | The first to point this out was Aristotle (Analytica Priora et Posteriora (ed. Ross [Oxf. Class. Texts]) 116:12–13), who stated “antiphasis de antithesis hês ouk esti metaxy kath’ heautên” (“contradiction is an opposition which in itself has no middle”). |
46 | |
47 | I use the term “synthetic” for in the modern version of dialectics; “synthesis” constitutes the basic element objective of the entire methodology. This of course does not entail that the Damascene’s negative evaluation of synthesis (see, for instance, SJD II, 12:7–8) is overlooked. But it should be noted that John Damascene entertains himself a very positive use of the term within his theological thought, and more specifically, within his Christology (see SJD II, 135:104–136:109). The Damascene regards, on the one hand, synthesis as a specific understanding of unity and on the other, accepts a typology of synthesis that allows him to make the necessary logical divisions and use particular meanings of the term, depending on context. At this point, the meaning that he has in mind is described as “hê de kata synthesin henosis estin hê eis allêla tôn merôn chôris afanismou perichorêsis” (“unity according to synthesis is the coinherence between parts that does not lead to their destruction”) [SJD II, 135:104–136:106]. In light of this definition, since there is no destruction, “perichorêsis” is logically/semantically equivalent to transcendence. |
48 | This kind of transcendence constitutes a rupture of the monistic/cyclical naturalism we find in Hellenism. Also, the Divine synthetic factor is primarily and mainly transcendent, not because it is notionally constituted through gnoseological transcendence, but because it is constituted as a peculiar condition of transcendence. In the first case, it would not be but relatively transcendent, whereas in the second case, it signifies human impossibility and its fullness, or to put it differently, impossibility as fullness thanks to the presence of “das ganz Andere”. |
49 | Ostensibly, there are as many types of transcendence as there are paradigms of self-realization. Each of them reflects a different experience of existence, as well. The Christian type of transcendence consists essentially of its peculiar historicity, that is, in a certain attitude within and over historical temporality. This differentiates it fundamentally from ancient Greek transcendence, which as monistic/cyclical, consists of a certain positioning within the natural world. For the latter, see Farouki (1996). |
50 | Here, John Damascene definitely has in mind the notion of regularity, for he writes about “alêktou phoras” (“endless cyclical moving”) and “to pan pheretai te kai diexagetai” (“everything is both moving cyclically and taking place repeatedly”). Furthermore, it is only in light of regularity that his negation of mere chance in what follows makes sense. |
51 | For the entire phrasing of syllogism II in the Damascene’s text, see SJD II, 11:44–12:50. Regarding syllogism II within its broader contextuality as allowing one to trace an incipient form of Thomas Aquinas’ quinque viae, see Adrahtas (2001b, p. 71 (n. 186)). |
52 | The manner of understanding (and not just explaining) nature is subject to change, either in the form of Karl Popper’s “gradual process” or the form of Thomas Kuhn’s “scientific revolutions”; the paradigm of science constitutes a relationship with natural reality, a relationship that is produced along with broader cultural changes. Regarding the latter, significant is the role played by the degree, that is, the range of the relationship between humans and natural reality. Crucial in this connection is the fact that the understanding of nature is not so much the emergence of an objectivity as it is a projection of a thought model on nature. Michael Polanyi, in particular, has emphasized the radically qualitative character of scientific knowledge in his theory about “personal knowledge”. For an introduction to these thinkers, see McGrath (1999, pp. 76–86). |
53 | This entails that in effect, John Damascene’s syllogism II is made up of two parts. It is the first one that constitutes an induction, in the sense of moving from the particular to the generic. The presence of induction at this point is due to the idea of regularity, which the Damascene has already presupposed. |
54 | |
55 | This extension is basically the second part of syllogism II, which from a logical point of view, constitutes an indirect proof. |
56 | In Chapter 39 of the Exact Exposition, the Damascene distinguishes between “tychê” (=luck) and “automaton” (SJD II, 96:14–21). However, both come as species under the notion of “symptôsis” (“coincidence”), which means that they are not to be seen as radically different. The Damascene’s distinction herein is of Aristotelian provenance, according to which the difference between “tychê” and “automaton” lies in the fact that they more or less have different fields of reference; “tychê” refers basically to things that happen in the sphere of human life, while “automaton” refers to what takes place in the sphere of nature. |
57 | This is not true in the case of ancient Greek philosophy—at least, not in the manner that it is in the case of the Christian Weltanschauung. For the ancient Greeks, “tychê” and “to automaton” are not always contradictory to logos. In the context of the monistic structure of Being, everything abides by the law of causal relationships, regardless of the fact that the latter may be impenetrable, unknown, or obscure. On the contrary, for Christian consciousness, Being is “trepton”, which means that the only essence it has is its propensity towards non-Being. Its logos, that is, the very fact that it presents causal relationships, does not stem from within Being but is derived from the transcendent creator. In this respect, once again we come across a fundamental inversion, namely “tychê” and “to automaton” do not constitute the noetic (pre)condition of Being, but constitute the very essence of Being, while logos is not the gnoseological decoding of “tychê” and “to automaton”, but their transcendence. |
58 | This is precisely what the Atomists and Epicureans did in ancient Greece. See the cosmological teaching of these two schools in Kirk et al. (1957) and Long (1974), respectively. |
59 | In the context of the cosmological argument per se, it is not possible to sustain such an exclusion. Furthermore, the aim of the Damascene throughout the text is to prove not the cause of creation but the existence of God. Nevertheless, being intrinsically related to the ontological argument, the cosmological could not accept in practise a position whereby the creator and “to automaton” are identified. To be sure, the exclusion under discussion does not constitute, as it may seem at first an arbitrary logical vacuum, it does work within the context of a certain conceptualization of “to automaton”. In particular, for onto-THEO-logical thought, the latter is per definitionem other than the creator. Hence, at this point, John Damascene writes based on the logical consistency between the notions of a given system that has been constructed logically as the inversion of onto-gnoseo-logical thinking. |
60 | This connection is a commonplace both in Hellenism and in Christianity. Ancient Greek philosophy in its entirety has been aptly characterized as a transition from myth to rationality (see the classic Nestle (1940)). But if this transition did not entail the invalidation of religiosity, then in reality, the emergence of rational thinking signalled the shift of the hierophanic centre within ancient Greek civilisation, where logic became the new locus of the Divine. On the other hand, Christian thinking about Christ as the logos of God signalled a corresponding rational performance of religiosity. The Damascene’s position about the relation between God and logos is in practise a confirmation of the synthesis that took place between the transcendent God of Judaism and the immanent logos of Hellenism. |
61 | That this is not so can be inferred directly from the beginning of Chapter 5 (SJD II, 13:2–3), where it is stated “hoti men esti theos, ikanôs apodedeiktai, kai hoti akatalêptos estin hê ousia autou” (“that God exists, has adequately been demonstrated, and that his essence is incomprehensible”; my emphasis). It is also evident, indirectly, from the very structure of this chapter. To put it otherwise, if Chapter 3 involves proving aspects of Chapter 1, then Chapter 4 involves proving aspects of Chapter 2. In this manner, the first four chapters of the Exact Exposition are intertwined in pairs of synthetic and analytic articulations; ultimately the Damascene’s arguments/proofs are but analyses/explanations. |
62 | Theologically, this distinction is not an original insight on the part of John Damascene, but goes back to Basil of Caesarea (ed. Moutsoulas [BEPES, 52], 175:23–25), who said “ou gar hê tou ti estin exereunêsis, all’ hê tou hoti estin homologia tên sôtêrian hêmin paraskeuazei” (“for not the exploration regarding what He is, but the confession that He is provides us with salvation”, my emphasis). More specifically, the distinction “what something is” is dialectically intertwined with other distinctions as well; “the category ti estin is opposed in the Damascene to other categories such as to en tini, to pou, to pote, etc.” (Rozemond 1959, p. 18, my translation and emphasis). |
63 | John Damascene regards the two notions as identical (that is, with the same signified). However, this is due to the context of divine revelation and not a formal truth. For example, in ancient Greek logical theory, these terms are not identical, but synonymous or equivalent. This is something that the Damascene is aware of (see SJD I, 93: chp. 31, pp. 3–6). He does not regard “ousia” and “physis” simply as synonymous but as identical points to the rupture of onto-logical thinking in light of onto-THEO-logical revelation. In this respect, the Damascene does not negate synonymity but transcends it. For this rupture–transcendence, see cf. Siasos (1989, pp. 31–56). |
64 | See Adrahtas (2001b, p. 78 (n. 206)): for bibliographical details regarding the somatic nature of the Divine according to the Presocratics, Plato, Aristotle, and the Stoics. |
65 | The terms “lysis” and “analysis” are intrinsically related to the meaning of “sôma”. Consequently, their use by the Damascene herein is quite expected, given that his objective is to prove “asômaton”. By maintaining that “sôma”, as subject to “lysis” and “analysis”, is incompatible to God, “asômaton” is suggested as compatible, since it is equivalent to the contradictory genus under which “sôma” comes, i.e., “synthesis”. In this manner, however, the sequence of cataphatic terms continues the sequence of apophatic terms, and for that matter, in a circular fashion. In other words, we are dealing here with a typical case of petitio principii. Moreover, when “asômaton” has been reduced to “asyntheton”, the implied image of an organism—which easily can be reduced to “synthesis”—gives the impression that it facilitates, even though from a negative perspective, what needs to be proved, namely “asômaton”. Of course, all this reasoning does not prove anything apart from the fact that the notion of “sôma” is incompatible to God because this is what the onto-THEO-logical experience of Being requires. However, in the context of a different experience, for instance, the experience of monistic unity, things work quite differently. On the other hand, one could ask the following: what is the purpose of this endless, so to speak, line of notions? I would dare say that it serves no other purpose but the Christian criticism of Hellenism, and for that matter, on the basis of the latter’s own notions. And this is a criticism that ends in appropriating dialectically ancient Greek notions. |
66 | This dialectic constitutes in effect the logical mediation of language with regard to the primary content of divine revelation. The Holy Scriptures as the word of God constitute basically the language of divine revelation. In this respect, they are of the rational but not of the logical order. The Holy Scriptures constitute the first mediation/interpretation of divine revelation, which consequently is broadened towards the direction of a second mediation/re-interpretation on the basis of logical thinking. This shift from one mediation to the other is required, primarily and mainly due to historical reasons—both diachronically and synchronically theology as language is in a state of interaction with its historical contextuality, an interaction that allows it to become a unifying principle of a given historicity, on the one hand, and a way of understanding the latter in light of the meaning of language, on the other. Thus, the dialectics between theological language and logic leads each time to a new use of language that unites the past with the present (cf. typology as a means of hermeneutics or the schema of “Divine Economy”) and also to an explanation of divine revelation that aims at interpreting the historical present. |
67 | In Chapter 17 of the Exact Exposition, the Damascene puts forward the view that only the Divine is truly “aylon” and “asômaton” (SJD II, 45:12–14). Thus, the notion of materiality is logically/semantically equivalent to that of changeability and createdness; put differently, it is understood as the absolute condition of created beings. On the contrary, in the context of the monistic experience of Being, immateriality constitutes the absolute condition of reality; it does not constitute simply a set of beings, but the ontic order (being-ness) itself. Both the intelligible and the sensible belong to this order. Christianity will adopt this Weltanschauung completely but at the same time, will modify it by introducing a transcendent principle. The introduction of such a principle will bring about a dialectics between transcendence and immanence; a dialectics that will eventually lead to the inversion of immanence. The latter will turn from an absolute into a relative condition of Being. |
68 | |
69 | For the entire phrasing of the syllogism, which is a simple categorical syllogism of the first figure (aaa), the major premise of which is based on a certain notional sequence, see SJD II, 12:19–21. |
70 | p (i) [=(“kinoumenon” = “sôma”)] ≠ p (ii) [=(“akinêton” = “asômaton”)]. |
71 | p (ii) [=(“akinêton” = “asômaton”)] ∧ p (iii) [=“theion” = “akinêton”)] ⇒ p (iv) [=(“theion” = “asômaton”)]. |
References
- Ables, Scott. 2015. John of Damascus on Genus and Species. In The Ways of Byzantine Philosophy. Edited by Mikonja Knežević. Alhambra: Sebastian Press, pp. 271–88. [Google Scholar]
- Ables, Scott. 2022a. The Purpose of the Anti-Manichean Polemic of John of Damascus. In John of Damascus: More than a Compiler. Leiden: Brill, pp. 65–85. [Google Scholar]
- Ables, Scott, ed. 2022b. John of Damascus: More than a Compiler. Leiden: Brill. [Google Scholar]
- Adrahtas, Vassilis. 2015. John of Damascus. In The Wiley Blackwell Companion to Patristics. Edited by Ken Parry. Chichester: Blackwell, pp. 264–77. [Google Scholar]
- Adrahtas, Vassilis. 2001a. The Quest: The “Proofs” about the Existence of God. Athens: Sacred/Profane. (In Greek) [Google Scholar]
- Adrahtas, Vassilis. 2001b. The Use of Logic in the Work of John Damascene: Approaches to “Fons Scientiae”. Masters’s thesis, Department of Theology, National and Kapodistrian University of Athens, Athens, Greece. (In Greek). [Google Scholar]
- Adrahtas, Vassilis. 2001c. Mircea Eliade, Le sacré et le profane: ‘Hierophany’ as a Basis for a Theory of Religion. Religious Studies Sacred/Profane 2: 7–19. (In Greek). [Google Scholar]
- Adrahtas, Vassilis. 2003. Theology as Dialectics and the Limits of Patristic Thought in the Post-Modern World: A Reading into St John of Damascus. Phronema 28: 109–27. [Google Scholar]
- Axelos, Kostas. 1962. Héraclite et la philosophie. La première saisie de l’être en devenir de la totalité. Paris: De Minuit. [Google Scholar]
- Batens, Diderik. 1992. Menselijke kennis. Pleidooi voor een bruikbare rationaliteit. Antwerp: Garant. [Google Scholar]
- Begzos, Marios. 1990. Lectures in the Medieval Philosophy of Religion. Athens: Phoitêtikê Enêmerosê. (In Greek) [Google Scholar]
- Bobzien, Susanne. 1986. Die stoische Modallogik. Würzburg: Koenigshausen and Neumann. [Google Scholar]
- Bradshaw, David, and Richard Swinburne, eds. 2021. Natural Theology in the Eastern Orthodox Tradition. St. Paul: IOTA. [Google Scholar]
- Buytaert, Eligius. 1953. Damascenus Latinus. Franciscan Studies 13: 37–70. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Craig, William. 1980. The Cosmological Argument from Plato to Leibniz. London: Macmillan. [Google Scholar]
- During, Ingemar. 1966. Aristoteles. Darstellung und Interpretation seines Denkens. Heidelberg: Carl Winter-Universität. [Google Scholar]
- Eliade, Mircea. 1959. Traité d’histoire des religions. Paris: Payot. [Google Scholar]
- Eliade, Mircea. 1965. Le sacré et le profane. Paris: Gallimard. [Google Scholar]
- Falcon, Andrea. 2023. Aristotle on Causality. The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Edited by Edward Zalta and Uri Nodelman. Available online: https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2023/entries/aristotle-causality (accessed on 5 August 2024).
- Farouki, Nayla. 1996. La foi et la raison. Histoire d’un malentendu. Paris: Flammarion. [Google Scholar]
- Fokin, Alexey. 2021. Natural Theology in Patristic Thought: Arguments for the Existence of God. In Natural Theology in the Eastern Orthodox Tradition. Edited by David Bradshaw and Richard Swinburne. St. Paul: IOTA, pp. 25–50. [Google Scholar]
- Gallow, J. Dmitri. 2022. The Metaphysics of Causation. The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Edited by Edward Zalta and Uri Nodelman. Available online: https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2022/entries/causation-metaphysics (accessed on 5 August 2024).
- Hartmann, Nikolai, Frédéric Tremblay, and Keith R. Peterson. 2017. The Megarian and the Aristotelian Concept of Possibility: A Contribution to the History of the Ontological Problem of Modality. Axiomathes 27: 209–23. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Hawthorne, James. 2024. Inductive Logic. The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Edited by Edward Zalta and Uri Nodelman. Available online: https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2024/entries/logic-inductive (accessed on 5 August 2024).
- Heis, Jeremy. 2018. Neo-Kantianism. The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. [Google Scholar]
- Ierodiakonou, Katerina, ed. 2002. Byzantine Philosophy and its Ancient Sources. Oxford: Oxford University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Kingsley, Scarlett, and Richard Parry. 2020. Empedocles. The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Edited by Edward Zalta. Available online: https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2020/entries/empedocles (accessed on 5 August 2024).
- Kirk, Geoffrey, John Raven, and Malcolm Schofield. 1957. The Presocratic Philosophers. London: Cambridge University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Kneale, William, and Martha Kneale. 1971. The Development of Logic. Oxford: Oxford University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Kontouma, Vassa. 2015. John of Damascus: New Studies on His Life and Work. London: Routledge. [Google Scholar]
- Leftow, Brian. 2005. The Ontological Argument. In The Oxford Handbook of Philosophy of Religion. Edited by William Wainwright. Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 80–115. [Google Scholar]
- Long, A. A. 1974. Hellenistic Philosophy. Stoics, Epicureans, Sceptics. London and New York: Duckworth. [Google Scholar]
- Louth, Andrew. 2001. St John Damascene. Tradition and Originality in Byzantine Theology. Oxford: Oxford University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Lowe, J. Edward. 2007. The Ontological Argument. In The Routledge Companion to Philosophy of Religion. Edited by Chad Meister and Paul Copan. London: Routledge, pp. 331–40. [Google Scholar]
- Manning, Russell, John Brooke, and Fraser Watts, eds. 2013. The Oxford Handbook of Natural Theology. Oxford: Oxford University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Markov, Smilen. 2015. Die Metaphysische Synthese des Johannes von Damaskus: Historische Zusammenhänge und Strukturtransformationen. Leiden: Brill. [Google Scholar]
- Matsoukas, Nikos. 1986. The Problem of Evil: A Patristic Theology Essay. Thessalonikê: Pounaras. (In Greek) [Google Scholar]
- Matsoukas, Nikos. 1994. A History of Byzantine Philosophy. Thessalonikê: Vanias. (In Greek) [Google Scholar]
- McGrath, Alister. 1999. Science and Religion. An Introduction. Oxford: Blackwell. [Google Scholar]
- Nestle, Wilhelm. 1940. Vom Mythos zum Logos. Die Selbstenfaltung des griechischen Denkens von Homer bis auf die Sophistik und Sokrates. Stuttgart: A. Knöner. [Google Scholar]
- Niarchos, G. Konstantinos. 1985. Fundamental Philosophical Notions. Athens: Kardamitsas. (In Greek) [Google Scholar]
- Nissiotis, Nikos. 1986. Philosophy of Religion and Philosophical Theology. Athens: Mênyma. (In Greek) [Google Scholar]
- Oehler, Claus. 1964. Aristotle in Byzantium. Greek, Roman and Byzantine Studies 5: 133–46. [Google Scholar]
- Otto, Rudolph. 2014. Das Heilige: Über das Irrationale in der Idee des Göttlichen und sein Verhältnis zum Rationalen. Munich: C. H. Beck. [Google Scholar]
- Papapetros, Konstantinos. 1979. Passages: Issues in Contemporary Apologetics and Philosophical Criticism. Athens. (In Greek) [Google Scholar]
- Patterson, Richard. 1995. Aristotle’s Modal Logic: Essence and Entailment in the Organon. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Plantinga, Alvin, ed. 1965. The Ontological Argument. New York: Doubleday. [Google Scholar]
- Plexidas, Ioannis. 2001. Person and Nature: Questions Regarding the Notion of Person in the Thought of John Damascene. Skopelos: Nêsides, pp. 23–50. (In Greek) [Google Scholar]
- Richter, Gerhard. 1964. Die Dialektik des Johannes von Damaskos, eine Untersuchungdes Textes nach Quellen und seiner Bedeutung. Studia Patristica et Byzantina 10. Ettal: Buch-Kunstverlag. [Google Scholar]
- Rowe, L. William. 1975. The Cosmological Argument. Princeton: Princeton University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Rozemond, Keetje. 1959. La christologie de saint Jean Damascène. Studia Patristica et Byzantina 8. Ettal: Buch-Kunstverlag. [Google Scholar]
- Siasos, Lambros. 1989. Patristic Critique of Philosophical Methodology. Thessaloniki: Pournaras. (In Greek) [Google Scholar]
- Smith, Abbey-Anne. 2017. Animals in Tillich’s Philosophical Theology. New York: Palgrave Macmillan. [Google Scholar]
- Steiger, Kornél. 2014. The Aristotelian Notion of Proairesis. Rhizomata 2: 33–51. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Studer, Basilius. 1956. Die theologische Arbeitsweise des Johannes von Damaskus. Studia Patristica et Byzantina 2. Ettal: Buch-Kunstverlag. [Google Scholar]
- Svoronos, Nikos. 1987. Comments on the Contribution of Byzantium to the Spiritual Development of Western Europe: The Case of John of Damascus. In Byzantium and Europe. Athens: European Cultural Centre of Delphi, pp. 115–52. (In Greek) [Google Scholar]
- Tatakis, Basile. 1949. Le philosophie byzantine. Paris: Presses Universitaires de France. [Google Scholar]
- Žunjić, Slobodan. 2015. John Damascene’s “Dialectic” as a Bond between Philosophical Tradition and Theology. In The Ways of Byzantine Philosophy. Edited by Mikonja Knežević. Alhambra: Sebastian Press, pp. 227–70. [Google Scholar]
Disclaimer/Publisher’s Note: The statements, opinions and data contained in all publications are solely those of the individual author(s) and contributor(s) and not of MDPI and/or the editor(s). MDPI and/or the editor(s) disclaim responsibility for any injury to people or property resulting from any ideas, methods, instructions or products referred to in the content. |
© 2024 by the author. Licensee MDPI, Basel, Switzerland. This article is an open access article distributed under the terms and conditions of the Creative Commons Attribution (CC BY) license (https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/).
Share and Cite
Adrahtas, V. John Damascene’s Arguments about the Existence of God: A Logico-Philosophical and Religio-Hermeneutic Approach. Religions 2024, 15, 1167. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel15101167
Adrahtas V. John Damascene’s Arguments about the Existence of God: A Logico-Philosophical and Religio-Hermeneutic Approach. Religions. 2024; 15(10):1167. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel15101167
Chicago/Turabian StyleAdrahtas, Vassilios. 2024. "John Damascene’s Arguments about the Existence of God: A Logico-Philosophical and Religio-Hermeneutic Approach" Religions 15, no. 10: 1167. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel15101167
APA StyleAdrahtas, V. (2024). John Damascene’s Arguments about the Existence of God: A Logico-Philosophical and Religio-Hermeneutic Approach. Religions, 15(10), 1167. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel15101167