Love Through Patience: A Contribution to the Kierkegaardian Discussion on the Spiritual Nature of Love Relationships
Abstract
:1. Introduction
2. The Intermediary Character of the Spirit’s Love
2.1. Human Love as a Work and the Neighbor as a Mirror
2.2. The Spirit’s Love as the Break of Identity
The more securely one I and another I join to become one I, the more this united I selfishly cuts itself off from everyone else. (…) This is explainable only because in preferential love there is a natural determinant (drive, inclination) and self-love (…). The spirit’s love, in contrast, takes away from myself all natural determinants and all self-love. Therefore love for the neighbor cannot make me one with the neighbor in a united self. Love for the neighbor is love between two beings eternally and independently determined as spirit; love for the neighbor is spirit’s love, but two spirits are never able to become one self in a selfish sense.
3. Preferential Love into Question
3.1. The Contradiction
3.2. Freedom Comes into Play
4. Patience: Love’s Infinite Movement
5. Conclusions: A Non-Final Word
Funding
Institutional Review Board Statement
Informed Consent Statement
Data Availability Statement
Conflicts of Interest
1 | Due to space constraints, this paper cannot provide a comprehensive overview of Kierkegaard’s thought. Nevertheless, as will be discussed below, love holds immense significance in Kierkegaard’s work. It is intimately tied to the emergence of the human spirit or self and, alongside faith and patience, represents the highest expression of religious existence. The human spirit exists in a tension between time and eternity, where eternity signifies transcendence or exteriority. Within human beings, the presence of eternity manifests as freedom—an intrinsic connection to both finitude and infinitude, without diminishing either. If transcendence defines the existence of the self, it is also something that must be embraced internally. Throughout Kierkegaard’s writings, this paradoxical nature of human existence is articulated through the concept of spirit. Spirit is not a fixed identity but rather a self-relating relationship between finitude and infinitude. The actuality of the human being as spirit is, therefore, the ability of both realities to relate itself to itself and thus be free. Faith, described as a leap, is the act of freedom that recognizes eternity within human beings. However, spirit cannot become itself in isolation. Freedom does not exist apart from the world and others, and the concrete recognition of eternity occurs through the acts of love we undertake. Faith’s counterpart, then, is love, which serves as both the origin and culmination of human existence and is deeply rooted in temporal existence through patience. Kierkegaard’s anthropological perspective on these themes is explored primarily in Works of Love, Fear and Trembling, The Concept of Anxiety, and The Sickness Unto Death as well as in his Upbuilding Discourses, which address love, patience, and temporality among other themes. |
2 | “Speaking exaggeratedly, in Kierkegaard’s doctrine of Love the object of love is, in a way, irrelevant.” (Adorno 1939, p. 415). “The rigorousness of the love advocated by Kierkegaard partially devaluates the beloved person” (Adorno 1939, p. 416). “This is the absurd, the wreckage of the finite by the infinite which Kierkegaard hypostatizes. The command to love is commanded because of its impossibility. This, however, amounts to nothing less than the annihilation of love and the installment of sinister domination” (Adorno 1939, p. 418). |
3 | See, e.g., K. E. Løgstrup’s criticism: “And the issue is heightened further when Kierkegaard starts to speak about erotic love. If the selfishness involved here is to be killed, he says, it is not sufficient that the beloved person is taken away from the person in love; no, he himself has to give her up. (…) In Christianity it is not cruel to be cruel, because this is the only thing that can save one from ruin” (Løgstrup 2023, pp. 41–42). |
4 | “This allegedly firm distinction has been challenged by a newer generation of scholars who have demonstrated that these types of love are not defined by mutual exclusion but are interrelated” (Hanson 2022, p. 196). |
5 | When quoting Kierkegaard’s works, I first refer to the Princeton translation by Edward and Edna Hong, followed by the volume and page number of the original Danish edition (Søren Kierkegaards Skrifter, abbreviated SKS). |
6 | Anti-Climacus is one of the several pseudonyms that make up Kierkegaard’s authorship. He is the author of The Sickness Unto Death. |
7 | Contradiction always presents a task and in doing so, sets history in motion (see Kierkegaard 1980a, p. 49/SKS 1997–2013, 4, 354). |
8 | “(…) We are placed outside of ourselves and where we can see ourselves as a stranger” (Grøn 2008, p. 87). |
9 | According to the Danish philosopher Arne Grøn, “the self is not the relation itself, but rather the relation’s act of relating to itself in such a way that the self emerges from what is intrinsic to the relation—namely, its opening of that which lies in between, what Kierkegaard refers to as existence” (Hansen et al. 2020, p. 117). |
10 | “But what, in the spiritual sense, is the ground and foundation of the spiritual life that is to bear the building? It is love. Love is the source of everything and, in the spiritual sense, love is the deepest ground of the spiritual life” (Kierkegaard 1995, p. 215/SKS 1997–2013, 9, 218). |
11 | It is already underlined by Amanda Houmark (see Houmark 2018) and especially by Elizabeth Li and René Rosfort (see Li and Rosfort 2024). |
12 | That love is a matter of conscience, and that God or the good always mediates in every loving relationship, also means that coming to love involves a ceaseless struggle against evil. It is an effort to ensure that love remains in its element, leaving no room for the infinite capacity of evil to find its place in the world. |
13 | “By the sensuous, the flesh, Christianity understands selfishness. A conflict between spirit and flesh is inconceivable unless there is a rebellious spirit on the side of flesh, with which the spirit then contends (…). Therefore, self-love is sensuousness. Christianity has misgivings about erotic love and friendship simply because preferential love in passion or passionate preference is actually another form of self-love.” (Kierkegaard 1995, pp. 52–53/SKS 1997–2013, 9, 59). |
14 | However, Kierkegaard distinguishes between a devoted and an unfaithful self-love, insofar as both kinds of self-love fall under the dominion of preference and are always corrected by self-denial, which “is also two-edged in such a way that it cuts off both sides equally” (See Kierkegaard 1995, pp. 53, 55/SKS 1997–2013, 9, 61, 62). |
15 | “Yet this love is not proudly independent of its object. Its equality [Ligelighed] does not appear in love’s proudly turning back into itself through indifference [Ligegyldighed] to the object—no, the equality appears in love’s humbly turning outward, embracing everyone, and yet loving each one individually but no one exceptionally” (Kierkegaard 1995, p. 67/SKS 1997–2013, 9, 73). |
16 | See Kierkegaard (1995, p. /SKS 1997–2013, 9, 142): “Christianity has begun from the foundation and therefore with the Spirit’s doctrine of what love is. In order to determine what love is, it begins either with God or with the neighbor, a doctrine about love that is the essentially Christian doctrine, since one, in order in love to find the neighbor, must start from God and must find God in love to the neighbor. From this foundation, Christianity now takes possession of every expression of love and is jealous for itself. Thus one can say that it is the doctrine about the human being’s God-relationship that has made erotic love a matter of conscience just as well as one can say that it is the doctrine of love for the neighbor. Both are equally the Christian objection to the self-willfulness of drives and inclination”. |
17 | “(…) a human being, even if from the moment of birth he is spirit, still does not become conscious of himself as spirit until later and thus has sensately-psychically acted out a certain part of his life prior to this. But this first portion is not to be cast aside when the spirit awakens any more than the awakening of the spirit in contrast to the sensate-psychical announces itself in a sensate-psychical way. On the contrary, the first portion is taken over [overtage] by the spirit and, used in this way, is thus made the basis-it becomes the metaphorical” (Kierkegaard 1995, p. 209/SKS 1997–2013, 9, 212). |
18 | See Nygren (1982, p. 12). Krishek also assimilates Elskov and Kjerlighed to eros and agape, although she considers, in complete opposition to Nygren, that both forms of love can coexist (see Krishek 2009, p. 154). |
19 | “Therefore, when we love our romantic beloveds correctly, we always love them in a neighbourly way as well (but not viceversa, of course)” (see Krishek 2009, p. 153). |
20 | René Rosfort and Elizabeth Li draw on the inherent ambiguity of love to critique the confident affirmations of romantic love advanced by the new generation of Kierkegaard scholars. This group includes not only Krishek but also Ferreira, Evans, Lippitt, Furtak, Hannay, Hughes, Strawser, Davenport, Marandiuc, and Hanson. Li and Rosfort emphasize the role of anxiety in love, arguing that it underscores the ambiguity of the phenomenon—an aspect that should not be overlooked in any serious consideration of its significance in human life (see Li and Rosfort 2024). |
21 | The apprehension of everything related to existence can never be captured in an abstract form: “(…) in relation to existential concepts it always indicates a greater discretion to abstain from definitions, because a person can hardly be inclined to apprehend essentially in the form of a definition what must be understood differently, what he himself has understood differently, what he has loved in an entire different way, and which in the form of definition easily becomes something else, something foreign to him” (Kierkegaard 1980a, p. 147/SKS 1997–2013, 4, 447). |
22 | See Kierkegaard (1995, p. 3/SKS 1997–2013, 9, 11): “Something that in its total richness is essentially inexhaustible is also in its smallest work essentially indescribable just because essentially it is totally present everywhere and essentially cannot be described”. |
23 | “Our experience of norms and values is, in other words, accompanied by an anxiety that constantly destabilizes our categorical distinctions between right and wrong, good and bad, appropriate and inappropriate” (Rosfort 2018, p. 36). |
24 | “The thorn in the flesh” became a warning, a reminder, that wherever a person goes he walks in danger, that even the one who grasps at the highest is still only aspiring to it (…)” (Kierkegaard 1990, p. 331/SKS 1997–2013, 5, 321). |
25 | “The soul is a “contradiction” or tension between eternity and temporality. Within time it can only be possessed by being constantly gained. Therefore, to “gain” my soul is not something that can be done once for all; it is a process that I am engaged in throughout my life, one that does not issue in secure results on which I can then sit comfortably back, but one that must be renewed in every moment” (Rudd 2008, pp. 499–500). |
26 | This transformation would impact the key concepts that belong to the realm of the upbuilding: expectancy, patience, resolution, and concern (see Durand 2020, pp. 10–12). |
27 | The relationship between love and patience has been explored by various thinkers. For instance, Emmanuel Levinas emphasizes patience as an essential way of engaging with otherness (see Levinas 2013, p. 90). However, Levinas considers the concept of “love” to be both dangerous and ambiguous, viewing it as a commanded act—an absolute exigency (see Levinas 2009, p. 5). In contrast, the dialectic between action and passion in Kierkegaard’s thought, which renders love ambiguous, presents a significant departure from Levinas’s treatment of love. More recently, from a Kierkegaardian perspective, Amber Bowen argues that patience is intrinsically linked to the constitution of the self (see Bowen 2024). |
References
- Adorno, Theodor. 1939. On Kierkegaard’s doctrine of love. Zeitschrift für Sozialforschung 8: 413–29. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Bowen, Amber. 2024. To Gain One’s Soul: Kierkegaard and the Hermeneutical Virtue of Patience. Religions 15: 317. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- De Gramont, Jérôme. 2001. Le Discours de la Vie. Trois Essais sur Platon, Kierkegaard et Nietzsche. Paris: L’Harmattan. [Google Scholar]
- Durand, Émeline. 2020. L’élément de l’esprit et sa souffrance. Éternité et temporalité dans les Discours Édifiants de Kierkegaard. Les Études philosophiques 1: 3–16. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Evans, C. Stephen. 2004. Kierkegaard’s Ethic of Love: Divine Commands and Moral Obligations. New York: Oxford University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Ferreira, Jamie M. 2001. Love’s Grateful Striving: A Commentary on Kierkegaard’s Works of Love. Oxford: Oxford University Press. [Google Scholar]
- García-Baró, Miguel. 2021. Mística Coral. Revista de Espiritualidad 80: 479–500. [Google Scholar]
- González, Darío. 1998. Poetics and the ‘Being’ of Love. Kierkegaard Studies Yearbook 1998: 129–46. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Grøn, Arne. 1998. Kierkegaards ‘zweite’ Ethik. Kierkegaard Studies Yearbook, 358–68. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Grøn, Arne. 2001. Spirit and Temporality in The Concept of Anxiety. Kierkegaard Studies Yearbook 2001: 128–40. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Grøn, Arne. 2008. The Concept of Anxiety in Søren Kierkegaard. Translated by Jeanette B. L. Knox. Macon: Mercer University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Hansen, Bjarke Mørkøre Stigel, Mads Peter Karlsen, and René Rosfort. 2020. Arne Grøn’s Existential Hermeneutics: Existence, Ethics and Religion. Danish Yearbook of Philosophy 53: 108–32. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Hanson, Jeffrey. 2022. “That Is Giving a Banquet”: Neighbor-Love as Spiritualization of Romantic Loves in Works of Love. Journal of Religious Ethics 50: 196–218. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Houmark, Amanda. 2018. Subjectivity and Ambiguity: Anxiety and Love in Kierkegaard. Kierkegaard Studies Yearbook 23: 55–73. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Kierkegaard, Søren. 1980a. The Concept of Anxiety. Princeton: Princeton University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Kierkegaard, Søren. 1980b. The Sickness unto Death. Princeton: Princeton University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Kierkegaard, Søren. 1985. Philosophical Fragments. Princeton: Princeton University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Kierkegaard, Søren. 1990. Eighteen Upbuilding Discourses. Princeton: Princeton University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Kierkegaard, Søren. 1993. Upbuilding Discourses in Various Spirits. Princeton: Princeton University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Kierkegaard, Søren. 1995. Works of Love. Princeton: Princeton University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Kierkegaard, Søren. 1997–2013. Søren Kierkegaards Skrifter. Copenhagen: Gads Forlag. [Google Scholar]
- Krishek, Sharon. 2008. Two forms of love. The problem of Preferential Love in Kierkegaard’s Works of Love. Journal of Religious Ethics 35: 595–617. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Krishek, Sharon. 2009. Kierkegaard on Faith and Love. New York: Cambridge University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Krishek, Sharon. 2013. In defence of a faith-like model of love: A reply to John Lippitt’s “Kierkegaard and the problem of special relationships: Ferreira, Krishek, and the ‘God filter’”. International Journal for Philosophy of Religion 75: 155–66. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Krishek, Sharon. 2022. Lovers in Essence. A Kierkegaardian Defense of Romantic Love. New York: Oxford University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Levinas, Emmanuel. 2009. Filosofía, justicia y amor. Topologik. Revista Internacional de Ciencias de la Filosofía. Study Filosofici 6: 1–16. [Google Scholar]
- Levinas, Emmanuel. 2013. Autrement qu’être ou au delà de l’essence. Paris: Le Livre de Poche. [Google Scholar]
- Li, Elizabeth, and René Rosfort. 2024. Anxious Love: Romantic Love as an Existence-Concept in Kierkegaard’s Ethics. Manuscript submitted for publication. [Google Scholar]
- Lippitt, John. 2012. Kierkegaard and the problem of special relationships: Ferreira, Krishek and the ‘God filter’. International Journal for Philosophy of Religion 72: 177–97. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Llevadot, Laura. 2011. La muerte del otro: Kierkegaard, Levinas, Derrida. Convivium 24: 103–17. [Google Scholar]
- Løgstrup, Knud Ejler. 2023. Controverting Kierkegaard. New York: Oxford University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Nygren, Anders. 1982. Agape and Eros. London: SPCK. [Google Scholar]
- Rosfort, René. 2018. Kierkegaard and the Problem of Ethics. In Hermeneutics and Negativism: Existential Ambiguities of Self-Understanding. Edited by Claudia Welz and René Rosfort. Tübingen: Mohr Siebeck, pp. 33–51. [Google Scholar]
- Rudd, Anthony. 2008. Kierkegaard on Patience and the Temporality of the Self: The Virtues of a Being in Time. Journal of Religious Ethics 36: 499–500. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Viñas, Ángel. 2017. S. Kierkegaard: Una Teoría del Cielo. Doctoral dissertation, Universidad Pontificia Comillas, Madrid, Spain. [Google Scholar]
- Viñas, Ángel. 2022. La paciencia en Kierkegaard. Veritas 51: 9–33. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
Disclaimer/Publisher’s Note: The statements, opinions and data contained in all publications are solely those of the individual author(s) and contributor(s) and not of MDPI and/or the editor(s). MDPI and/or the editor(s) disclaim responsibility for any injury to people or property resulting from any ideas, methods, instructions or products referred to in the content. |
© 2024 by the author. Licensee MDPI, Basel, Switzerland. This article is an open access article distributed under the terms and conditions of the Creative Commons Attribution (CC BY) license (https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/).
Share and Cite
Carpintero, R. Love Through Patience: A Contribution to the Kierkegaardian Discussion on the Spiritual Nature of Love Relationships. Religions 2024, 15, 1372. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel15111372
Carpintero R. Love Through Patience: A Contribution to the Kierkegaardian Discussion on the Spiritual Nature of Love Relationships. Religions. 2024; 15(11):1372. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel15111372
Chicago/Turabian StyleCarpintero, Raquel. 2024. "Love Through Patience: A Contribution to the Kierkegaardian Discussion on the Spiritual Nature of Love Relationships" Religions 15, no. 11: 1372. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel15111372
APA StyleCarpintero, R. (2024). Love Through Patience: A Contribution to the Kierkegaardian Discussion on the Spiritual Nature of Love Relationships. Religions, 15(11), 1372. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel15111372