Aquinas, Suicide, and Communities of Faith
Abstract
:1. Introduction
Finley’s research also suggests that those in the church who have mental health disorders are currently attempting to create meaning from their suffering within the context of their faith (Finley 2023a, 2023b). Thus, the church should consider what role it can play in helping those struggling with suicidal ideation. In this paper, I will use the thought of Thomas Aquinas to suggest some ways that the church can help those struggling with suicidal ideation or thoughts of suicide (Van Orden et al. 2010, p. 576). My conversation about mental health will focus on how those in Christian faith communities can help those who are a part of the church who struggle with suicidal ideation. At first glance, Aquinas seems a strange starting point for this conversation. While Aquinas is an authoritative voice in the Christian tradition, he argues that suicide is wrong. However, I will argue that when we incorporate what Aquinas has to say about friendship, especially as it concerns the virtue of charity, we can find some insight for thinking about how to help people struggling with suicidal ideation.Notably, those in the US with mental health concerns are more likely to seek help from spiritual or religious leaders than from psychologists or psychiatrists combined (Heseltine-Carp and Hoskins 2020; Oppenheimer et al. 2004)—thus resulting in spiritual and religious leaders often acting as ‘frontline’ mental health care workers and ‘gatekeepers’ to mental health treatment and services.
2. Aquinas on the Wrongness of Suicide
From nature, we learn that whatever exists seeks to preserve its own life and well-being. The person who commits suicide, however, acts contrary to that natural desire to keep existing and flourishing (Novak 1975, pp. 44–54; Leget 2002, esp pp. 289–93). Aquinas also says that suicide undercuts the charity that a person ought to have for themselves. Charity is a gift from God (ST II-II. q23. a1; see also Aquinas, Commentary on the Sentences I. 17 (Lectura Romana). q1 a.1).4 One way to define mortal sin is as the rupturing or destroying of the bond of charity between God and a human person (see ST I-II. q88).5 Because suicide is a rejection of charity, “Suicide, then, becomes not only a rejection of man’s love for himself but of God’s love for man” (Novak 1975, p. 53).6because everything naturally loves itself, the result being that everything naturally keeps itself in being, and resists corruptions so far as it can. Wherefore suicide is contrary to the inclination of nature, and to charity whereby every man should love himself. Hence suicide is always a mortal sin, as being contrary to the natural law and to charity.(ST II-II. q64. a5)
Our birth date and death dates are under God’s providence, not our own power, and to take one’s own life is, according to Aquinas, to try to take what belongs to God (Novak 1975, pp. 70–71; see also Stump 2003, pp. 331–32).life is God’s gift to man, and is subject to His power, Who kills and makes to live. Hence whoever takes his own life, sins against God, even as he who kills another’s slave, sins against that slave’s master, and as he who usurps to himself judgment of a matter not entrusted to him. For it belongs to God alone to pronounce sentence of death and life, according to Dt. 32:39, “I will kill and I will make to live.”(ST II-II. q64. a5)
3. Aquinas on Justice
Because justice in this sense directs us to the common good, justice, as Aquinas has described things here, may also be termed “legal justice”. Aquinas continues in the same section of the Summa Theologiae thatJustice, as stated above (a2) directs man in his relations with other men. Now this may happen in two ways: first as regards his relation with individuals, secondly as regards his relations with others in general, in so far as a man who serves a community, serves all those who are included in that community. Accordingly justice in its proper acceptation can be directed to another in both these senses. Now it is evident that all who are included in a community, stand in relation to that community as parts to a whole; while a part, as such, belongs to a whole, so that whatever is the good of a part can be directed to the good of the whole. It follows therefore that the good of any virtue, whether such virtue direct man in relation to himself, or in relation to certain other individual persons, is referable to the common good, to which justice directs: so that all acts of virtue can pertain to justice, in so far as it directs man to the common good. It is in this sense that justice is called a general virtue.(II-II. q58 a5)
Now legal justice is not directed toward particular individuals, meaning that it does not govern what particular good is due to some particular person. Thus, Aquinas says thatAnd since it belongs to the law to direct to the common good, as stated above (I. q90. a2.), it follows that the justice which is in this way styled general, is called “legal justice,” because thereby man is in harmony with the law which directs the acts of all the virtues to the common good.(II-II. q58 a5; see also ST II-II. q58. a6; see also Leget 2002)
And he also continues in this same section by arguing thatbesides legal justice which directs man immediately to the common good, there is a need for other virtues to direct him immediately in matters relating to particular goods: and these virtues may be relative to himself or to another individual person. Accordingly, just as in addition to legal justice there is a need for particular virtues to direct man in relation to himself, such as temperance and fortitude, so too besides legal justice there is need for particular justice to direct man in his relations to other individuals.(ST II-II. q58. a7)
Thus, Aquinas argues that we need a different division of justice for those items that pertain to the rights of the individual: particular justice. Farrell notes thatThe common good of the realm and the particular good of the individual differ not only in respect of the “many” and the “few”, but also under a formal aspect. For the aspect of the “common” good differs from the aspect of the “individual” good, even as the aspect of “whole” differs from that of “part”.(ST II-II. q58. a7. Reply to Objection 2)
Legal justice, then, is acting for the sake of the common good. This does not mean simply following the law because we are commanded to by authorities but rather that one is “following the law so as to perform virtuous acts for the sake of the common good” (Farrell 2018).Since justice is the virtue that disposes us to treat others correctly, there has to be a form of justice that disposes us to respect the good of the other qua single person. Unlike general justice, this form of justice is not an all-encompassing general virtue, but covers a limited area of human action. It can be called particular justice.
Both distributive justice and commutative justice concern the proper distribution of goods (ST II-II q61 a1, Replies to Objections), but distributive and commutative justice distribute goods in different ways. Of distributive justice, Aquinas says thatparticular justice is directed to the private individual, who is compared to the community as a part to the whole. Now a twofold order may be considered in relation to a part. In the first place there is the order of one part to another, to which corresponds the order of one private individual to another. This order is directed by commutative justice, which is concerned about the mutual dealings between two persons. In the second place there is the order of the whole towards the parts, to which corresponds the order of that which belongs to the community in relation to each single person. This order is directed by distributive justice, which distributes common goods proportionately. Hence there are two species of justice, distributive and commutative.(ST II-II. q61. a1)
An example of this kind of proportional justice would be wages paid for work performed. So, for example, if Matthew works a 12 h shift, but Cassondra works a 6 h shift, distributive justice dictates that Matthew be paid more because he has worked the longer shift. In other words, in distributive justice, desert matters for how much of the common good one receives. Stump comments that,in distributive justice something is given to a private individual, in so far as what belongs to the whole is due to the part, and in a quantity that is proportionate to the importance of the position of that part in respect of the whole. Consequently in distributive justice a person receives all the more of the common goods, according as he holds a more prominent position in the community. This prominence in an aristocratic community is gauged according to virtue, in an oligarchy according to wealth, in a democracy according to liberty, and in various ways according to various forms of community. Hence in distributive justice the mean is observed, not according to equality between thing and thing, but according to proportion between things and persons: in such a way that even as one person surpasses another, so that which is given to one person surpasses that which is allotted to another. Hence the Philosopher says (Ethic. v, 3,4) that the mean in the latter case follows “geometrical proportion”, wherein equality depends not on quantity but on proportion.(ST II-II q61 a2)
But of commutative justice, Aquinas says that,Any society has certain common goods to distribute…and certain burdens to impose. …Just distribution is thus proportional to desert but what counts as desert varies from society to society. In aristocracies, it is virtue, Aquinas says; in oligarchies, wealth or nobility of birth. In democracy, it is being a free citizen, so that the goods of society are equally distributed to all.
An example of this kind of justice would be economic trade between individuals in a society. If Jerry buys a car that is worth $5000 from Sophia, then he should pay Sophia the value of the car, $5000. In this way, both Jerry and Sophia come away from the transaction with something that is worth $5000, and commutative justice, which demands equality of “thing with thing”, is upheld.10in commutations something is paid to an individual on account of something of his that has been received, as may be seen chiefly in selling and buying, where the notion of commutation is found primarily. Hence it is necessary to equalize thing with thing, so that the one person should pay back to the other just so much as he has become richer out of that which belonged to the other. The result of this will be equality according to the “arithmetical mean” which is gauged according to equal excess in quantity.(ST II-II q61 a2)
4. What Kind of Injustice Is Suicide?
When thinking in terms of legal justice, Aquinas thinks that when someone commits suicide, the wrong committed is committed against the state. He argues that “the man who commits suicide does some injustice. But we must consider against whom he acts unjustly. Certainly he does an injustice to the state, which he deprives of a citizen, even if he does no injustice to himself” (CNE V. Lecture XVII. 1094). For Aquinas, one motivation for thinking that suicide violates legal justice is the punishments and dishonors that the State imposes on those who commit suicide (ibid., V. Lecture XVII. 1096).11the things that are just according to any virtue are ordered by law. Hence what is not ordered at all by law does not seem to be just in terms of any virtue and hence is unjust. In no case does the law command a man to take his own life. But those acts that the law does not command as just, it forbids as unjust. This is not to be understood as if no mean exists between the command and the prohibition of the law, since there are many acts that are neither commanded nor forbidden by the law but are left to man’s will, for example, buying or not buying a particular thing. But this is to be understood in the sense that it is only those things which are forbidden as unjust in themselves that the law in no case commands. So it seems that to take one’s own life is of itself unjust, since the law never commands it.(CNE V. Lecture XVII. 1092)
5. What Are Faith Communities to Do?
6. The Psychological Literature on Suicide and Suicidal Ideation
7. Aquinas on Charity: A Shift in Thinking About How to Love One Another
As Leget reads Aquinas, because Aquinas sees the aim of the moral life to be human happiness, Aquinas thinks that the task of the human person is to improve oneself. This improvement involves finding a balance of the goods of human life, and the point of natural inclination is to point us in the direction of these goods. If committing suicide is against natural inclination, then, on Leget’s view, suicide becomes a disruption of the “natural dynamism” of obtaining these human goods (Leget 2002, p. 291). Leget also argues that we can see the different ways in which suicide is wrong as different relationships: to oneself, to one’s community, and to God, and these relationships, considered as goods, require a kind of receptivity. He says that,Thomas does not consider justice to be the same as law and external obligation, but primarily, to be a virtue of the human will. And as a virtue, justice is essentially the art of balance. Now we enter a different realm of thinking: we enter the language of harmony, on the Stoic foundations of which Aquinas developed his theory of sin. Reading Sth II-II, q. 64 a. 5 co in this light, suicide appears as the ultimate act of disharmony or imbalance.
Now the badness of suicide can be seen in that it undercuts the flourishing of a human life. Leget writes that,The vital level, the social level, and the religious level are three dimensions that sustain life and that cannot be disposed of completely. All three of them are essential to the goods that are constitutive of the good life. To put it differently: all three of them ask for a specific attitude of accepting, and of being open to the goods that we cannot produce or make; goods that make life worth living.
Leget points out that this “objective disorder” is where the wrongness and injustice of suicide truly lie (Ibid., p. 292).Losing the balance of these three relationships, human life becomes a life that is threatened in that which concerns the access to the good. A life that is lived without having access to oneself, cut off from social bonds and without any hope, is a dead end. Thus suicide appears as an act of objective disorder, running contrary to the three dimensions that sustain life and make it valuable.
8. What Aquinas Has to Say About Charity
This divine assistance comes in the form of charity, and this form results in the human person being made like God in such a way that they can enjoy him.18 Aquinas argues thatwhatever exceeds the limitations of a nature cannot accrue to it except through the action of another being. For instance, water does not tend upward unless it is moved by something else. Now, seeing God’s substance transcends the limitations of every created nature; indeed, it is proper for each created intellectual nature to understand according to the manner of its own substance. But divine substance cannot be understood in this way, as we showed above. Therefore, the attainment by a created intellect to the vision of divine substance is not possible except through the action of God, Who transcends all creatures. Thus, it is said: “The grace of God is life everlasting” (Rom. 6:23). In fact, we have shown that man’s happiness, which is called life everlasting, consists in this divine vision, and we are said to attain it by God’s grace alone, because such a vision exceeds all the capacity of a creature and it is not possible to reach it without divine assistance.(SCG III. 52. vi–vii) 17
What affects this participation in the divine likeness for Aquinas is the form of charity. According to Aquinas,Indeed, it is not possible for what is the proper form of one thing to become the form of another unless the latter thing participates some likeness of the thing to which the form belongs. For instance, light can only become the act of a body if the body participates somewhat in the diaphanous. But the divine essence is the proper intelligible form for the divine intellect and is proportioned to it; in fact, these three are one in God: the intellect, that whereby understanding is accomplished, and the object which is understood. So, it is impossible for this essence to become the intelligible form of a created intellect unless by virtue of the fact that the created intellect participates in the divine likeness. Therefore, this participation in the divine likeness is necessary so that the substance of God may be seen.(SCG III. 53. ii)
In other words, Aquinas thinks that human persons need to be given the form of charity for them to be able to see and enjoy God. In his Commentary on the Sentences of Peter Lombard, Aquinas makes the point more succinctly that the form of charity is that,Furthermore, nothing can be elevated to a higher operation unless because its power is strengthened. But there are two possible ways in which a thing’s power may be strengthened. One way is by a simple intensification of the power itself; thus, the active power of a hot thing is increased by an intensification of the heat, so that it is able to perform a stronger action of the same species. A second way is by the imposition of a new form; thus, the power of a diaphanous object is increased so that it can shine with light, by virtue of its becoming actually luminous, through the form of light received for the first time within it. And in fact, this latter kind of increase of power is needed for the acquisition of an operation of another species. Now, the power of a created intellect is not sufficient to see the divine substance, as is clear from what we have said. So, its power must be increased in order that it may attain such a vision. But the increase through the intensification of a natural power does not suffice, since this vision is not of the same essential type as the vision proper to a natural created intellect. This is evident from the difference between the objects of these visions. Therefore, an increase of the intellectual power by means of the acquisition of a new disposition must be accomplished.(SCG III. 53. v)
The point at which the believer receives the form of charity from God is the point at which she also begins to love the goodness which God is. According to Aquinas, when we are genuinely in a union of love, we also begin to desire what the beloved desires (Commentary on the Sentences, III. d.32 a. 1–2). As Aquinas sees things, God desires the goodness that he is, and if the believer loves God, she will also desire what God desires. Thus, to possess charity means that one is also shaped by the goodness that God is (see ST I.q2.a3; I.q3.a4; I.q6.a3; I.q3.a3; I–II.q26.a1; I-II.q27.a1).20by which man transcends all effects and every creature and directs his affection to God himself and loves the very goodness of God as our beatitude, so that we may have a certain fellowship with him; and this is altogether above nature and natural reason. Hence in order to love God in this way, a supernatural light is required, which elevates our affection to God himself, according as he is to be loved in and of himself.(I. 17 (Lectura Romana) q.1. a.1.)19
Charity, for Aquinas, makes us God’s friends, but charity also extends to the love of others, including our enemies. Aquinas argues that,since there is a communication between man and God, inasmuch as He communicates His happiness to us, some kind of friendship must needs be based on this same communication, of which it is written (1 Cor. 1:9): “God is faithful: by Whom you are called unto the fellowship of His Son.” The love, which is based on this communication, is charity: wherefore it is evident that charity is the friendship of man for God.(ST II-II. q23. a1)
In fact, Aquinas says that, when one possesses charity, they love their neighbor “for God’s sake” (ST II-II. q25. a1. Reply to Objection 3). As Meghan Clark succinctly puts it, “God is to be loved above all else, and all other things are to be loved in relation to God” (Clark 2011, p. 419).Now the aspect under which our neighbor is to be loved, is God, since what we ought to love in our neighbor is that he may be in God. Hence it is clear that it is specifically the same act whereby we love God, and whereby we love our neighbor. Consequently the habit of charity extends not only to the love of God, but also to the love of our neighbor.(ST II-II. q25. a1; see also ST II-II. q27. a8)
Aquinas points out that, in friendship, we desire another person’s good, not for the good itself, but rather for the sake of the friend.As the Philosopher says (Rhet. ii, 4), “to love is to wish good to someone.” Hence the movement of love has a twofold tendency: towards the good which a man wishes to someone (to himself or to another) and towards that to which he wishes some good. Accordingly, man has love of concupiscence towards the good that he wishes to another, and love of friendship towards him to whom he wishes good.(ST II-II. q26. a4)
Furthermore, Aquinas writes in ST I. q20. a1. Reply to objection 3:Union belongs to love in so far as by reason of the complacency of the appetite, the lover stands in relation to that which he loves, as though it were himself or part of himself. Hence it is clear that love is not the very relation of union, but that union is a result of love. Hence, too, Dionysius says that “love is a unitive force” (Div. Nom. iv), and the Philosopher says (Polit. ii, 1) that union is the work of love.(ST II-II. q26. a2. Reply to Objection 2)
Notice that Aquinas emphasizes that when we truly love someone, their flourishing matters to us as much as our own. Aquinas says that,An act of love always tends towards two things; to the good that one wills, and to the person for whom one wills it: since to love a person is to wish that person good. Hence, inasmuch as we love ourselves, we wish ourselves good; and, so far as possible, union with that good. So love is called the unitive force, even in God, yet without implying composition; for the good that He wills for Himself, is no other than Himself, Who is good by His essence, as above shown [citation omitted]. And by the fact that anyone loves another, he wills good to that other. Thus he puts the other, as it were, in the place of himself; and regards the good done to him as done to himself. So far love is a binding force, since it aggregates another to ourselves, and refers his good to our own. And then again the divine love is a binding force, inasmuch as God wills good to others; yet it implies no composition in God.
Thus, for Aquinas, if we genuinely have charity toward another person, we cannot ignore their well-being. The other person becomes as dear to us as we are to ourselves. When I love another person, I desire on their behalf what is good for them. This seems obvious at first but notice that Aquinas also thinks that we care so much for the well-being of others that their good is as dear to us as our own well-being. Thus, love requires that we deeply care about the well-being of others. Love requires that the flourishing of others matter to us (see Stump 2006; 2010, chaps. 5 and 6).21Whereas, in the love of friendship, the lover is in the beloved, inasmuch as he reckons what is good or evil to his friend, as being so to himself; and his friend’s will as his own, so that it seems as though he felt the good or suffered the evil in the person of his friend. Hence it is proper to friends “to desire the same things, and to grieve and rejoice at the same”, as the Philosopher says (Ethic. ix, 3 and Rhet. ii, 4). Consequently in so far as he reckons what affects his friend as affecting himself, the lover seems to be in the beloved, as though he were become one with him: but in so far as, on the other hand, he wills and acts for his friend’s sake as for his own sake, looking on his friend as identified with himself, thus the beloved is in the lover.(ST I-II. q28. a2)
For Aquinas, friends are a source of comfort and joy. Aquinas writes that,it is not only proper to love that one reveal his secrets to a friend by reason of their unity in affection, but the same unity requires that what he has he have in common with the friend. For, “since a man has a friend as another self,” he must help the friend as he does himself, making his own possessions common with the friend, and so one takes this as the property of friendship “to will and to do the good for a friend”.(SCG IV. 21. 7)
A feature of Aquinas’s discussion of friendship that should stand out is this idea of a shared life. Aquinas emphasizes the unity and shared life between friends. Friends share the joys, the sorrows, and the goods of normal life.It is also a property of friendship that one take delight in a friend’s presence, rejoice in his words and deeds, and find in him security against all anxieties; and so it is especially in our sorrows that we hasten to our friends for consolation.(SCG IV. 22. 3)
In this same vein, Aquinas claims that we are to love the unvirtuous, again because of our love for God in charity:Indeed so much do we love our friends, that for their sake we love all who belong to them, even if they hurt or hate us; so that, in this way, the friendship of charity extends even to our enemies, whom we love out of charity in relation to God, to Whom the friendship of charity is chiefly directed.(ST II-II. q23. a1. Reply to Objection 2)
As Aquinas sees things, love of God means that we love neighbors, enemies, and those who are unvirtuous or the “sinner” (Clark 2011, p. 416). For Aquinas, charity requires that we love all others within our community. In fact, this community is quite extensive. Clark notes that, “From the beginning, Aquinas is clear that charity extends to one’s neighbors, by which he means the entire human community. It is clear that one is to love one’s neighbor as part of charity” (Ibid., p. 418).The friendship that is based on the virtuous is directed to none but a virtuous man as the principal person, but for his sake we love those who belong to him, even though they be not virtuous: in this way charity, which above all is friendship based on the virtuous, extends to sinners, whom, out of charity, we love for God’s sake.(ST II-II. q23. a1. Reply to Objection 3)
However, Aquinas’s view that we should help those more closely connected to us is not a hard and fast rule: There are times when someone’s need creates exceptions to helping those closest to us (see also Clark 2011; Pope 1991). When commenting on whom we are to show beneficence, which is an act of charity (ST II-II. q31. a1; see also Clark 2011, p. 423), Aquinas argues thatout of charity, we love more those who are more nearly connected with us, since we love them in more ways. For, towards those who are not connected with us we have no other friendship than charity, whereas for those who are connected with us, we have certain other friendships, according to the way in which they are connected. Now since the good on which every other friendship of the virtuous is based, is directed, as to its end, to the good on which charity is based, it follows that charity commands each act of another friendship, even as the art which is about the end commands the art which is about the means. Consequently this very act of loving someone because he is akin or connected with us, or because he is a fellow-countryman or for any like reason that is referable to the end of charity, can be commanded by charity, so that, out of charity both eliciting and commanding, we love in more ways those who are more nearly connected with us.(ST II-II. q26. a7)
For Aquinas, then, love of God means love of neighbor, and our love should especially extend to (1) those closest to us and (2) those in need.22Now one man’s connection with another may be measured in reference to the various matters in which men are engaged together; (thus the intercourse of kinsmen is in natural matters, that of fellow-citizens is in civic matters, that of the faithful is in spiritual matters, and so forth): and various benefits should be conferred in various ways according to these various connections, because we ought in preference to bestow on each one such benefits as pertain to the matter in which, speaking simply, he is most closely connected with us. And yet this may vary according to the various requirements of time, place, or matter in hand: because in certain cases one ought, for instance, to succor a stranger, in extreme necessity, rather than one’s own father, if he is not in such urgent need.(ST II-II. q31. a3)
9. How the Church Can Help the Hurting
10. Conclusions
Funding
Institutional Review Board Statement
Informed Consent Statement
Data Availability Statement
Conflicts of Interest
1 | I am indebted to two groups for this article. First, I am indebted to my Cultural Perspectives course (Spring 2023) at Hope College for prompting my interest in this question. Our discussions and work in that class on Dante’s Circle of the Suicides in The Inferno were helpful in shaping the structure, content, and trajectory of this paper. I am also indebted to Eleonore Stump and her lectures on Dante for inspiring this paper. Her way of questioning the symbolism of Dante’s Divine Comedy (Alighieri 2003) was also helpful in raising the questions that are discussed here. I am indebted to three anonymous reviewers for their helpful insights in revising this paper. |
2 | I am also indebted to Eleonore Stump and Carlo Leget for shaping how I crafted this paper. David Novak and Carl Leget were significant in shaping my discussion of justice throughout the paper, especially when it comes to understanding the notion of the common good. The styles of both Stump and Leget in handling the issues of both justice and suicide were helpful for thinking about how to narrow the scope of my own project at certain points. |
3 | Although outside the scope of this paper, Leget raises the objection of why we should think Aquinas is an authority on the wrongness of suicide. He points to the objections of both John Donne and David Hume to raise challenges to Aquinas’s argument against suicide. As Leget reads Donne, Donne argues that one cannot know whether suicide is wrong unless one looks at the intention of the action, and he appeals specifically to martyrdom to make his case. As Leget reads Hume, Hume raises an objection to each of Aquinas’s arguments. To the first, Hume objects that suicide does not bring harm to the person in every instance. To the second argument, Hume objects that the obligations between members of society only hold if both sides “have profit of each other” (Leget 2002, p. 283). And to the third argument, Hume objects that because of God’s total providence over the world, one’s taking their own life could never be outside of that providence. These objections came from the new worldviews that each represents—the Renaissance and the Enlightenment. Leget was helpful in pointing out the need to take into account an author’s context when analyzing an argument. While helpful, the constraints of space in this paper prevent me from examining these arguments in detail; (see Leget 2002, pp. 279–84; Donne 1983; Hume 1992). |
4 | In his broader discussion of charity, Aquinas describes it as a form that makes human beings fit for union with God. This form is not also necessary for human beings to be able to see God, but once we are made fit for union with God, we are then able to enjoy him in this life and the next. Novak (1975) picks up on this notion of charity and how it relates to the wrongness of suicide in relationship to oneself and with God. Because of the focus in this paper on the relationship between the church community and individuals struggling with suicidal ideation, I have chosen to omit this discussion, but it is an important aspect of Aquinas’s thought on charity; see Aquinas, Summa Contra Gentiles, III.52 and 53; IV. 21 and 22. ST II-II 23.1, Aquinas, Commentary on the Sentences I. 17 (Lectura Romana) q1. a1 and a2; (see also Novak 1975, pp. 53–54; Stump 2018, chap. 7). |
5 | I am also indebted to correspondence with Eleonore Stump for this way of reading what mortal sin means. |
6 | Novak contains a wonderful discussion of how one’s love of self is connected to love of God and the virtue of charity. He sees natural inclination as connected to charity, as charity perfects human nature (including inclination, especially when it comes to the love of God) (Novak 1975, pp. 53–54); see also ST II-II. q23 a1. and ST II-II. q26. a4. |
7 | I am indebted to Aristotle’s discussion of the political community as understood in the Nicomachean Ethics for my own use of it here, (see also Stump 2003; Novak 1975). Later in the paper, I modify the notion of community from political to religious communities, but I think much of what is true of political community can translate to religious community, with some modification. |
8 | I am indebted to (Leget 2002, pp. 289–93) for putting Aquinas’s discussion of suicide in terms of relationships. |
9 | I am grateful to an anonymous reviewer’s comments for the shape of these sections on justice. |
10 | I am indebted to (Stump 2003) for many of the citations of Aquinas. I am also indebted to her chapter on Justice in that text for the structure and examples found in this section. My examples were inspired by hers (Stump 2003, p. 317). |
11 | This way of understanding the wrongness of suicide might come off as offensive to the modern reader. While not pertinent to my discussion at this point in the text, Leget offers a helpful explanation for this initial reactions by pointing to a difference in worldviews, (see Leget 2002, pp. 279–85, 292–93). |
12 | Clark (2011) and Pope (1991) argue that almsgiving is an expression of charity for Aquinas. One way we might also understand such avoidance of sin is as an expression of spiritual almsgiving, which can involve the correction of a sinner, see ST II-II. q32. q2. I am also indebted to correspondence with Eleonore Stump for my understanding of almsgiving on this point. |
13 | See Tynes et al. for similar findings among Black young people who struggled with suicidal ideation post discrimination on online platforms. |
14 | For more on Van Orden’s study of the Interpersonal Theory of Suicide, (see Van Orden et al. 2008, 2012). |
15 | I should note that my discussion of charity will not include its relation to the gifts of the Holy Spirit or to the infused virtues. For more on this, see ST I-II. q68.a1-a2 and ST I-II. q62.a1. (See also Stump 2010, 2011, 2016, 2018) for more on the gifts and infused virtues. It should also be noted that the form of charity is received freely. This coming to will what God wills is not forced on the human person, but one that they themselves desire. See Stump 2010, 2018 for more on this point about justification, or coming to will what God wills. |
16 | There is some ambiguity among the commentators about whether, for Aquinas, charity is infused at baptism or in connection to the presence of faith. Eleonore Stump (2003, chap. 12; 2011, 2016, 2018, chap. 7), for example, argues that Aquinas thinks that the virtues are infused at the moment of justification, when one comes to faith in Christ. Brian Davies (1992, chaps. 16 and 17) emphasizes that, on Aquinas’s view it is Christ’s work on the cross that effects salvation, and we are united to that work via faith. Davies cites ST III. Q62. a5 to this effect (see also ST III. Q61, a1, reply to objection 3). The sacraments remain important as physical signs of the experience of salvation (Davies 1992, chap. 17), but there is some debate on what their importance for salvation is. Aquinas deals with baptism in the ST III. Q60-69 (see also Davies 1992, chap. 17). For more on this debate over what baptism accomplishes, (see Weed 2014, 2019; Kaczor and Sherman 2020; Kaczor 2020; Bauerschmidt 2013). I am indebted to an anonymous reviewer for pointing out the need to address this point about baptism. |
17 | All references to the Summa Contra Gentiles are from the following version: (Aquinas 1955–1957). |
18 | For a more technical explanation of how the form comes to be in the believer, (see Sherwin 2005, chap. 3). |
19 | I use selections from the Paris and Lectura Romana versions with equal authority. As I understand the two texts, both contain the same ideas, but in more direct expression in the Lectura Romana. Thus, I hold both versions to be equally representative of Aquinas’s views, see (Doyle 2016). All references to Aquinas’s Commentary on the Sentences are from the following edition: (Aquinas 2008). |
20 | For more on how God is goodness itself, and God’s relationship to that goodness and to himself, (see Stump 2010), “Theodicy in Another World” and “What We Care About: The Desires of the Heart”; as well as (Stump 2003), “Goodness”. For more on the claim that sanctification involves growth in goodness, becoming more like God, (see Stump 2018, pp. 204–9, 290–99). Aquinas claims in the ST II-II. Q23 that part of charity or a person’s friendship with God involves loving what that other person loves as well. If God is goodness, and what it means to love God is to love goodness, then sanctification means that we grow in love of goodness itself. All references to the Summa Theologica are from the following version: (Aquinas 1947). |
21 | My understanding of Aquinas on love in this section and what follows is heavily shaped by Stump (2006; 2010, chaps. 5 and 6). |
22 | |
23 | In what follows I discuss flourishing. I am grateful for the correspondence with Dan Haybron for my use of flourishing in this paper. |
References
- Ahmadboukani, Soliman, Hosein Ghamari Kivi, Ahmedreza Kiani, and Ali Rezaeisharif. 2023. A structural test of the three-step theory (3ST) of suicide in the Iranian population: From ideation to action. Health Science Reports 6: e1697. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed]
- Alighieri, Dante. 2003. The Divine Comedy. Translated by John Ciardi. New York: Penguin. [Google Scholar]
- Aquinas, Thomas. 1947. Summa Theologiae. Translated by the Fathers of the Dominican Province. Available online: https://www.ccel.org/a/aquinas/summa/home.html (accessed on 1 September 2024).
- Aquinas, Thomas. 1955–1957. Summa Contra Gentiles. Edited by Joseph Kenny, O.P. New York: Hanover House. Available online: https://isidore.co/aquinas/english/ContraGentiles.htm (accessed on 1 October 2024).
- Aquinas, Thomas. 1964. Commentary on the Nicomachean Ethics. Translated by C. I. Litzinger, O.P. Chicago: Henry Regnery Company. Available online: https://isidore.co/aquinas/english/Ethics.htm (accessed on 1 October 2024).
- Aquinas, Thomas. 2008. On Love and Charity: Readings from the Commentary on the Sentences of Peter Lombard. Translated by Peter A. Kwasniewski, Thomas Bolin, and Joseph Bolin. Washington, DC: Catholic University Press of America. [Google Scholar]
- Aristotle. 1999. Nicomachean Ethics. Translated by Terence Irwin. Indianapolis: Hackett. [Google Scholar]
- Az, Adem, Cigdem Orhan, and Ozgur Sogut. 2023. Suicide attempts and the factors that lead to suicidal ideation: A 3-year analysis. Northern Clinics of Istanbul 10: 745–53. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed]
- Bauerschmidt, Frederick Christian. 2013. Thomas Aquinas: Faith, Reason, and Following Christ. Oxford: Oxford University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Bernstein, Jeffrey A. 2016. Righteousness and Divine Love: Maimonides and Thomas on Charity. In Aquinas: Questions on Love and Charity: Summa Theologiae, Secunda Secundae, Questions 23–46. Translated by Robert Miner. New Haven: Yale University Press, pp. 336–54. [Google Scholar]
- Center for Disease Control and Prevention (CDC). 2024. Suicide Prevention: Facts About Suicide. Available online: https://www.cdc.gov/suicide/facts/index.html (accessed on 1 October 2024).
- Cerel, Julie, Margaret M. Brown, Myfanwy Maple, Michael Singleton, Judy van de Venne, Melinda Moore, and Chris Flaherty. 2018. How Many People Are Exposed to Suicide? Not Six. Suicide and Life-Threatening Behavior 49: 529–34. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed]
- Clark, Meghan J. 2011. Love of God and Neighbor: Living Charity in Aquinas’ Ethics. New Blackfriars 92: 415–30. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Davies, Brian. 1992. The Thought of Thomas Aquinas. New York: Oxford. [Google Scholar]
- Donne, John. 1983. Suicide. Chico: Scholars Press. [Google Scholar]
- Doyle, Dominic. 2016. Is Charity the Holy Spirit? The Development of Aquinas’s Disagreement with Peter Lombard. In Aquinas: Questions on Love and Charity: Summa Theologiae, Secunda Secundae, Questions 23–46. Translated by Robert Miner. New Haven: Yale, pp. 311–35. [Google Scholar]
- Drum, David J., Chris Brownson, Adryon Burton Denmark, and Shanna E. Smith. 2009. New data on the nature of suicidal crises in college students: Shifting the paradigm. Professional Psychology: Research and Practice 40: 213. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Farrell, Dominic. 2018. Wanting the Common Good: Aquinas on General Justice. Review of Metaphysics 71: 517–49. [Google Scholar]
- Fiala, Andrew. 2023. Pacifism. In The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Edited by Edward N. Zalta and Uri Nodelman. Fall 2023 Edition. Available online: https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2023/entries/pacifism/ (accessed on 1 September 2024).
- Finley, Kate. 2023a. Mental Disorder, Meaning Making, and Religious Engagement. TheoLogica: An International Journal for Philosophy of Religion and Philosophical Theology 7: 56–101. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Finley, Kate. 2023b. Narrative & Spiritual Meaning Making in Mental Disorder. International Journal for Philosophy of Religion 94: 233–56. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Heseltine-Carp, William, and Mathew Hoskins. 2020. Clergy as a frontline mental health service: A UK survey of medical practitioners and clergy. General Psychiatry 33: e100229. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Hume, David. 1992. Essays on Suicide and the Immortality of the Soul. Bristol: Thoemmes Press. [Google Scholar]
- Kaczor, Christopher. 2020. Thomas Aquinas on Faith, Hope, and Love: A Summa of the Summa on the Theological Virtues. Washington, DC: Catholic University of America Press. [Google Scholar]
- Kaczor, Christopher, and Thomas Sherman, S.J. 2020. Thomas Aquinas on the Cardinal Virtues: A Summa of the Summa on Prudence, Justice, Temperance, and Courage. Washington, DC: Catholic University of America Press. [Google Scholar]
- Kim, Soo Hyun, Han Joon Kim, Sang Hoon Oh, and Kyungman Cha. 2020. Analysis of attempted suicide episodes presenting to the emergency department: Comparison of young, middle aged and older people. International Journal of Metal Health Systems 14: 1–8. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Lee, Hyunju Lee, C. Hyung Keun Park, Sang Jin Rhee, Jayoun Kim, Bora Kim, Sang Sin Lee, Kyooseob Ha, Chang Jae Baik, and Yong Min Ahn. 2021. An integrated model for the relationship between socio-cultural factors, Attitudes Toward Suicide, and intensity of suicidal ideation in Korean, Japanese, and American populations. Journal of Affective Disorders 280: 203–10. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed]
- Leget, Carlo. 2002. Authority and Plausibility: Aquinas on Suicide. In Aquinas on Authority. Edited by Paul van Geest, Harm Goris and Carlo Leget. Leuven: Peeters, pp. 277–93. [Google Scholar]
- Mitchell, Ann M., Teresa J. Sakraida, Yookyung Kim, Leann Bullian, and Laurel Chiapetta. 2009. Depression, Anxiety and Quality of Life in Suicide Survivors: A Comparison of Close and Distant Relationships. Archives of Psychiatric Nursing 23: 2–10. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed]
- Novak, David. 1975. Suicide and Morality: The Theories of Plato, Aquinas, and Kant and Their Relevance for Suicidology. New York: Scholars Studies Press. [Google Scholar]
- Oppenheimer, Julia E., Kevin J. Flannelly, and Andrew J. Weaver. 2004. A comparative analysis of the psychological literature on collaboration between clergy and mental-health professionals—Perspectives from secular and religious journals: 1970–1999. Pastoral Psychology 53: 153–62. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Pope, Stephen J. 1991. Aquinas on Almsgiving, Justice and Charity: An Interpretation and Reassessment. Heythrop Journal 32: 167–91. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Sherwin, Michael S., O.P. 2005. By Knowledge & By Love. Washington, DC: The Catholic University of America Press. [Google Scholar]
- Stump, Eleonore. 2003. Aquinas. New York: Routledge. [Google Scholar]
- Stump, Eleonore. 2006. Love, by All Accounts. Proceedings and Addresses of the American Philosophical Association 80: 25–43. [Google Scholar]
- Stump, Eleonore. 2010. Wandering in Darkness: Narrative and the Problem of Suffering. New York: Oxford. [Google Scholar]
- Stump, Eleonore. 2011. The Non-Aristotelian Character of Aquinas’s Ethics: Aquinas on the Passions. Faith and Philosophy: Journal of the Society of Christian Philosophers 28: 29–43. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Stump, Eleonore. 2016. The God of the Bible and the God of the Philosophers. Milwaukee: Marquette University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Stump, Eleonore. 2018. Atonement. New York: Oxford. [Google Scholar]
- Tynes, Brendesha M., Ashley Maxie-Moreman, Tuyet-Mai Ha Hoang, Henry A. Willis, and Devin English. 2024. Online Racial Discrimination, Suicidal Ideation, and Traumatic Stress in a National Sample of Black Adolescents. JAMA Psychiatry 81: 312–16. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Van Orden, Kimberly A., Kelly C. Cukrowicz, Tracy K. Witte, and Thomas E. Joiner, Jr. 2012. Thwarted belongingness and perceived burdensomeness: Construct validity and psychometric properties of the Interpersonal Needs Questionnaire. Psychological Assessment 24: 197–215. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Van Orden, Kimberly A., Tracy K. Witte, Kathryn H. Gordon, Theodore W. Bender, and Thomas E. Joiner, Jr. 2008. Suicidal desire and the capability for suicide: Tests of the interpersonal-psychological theory of suicidal behavior among adults. Journal of Consulting and Clinical Psychology 76: 72–83. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Van Orden, Kimberly A., Tracy K. Witte, Kelly C. Cukrowicz, Scott Braithwaite, Edward A. Selby, and Thomas E. Joiner, Jr. 2010. The Interpersonal Theory of Suicide. Psychological Review 117: 575–600. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Wagner, Birgit, Laura Hofmann, and Raphaela Grafiadeli. 2021. The Relationship Between Guilt, Depression, Prolonged Grief and Posttraumatic Stress Symptoms after Suicide Bereavement. Journal of Clinical Psychology 77: 2545–58. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed]
- Weed, Jennifer Hart. 2014. Faith, Salvation, and the Sacraments in Aquinas: A Puzzle Concerning Forced Baptisms. Philosophy, Culture, and Traditions 10: 95–109. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Weed, Jennifer Hart. 2019. Thomas Aquinas and the Baptism of Desire. Res Philosophica 96: 77–89. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Wolford-Clevenger, Caitlin, Gregory L. Stuart, Lawrence Christian Elledge, James K. McNulty, and Anthony Spirito. 2020. Proximal Correlates of Suicidal Ideation and Behaviors: A Test of the Interpersonal-Psychological Theory of Suicide. Suicide and Life-Threatening Behaviors 50: 249–62. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Zhang, Jie, Yuxin Liu, Jianwei Zhang, and Chen Chen. 2018. Linking Psychological Strain and Suicide Ideation: A Test of the Mediating Effect of Self-Determination Among Chinese Workers. The Journal of Nervous and Mental Disease 206: 362–69. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
Disclaimer/Publisher’s Note: The statements, opinions and data contained in all publications are solely those of the individual author(s) and contributor(s) and not of MDPI and/or the editor(s). MDPI and/or the editor(s) disclaim responsibility for any injury to people or property resulting from any ideas, methods, instructions or products referred to in the content. |
© 2024 by the author. Licensee MDPI, Basel, Switzerland. This article is an open access article distributed under the terms and conditions of the Creative Commons Attribution (CC BY) license (https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/).
Share and Cite
McCarty, E. Aquinas, Suicide, and Communities of Faith. Religions 2024, 15, 1395. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel15111395
McCarty E. Aquinas, Suicide, and Communities of Faith. Religions. 2024; 15(11):1395. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel15111395
Chicago/Turabian StyleMcCarty, Emily. 2024. "Aquinas, Suicide, and Communities of Faith" Religions 15, no. 11: 1395. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel15111395
APA StyleMcCarty, E. (2024). Aquinas, Suicide, and Communities of Faith. Religions, 15(11), 1395. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel15111395