Why Can’t Angels See Our Future? Aquinas’s View of the Relation between Continuous and Discrete Time
Abstract
:1. Introduction: Aquinas’s Two Apparently Conflicting Claims about Angelic Time
2. Aquinas’s Claim That Angels Do Not Know Future Contingent Events by Natural Knowledge
3. Aquinas’s Claim That Angels Neither Exist Nor Act in Physical Time
3.1. Aeviternity: The Measure of Angelic Existence
3.2. Discrete Time: The Measure of Angelic Operation
Notably, this claim that angelic time is composed of “discrete” moments, each corresponding to an angelic act, presumes not only that there is no time between angelic acts but also that there is no time within angelic acts (i.e., that the duration of angelic acts is not intrinsically extended into “earlier” and “later” parts). In fact, although Aquinas does not make this claim explicitly in In Sent. I.37.4.3, he does so elsewhere, including in a particularly striking way in Quaestiones disputatae De veritate [De ver.] 8.14 ad 12 in a discussion of angelic cognitive acts:Hence, since the motion of the angel is not continuous, … so too the corresponding time is not continuous but rather is composed of “nows” following each other, taking “time” as the number of the successive operations themselves, in the same way that the succession itself of operations is called “motion.” And however many operations there are out of which the motion with respect to different places is composed, there will be that many “nows” out of which the time is composed.44
Because of their interior immutability, angelic acts are interiorly timeless and, thus, properly measured by a single instant.Those operations which possess their complete species immediately [statim] are not measured by time except per accidens, for example, understanding, sensing, and the like, which is why the Philosopher says in Nic. Eth. X[.5.1174b8] that “taking delight” is not in time. Such operations can be in time per accidens, however, insofar as they are conjoined to motion by existing in a nature subject to time, namely the generable and corruptible corporeal nature which the sense powers use as an organ, and from which our intellect also receives. Hence, it is clear that the understanding [intelligere] itself of the angel does not fall under time either per se or per accidens; wherefore there is no before and after [prius et posterius] in one operation by which he understands one intelligible.45
This is a striking claim: angels, according to Aquinas, can watch changing physical history unfold without any change whatsoever in their own intellects. The central principle undergirding this claim is that a pure intellect’s knowledge of contingent things in their existence and presence requires nothing more than the formal likeness between an activated intelligible species in the knower’s mind and the contingent thing itself. The change by which a contingent object newly begins to be present to such an intellect may thus be entirely on the side of the object.Since knowledge takes place [sit] through the knower’s becoming similar [assimilari] to the known thing, one gains new knowledge of something in the same way that one becomes newly similar to something. This happens in two ways: first, by one’s own movement; second, by something else’s movement toward a form one already possesses. Likewise, someone newly begins to know something in one way by newly receiving the form of the thing known, as happens in us; in another way, by the fact that the known thing newly attains the form that is in the knower. And it is in the latter way that the angels newly know present things that previously had been future. For example, if something was not yet a man, the angelic intellect will not yet have become similar to it by the form of man that the angel possesses; but when it begins to be a man, the angelic intellect begins to be similar to it according to that same form, without any change on its side.46
In other words, Aquinas thinks that the angels have a perfect, luminous understanding of the object’s essence in all of its possible instantiations, and that this perfect understanding gives them an immediate grasp not only of the essence itself but also of everything actually belonging to it. While Aquinas does not defend this crucial move from knowing possibilities to knowing actuality in this article, the underlying principle is presumably the one we saw above in De ver. 8.9 ad 3: that knowledge consists in the knower’s spiritual likeness to the actual object. Since the angel’s rich concreated intelligible species, unlike our impoverished abstraction-based ones, already includes a proper likeness of all the object’s essential possibilities, it will a fortiori include a proper likeness of the essence’s particular actual determinations. Hence, the act of simply apprehending the object’s essence is sufficient for them; they do not need to “flesh it out” by forming a proposition to add further detail to an initial empty abstraction, just as they do not need to “flesh out” their understanding of first principles by inferentially deducing their conclusions (ST I.58.3). (This does not mean that they do not judge; indeed Aquinas attributes judgment to them in the immediately ensuing I.58.5. It simply means that their judgment is a simple rather than a complex act.) Moreover, lest there be any doubt that this claim applies to angelic knowledge not only of essential properties but even of contingent existence, Aquinas explicitly asserts in De malo 16.6 ad s.c. 1 that “the angel knows existence and nonexistence by simple apprehension of the subject, just as we do by composing and dividing.”49If the intellect, in its apprehension of the subject’s quiddity, were immediately aware [haberet notitiam] of everything which can be attributed to or removed from the subject, it would never understand by composing and dividing, but only by understanding the thing’s essence [quod quid est]. Therefore, it is clear that it is for the same reason that our intellect understands by discursive reasoning and by composing and dividing: namely, because it cannot instantly inspect whatever is virtually [virtute] contained in something newly apprehended in its first apprehension thereof. This is due to the weakness of the intellectual light in us, as has been said [I.58.3]. Hence, since there is a perfect intellectual light in the angel … it follows that the angel, just as it does not understand by reasoning [ratiocinando], so neither does it understand by composing or dividing. Nonetheless, the angel understands the composition and division of propositions [enuntiationum], just as it understands the reasoning of syllogisms: for it understands composite things simply, and changeable things changelessly [mobilia immobiliter], and material things immaterially.48
In other words, there is no intrinsic connection between angelic time and our physical time. Angelic instants cannot correspond one-to-one to physical instants, since physical instants are potentially infinite, but angelic instants are only finite. Nor can they correspond one-to-one to any particular length of physical time, since there is no proportion between the finite and the infinite.There can be no proportion between the time in which a body is in motion and the time in which an angel is in motion. For the time in which the angel is in motion is not divisible by a continuous division but rather by a discrete division into a finite number of instants; whereas in the time in which the body is in motion, there are potentially infinite instants; and so there is no proportion, just as there is no proportion between the infinite and the finite.51
Correspondingly, in the reply to the first objection, Aquinas no longer denies unqualifiedly that angelic time has any proportion to our physical time (as he had at In Sent. I.37.4.3 ad 3); rather, he only says that the non-continuous time corresponding to the angel’s non-continuous motion lacks such proportion, while the angel’s continuous time is commensurable to our time.61It follows that the motion of the angel is in time. In continuous time, if his motion is continuous; but in non-continuous time, if his motion is non-continuous (for the motion of the angel can exist in either way, as was said above [ST I.53.1–2]), since the continuity of time is derived from the continuity of motion, as is said in Phys. IV.60
In other words, precisely because angelic time is not continuous, there need be no intervening time between one instant and another; so Aquinas can conclude that the devil sinned immediately in his second instant rather than after some interval (mora), as would have necessarily been the case in continuous time. Or, as Aquinas states even more explicitly in ST I-II.113.7 ad 5:The statement that between any two instants there is an intermediate time is true insofar as time is continuous, as is proven in Physics VI.[1.231b9]. However, in the angels, who are not subject to the heavenly motion, which is what is primarily measured by continuous time, time is taken to refer to the succession itself of operations of understanding or of loving [affectus].63
Aquinas also affirms the discreteness of the succession of angelic operations and the time measuring that succession at Quodl. II.3, which is generally dated to 1269 or 1270 (after the Prima Pars, which was completed no later than 1268).65 So, even in his mature works, Aquinas still insists that the time measuring the angel’s intrinsic operations is always discrete, without exception.But it is otherwise in things which are above time. If there is some succession there of affections or of intellectual conceptions, for example in the angels, such succession is not measured by continuous time but rather by discrete time, just as the things themselves which are measured are non-continuous. Hence, with such things, one must assign a last instant at which the first thing existed and a first instant at which the following thing exists; nor does there need to be an intermediate time, for the continuity of time that requires this does not obtain there.64
In other words, in this later work, Aquinas simply equates traversing a whole continuum (of which he had always claimed angels were capable) with continuous motion (of which he had originally said that angels were not capable). This is precisely what he is doing in ST I.53.1 when he attributes continuous motion to the angels: his whole reason for doing so is simply that angels can apply their power to a divisible, continuous place and, therefore, can shift that application in the continuous way proper to divisible things69—that is, through the intermediate places, which as he states in the ensuing I.53.2 (another parallel to In Sent. I.37.4.2 and Quodl. I.3.2 on traversing intermediate places) is simply a corollary of continuous motion.The angel is not in a place as commensurate with it [per commensurationem], but by the application of his power to the place, which may equally be to a divisible or an indivisible place. Hence, it can move continuously, as something occupying a divisible place, continuously intercepting space; however, insofar as it is in an indivisible place, its motion cannot be continuous, nor can it travel through all the intermediate places.68
4. Can the Tension Be Resolved?
4.1. What Aquinas Does Say
His response to this objection is not very helpful for our purposes, however: he simply says that the demons, even though they are not in our continuous time, are still in a kind of time inasmuch as they do not know all things at once and, hence, must have a succession (vicissitudo) of operations of knowing and willing, which Aquinas identifies with their time.76 No explanation is given, however, of how the “nows” of such different times could be synchronized.If the demons are incorporeal substances, it is necessary that they be above time with respect to their substance and operation, according to what is said in the Liber de causis that the substance and operation of an intelligence is above time [supra tempus]. Now, present, past, and future are differences of time. Therefore, with respect to the knowledge of the demons, it makes no difference whether something is present, past, or future. However, the demons can know present and past things. Therefore, they can also know future things.75
In this scenario, the angel’s two-instant locomotion is still, in Aquinas’s view, simultaneous with the whole physical motion—but only in the sense that the angel’s two instants surround that physical motion.87 In “between” those two angelic instants, while the physical body’s motion is underway at pt1.5, there just is no corresponding angelic instant at1.5; the only angelic duration-measure that is simultaneous with any of the physical body’s intermediate instants like pt1.5 is the aeviternity of the angel’s being. In other words, as far as the angel’s conscious life goes, he can simply “skip” whole stretches of physical time88—a possibility that Pecham and his supporters do not allow for.89 This “gappy” account goes at least some way toward lining up the incommensurable instants of angelic and physical time, since, by removing the requirement for every angelic instant to correspond to a physical one, it makes it possible for a finite number of angelic instants to correspond to our infinitely divisible physical time despite the lack of “proportion” between them.If we posit that the movements of the angel and the physical body begin simultaneously, when the angel is at the other endpoint at a different instant of his time, the physical body will also be at the other endpoint at a different instant of its own time. Now, there is an intermediate time between the two instants of this physical body’s time, inasmuch as its motion is continuous; and so we can designate an intermediate instant in that intermediate time. However, between the two instants of the angel there is no intermediate time. Hence, neither can we designate an intermediate instant there (though we could designate an intermediate instant if the angel were in three places successively, for in that case the angel’s time would be composed of three “nows,” of which one would be intermediate); and those two instants can include all the instants of the [physical] time, just as the single stationary “now” of aeviternity85 includes every time. So, there is no difficulty with the angel’s motion occupying only two instants while the physical body’s motion occupies infinite instants—even though the motion of the angel lasts just as long as that of the physical body, and even though neither motion is indivisible. Furthermore, when this physical body is at an intermediate instant, the angel will be in no place, since it is not necessary for him always to be in a place, as was said above (I.37.3.1); and so no “now” corresponding to that time [secundum coordinationem illius temporis] will pertain [respondeat] to the angel, but only aeviternity.86
4.2. What Aquinas Could Say
4.2.1. Angelic Instants Are “Exceeding Measures” of Physical Times
4.2.2. Angels Cannot “Skip” Physical Time
4.2.3. An Exotic Solution to the Foreknowledge Problem: Angelic Instants Are Entirely Extensionless, and, Therefore, Are Simultaneous with a Predetermined Duration of Physical Time as a Whole
- (1)
- At a given angelic instant at1, the angel can have no natural knowledge of what he will see in a subsequent at2.
- (2)
- Angelic instants are divided from each other by successive acts of either intellect or will.
- (3)
- Any angelic act of choice in at1 to intervene in the physical world would have to be directed at a later physical time corresponding to a subsequent intellectual act in at2 (on pain of violating the necessity of the physical past and of the angelic present).
- (4)
- Hence (by 2), all physical time after any angelic intervention would still be future to the angel at the angelic instant when he chooses to intervene.
- (5)
- Therefore (by 1), such physical time would be hidden from the angel’s natural knowledge.
4.2.4. A Modest Solution to the Foreknowledge Problem: Angelic Instants Are Relationally Extended and, Therefore, Sequentially Simultaneous with an Improvised Duration of Physical Time
5. Conclusions
Funding
Institutional Review Board Statement
Informed Consent Statement
Data Availability Statement
Acknowledgments
Conflicts of Interest
1 | For discussion of Aquinas’s view of the angels’ natural knowledge of future contingents, see esp. John of St. Thomas, Cursus theologicus 42.2 (John of St. Thomas 1931–1953, vol. 4, pp. 636–55). See also Goris (2012, pp. 178–82); Suarez-Nani (2002, pp. 54–58); Bonino (2016, pp. 145–46); and Collins (1947, pp. 228–32). |
2 | Cf. Aquinas, Quaestiones disputatae De veritate [De ver.] 8.12 (Aquinas 1882ff, vol. 22/2), where Aquinas adds that angels can naturally know not only (a) things which follow necessarily from a single cause but also (b) things which, though they only follow contingently from their cause taken singillatim, follow necessarily given the concurrence of that cause with other causes. Thus, what seem like chance events to our limited knowledge will be known as necessary by the angels. |
3 | Aquinas, Summa theologiae [ST] I.57.3 (Aquinas 1882ff, vol. 5, p. 75a): “Alio modo cognoscuntur futura in seipsis. Et sic solius Dei est futura cognoscere, non solum quae ex necessitate proveniunt, vel ut in pluribus, sed etiam casualia et fortuita: quia Deus videt omnia in sua aeternitate, quae, cum sit simplex, toti tempori adest, et ipsum concludit. Et ideo unus Dei intuitus fertur in omnia quae aguntur per totum tempus sicut in praesentia, et videt omnia ut in seipsis sunt; sicut supra dictum est cum de Dei scientia ageretur [ST I.14.13]. Angelicus autem intellectus, et quilibet intellectus creatus, deficit ab aeternitate divina. Unde non potest ab aliquo intellectu creato cognosci futurum, ut est in suo esse” (emphasis added). Aquinas, Quaestiones disputatae De malo [De malo] 16.7 (Aquinas 1882ff, vol. 23, p. 315a–b, lines 184–206): “[F]utura prout futura sunt nondum habent esse in se ipsis; esse autem et uerum conuertuntur; unde cum omnis cognitio sit alicuius ueri, impossibile est quod aliqua cognitio respiciens futura in ratione futuri cognoscat ea in se ipsis. Cum autem presens, preteritum et futurum sint differentie temporis temporalem ordinem designantes, omne quod qualitercumque est in tempore comparatur ad futura sub ratione futuri; et ideo impossibile est quod aliqua cognitio subiacens ordini temporis cognoscat futura in seipsis. Talis autem est omnis cognitio creature, ut post dicetur. Vnde impossibile est quod aliqua creatura cognoscat futura in se ipsis; set hoc est proprium solius Dei, cuius cognitio est omnino eleuata supra totum ordinem temporis, ita quod nulla pars temporis comparatur ad cognitionem diuinam sub ratione preteriti vel futuri, set totus decursus temporis et ea que per totum tempus aguntur presentialiter et conformiter eius aspectui subduntur, et eius simplex intuitus super omnia simul fertur prout unumquodque est in suo tempore” (emphasis added). |
4 | For Aquinas’s thematic discussions of God’s eternity-based knowledge of our future, see esp. ST I.14.13; Summa contra gentiles [SCG] I.66–67, nn. 547–51, 556–58, and 564 (Aquinas 1961); Scriptum super libros Sententiarum [In Sent.] I.38.1.5 (Aquinas 1929–1947); Quodlibet [Quodl.] XI.3 (Aquinas 1882ff, vol. 25/1); and Compendium theologiae [Comp. theol.] I.133 (Aquinas 1882ff, vol. 42). |
5 | This is, of course, Aristotle’s famous claim about the future sea battle at De interpretatione 9.18b25–19b4 (Aristotle 1984), which Aquinas cites at De malo 16.7 s.c. 3. |
6 | This is the RSV-CE translation. The Vulgate rendering of Is 41:23 quoted by Aquinas is as follows: “Annuntiate quae ventura sunt in futurum, et sciemus quia [Aquinas: quod] dii estis vos.” |
7 | See ST I.57.5 and II-II.172.2 and SCG III.80 and III.154 nn. 3256–57. For discussion, see, for example, Oliva (2022, p. 10). |
8 | See esp. Aquinas, SCG I.6 & III.154 nn. 3263–67 & 3272. |
9 | For the demons’ ability to simulate knowing the future, see Aquinas’s texts on divination, notably ST II-II.95.2–3; cf. In Sent. II.7.2.2, SCG III.154 nn. 3268–71, De sortibus 4 n. 665 (Aquinas 1882ff, vol. 43), and De malo 16.7 ad 2. |
10 | ST II-II.95.1 (Aquinas 1882ff, vol. 9, pp. 311b–12a) : “Quaedam vero causae sunt quae, si secundum se considerentur, se habent ad utrumlibet: quod praecipue videtur de potentiis rationalibus, quae se habent ad opposita, secundum Philosophum... [E]ffectus huiusmodi praenosci non possunt nisi in seipsis considerentur... Sed considerare huiusmodi in seipsis antequam fiant, est Dei proprium, qui solus in sua aeternitate videt ea quae futura sunt quasi praesentia, ut in Primo habitum est [I.14.13, I.57.3, & I.86.4]: unde dicitur Isaiae XLI [41:23]: Annuntiate quae futura sunt in futurum, et sciemus quoniam dii estis vos. Si quis ergo huiusmodi futura praenoscere aut praenuntiare quocumque modo praesumpserit, nisi Deo revelante, manifeste usurpat sibi quod Dei est. Et ex hoc aliqui divini dicuntur: unde dicit Isidorus, in libro Etymol. [VIII.9]: Divini dicti quasi Deo pleni: divinitate enim se plenos simulant, et astutia quadam fraudulentiae hominibus futura coniectant... Tunc autem solum dicitur divinare quando sibi indebito modo usurpat praenuntiationem futurorum eventuum. Hoc autem constat esse peccatum.” |
11 | For texts that contain both kinds of arguments, besides ST I.57.3 and II-II.95.1 and De malo 16.7, see also De ver. 8.12 c. & s.c. 1, on angelic foreknowledge; In Sent. II.7.2.2 c., arg. 1, & ad 1, containing Aquinas’s early treatment of divination, and IV.50.1.4 ad 4 (Aquinas 1856–1858, vol. 7); Super Isaiam 3.3 (Aquinas 1882ff, vol. 28), which is also against divination—though curiously Aquinas does not mention Is 41:23 explicitly here, and does so only very briefly in his commentary on ch. 41 itself; Quodl. VII.1.3 arg. 1 & ad 1 and Quaestiones disputatae De anima [QD de an.] 20 arg. 4 & ad 4 (Aquinas 1882ff, vol. 24/2), which are both on how an unchanging angelic intelligible species can allow the angel to know changing singulars; and Comp. theol. I.133–34, on the exclusivity of God’s foreknowledge. The following texts contain only the philosophical argument. In ST I.14.13 and In Sent. I.38.1.5 Aquinas only discusses divine foreknowledge and does not even mention angels, but he still argues that foreknowledge is only possible for God’s eternity. In Sent. II.3.3.3 ad 4 and Quaestiones disputatae De spiritualibus creaturis [QD de spir. Creat.] 5 arg. 7 & ad 7 (Aquinas 1882ff, vol. 24/2) both concern angelic knowledge of singulars, like Quodl. VII.1.3 and QD de an. 20. SCG III.154 nn. 3264–65 concerns prophecy and divination, relying in turn on SCG I.66 nn. 547–51 & I.67 nn. 557–58 on God’s foreknowledge; and ST I.86.4 concerns the possibility of human foreknowledge. For texts that give only a theological argument based in Is 41:23, without the philosophical argument, see also De ver. 12.6 arg. 5 & ad 5, De sortibus 2 n. 644, Super Evangelium S. Ioannis lectura [Super Io.] 16.3 n. 2104 (Aquinas 1972), Super I Cor. 12.2 n. 728 (Aquinas 1953, vol. 2), Super Epistolam ad Romanos lectura 2.1 n. 175 (Aquinas 1953, vol. 1), and De decem praeceptis 3. |
12 | Aquinas does not raise this argument in his thematic discussions of angelic knowledge, but in his commentaries on these Scriptural passages, he does link them to the uniqueness of God’s presence to all times. See, for example, Super Evangelium S. Matthei lectura [Super Matt.] 24.3 (Aquinas 1951), commenting on Mt 24:36, and also referencing Mal 3:2 and 1 Thess 5:2; see also Super I Thess. 5.1 (Aquinas 1953, vol. 2), where, in addition to commenting on 1 Thess 5:2, Aquinas also references 2 Pet 3:10 and Rev 3:3, both on Christ’s claim that he will come “like a thief in the night.” |
13 | For Aquinas’s use of the term duratio to signify the existence that is analogously measured by eternity, aeviternity, and time (rather than the measures themselves), see esp. In Sent. II.2.1.pr.–1, ST I.10.4 (c. & arg. 1); Commentaria in octo libros Physicorum Aristotelis [In Phys.] IV.20 nn. 2, 6, and 12 (Aquinas 1882ff, vol. 2); De substantiis separatis 9 (Aquinas 1882ff, vol. 40/D); In De divinis nominibus [In De div. nom.] 2.5 n. 203, 4.3 n. 310, and 5.1 n. 627 (Aquinas 1950); and Quodl. X.2 (though this last text seems to imply that, though duratio is measured by time, aeviternity, or eternity, duratio itself measures existence [esse]—perhaps because “duration” is being taken as a kind of quantity, which is an intrinsic measure, while “time” and “aeviternity” are being taken as extrinsic measures of everything except the primum mobile and the highest angel, respectively). Cf. In Sent. IV.43.1.3.2 ad 1, SCG IV.82 n. 4169, De malo 5.5 ad 6, Quodl. VII.4.2 ad 2, Responsio de 30 articulis ad 27, and Responsio de 36 articulis 7 (Aquinas 1882ff, vol. 42), as well as De ver. 23.2 arg. 8 and Quaestiones disputatae De potentia [De pot.] 3.10 arg. 8 and 3.14 arg. 2 (Aquinas 1965; left undisputed in the replies). For discussion of this distinction between duration and its measures, see, for example, Porro (2008, p. 77). Often, however, Aquinas seems to use duratio to signify the measures themselves (eternity, aeviternity, and time). See, for example, In Sent. I.19.2.1–2, I.31.2.1, and II.1.1.5 (esp. ad s.c. 7 and 9); ST I.10.2 & 5; SCG II.35 n. 1116; In De div. nom. 5.1 n. 631, 10.1 n. 847, and 10.2 n. 860 (the last two being especially clear texts); Super Io. 1.1 n. 37; and De pot. 3.17 ad 20. Cf. ST I.10.1 arg. 2 & 6 and Quodl. X.2 arg. 4 (again left undisputed in the replies). Sometimes, he uses duratio to describe both the measure and the thing measured in the very same passage (ST I.10.6 arg. 3, c., and arg. 4/ad 4, and In De div. nom. 5.1 nn. 627 and 631); and sometimes he will attribute “duration” to both the thing measured and the measure itself (ST I.10.4 c. and arg. 1 and I.10.5 ad 4; De pot. 3.17 c. & arg. 18 and 24). For discussions that assume that Aquinas thinks time, aeviternity, and eternity simply are types of duration, see Fox (2006, pp. 35–39, 262) and Goris (2003, pp. 196–97). |
14 | Aquinas’s chief discussions of angelic aeviternity are to be found at In Sent. I.8.2.2, I.19.2.1–2, and II.2.1.1–2; ST I.10.5–6; and Quodl. V.4 (Aquinas 1882ff, vol. 25/2) and X.2. Other noteworthy discussions are contained in In De div. nom. 4.3, 5.1, 5.3, and esp. 10.2–3; Super librum De Causis expositio [In De causis] 2 (Aquinas 1954); and De pot. 3.14 ad s.c. 9 and 3.17 ad 23.—Surprisingly, however, the term “aevum” shows up only once, and in passing, in Aquinas’s thematic treatment of the angels at ST I.50–64: namely, precisely at ST I.57.3 arg. 2 (on the angels’ knowledge of the future)! The notion of aeviternity (as a measure of substantial duration above time but compatible with a beginning and end) also appears in that treatment at ST I.61.2 ad 2, but is labeled as a special kind of tempus rather than as aevum. For discussion of Aquinas’s theory of angelic aeviternity, see esp. Porro (1996, pp. 105–15, 139–48, 159, 163–64, 199–205, 231–37) and Peter (1964). See also Bonino (2016, p. 129); and cf. Suarez-Nani (1989, pp. 45–77), which, while focused on Nicholas of Strasburg’s theory of angelic aeviternity, presents it as based on Aquinas’s and Albert’s theories (pp. xxi and 149–55). For broader treatments of the general medieval discussion about angelic aeviternity, including but not limited to Aquinas, see Porro (2001, pp. 143–49; 2002, pp. 12–14) and Fox (2006, pp. 244–73). |
15 | For Aquinas’s claim that aeviternity is in a sense totum simul, see esp. In Sent. I.8.2.2. See also In Sent. I.19.2.1 ad 5 (cf. I.19.2.1 c. and the immediately following I.19.2.2, which do not use the term “simul” for aeviternity but do deny succession therein) and II.2.1.1; ST I.10.5 ad 2; and Quodl. X.2. |
16 | See ST I.10.5, In Sent. II.2.1.1, and Quodl. X.2. |
17 | For the aeviternity of human souls, see ST I.10.6 ad 3 and De pot. 3.10 ad 8–9. For the aeviternity of celestial bodies, see ST I.10.5 and I.10.6 ad 2; Quodl. V.4 (c. and ad 1); In Sent. II.2.1.1; and In De div. nom. 8.2 n. 757. Their materiality does not pose an obstacle to their aeviternity, in Aquinas’s view, because their celestial matter is in potency only to local motion, not to substantial change (see ST I.9.2 for a representative text). |
18 | See In Sent. I.37.4.3 ad 7 (an important text to which we will have occasion to return), in the Parma edition (Aquinas 1856–1858, vol. 6, p. 310b), for Aquinas’s use of the Boethian phrase “nunc stans” to describe the “now” of aeviternity: “cum enim unum nunc aevi stans includat omne tempus.” The Mandonnet edition (Aquinas 1929–1947, vol. 1, p. 891) replaces the Parma edition’s phrase “unum nunc aevi stans” with “unum nunc et instans”; but in my view, the Parma edition’s version makes more sense in context, since [a] the “nunc” in question would have to be the nunc aevi rather than the ordinary nunc temporis in order for the sentence to be true, but [b] there is no prior reference to the aevum in the passage, which makes the Mandonnet version quite cryptic. Moreover, the reference to aeviternity at the very end of the response makes considerably less sense if it cannot rely on the prior claim that aeviternity includes all time. See also In Sent. I.19.2.2, where Aquinas contrasts the relationship between our time and its temporal “now” with the relationship between aeviternity and its aeviternal “now.” Time differs from its temporal “now” in that time is successive while its “now” is not: time’s single, unchanging “now” moves through successive parts of time. Aeviternity, however, does not differ from its aeviternal “now” in this respect, since neither one is successive. |
19 | See In Sent. I.19.2.1 and II.2.1.1 ad 5. |
20 | See, for example, Quodl. V.4 and In Sent. I.8.2.2, I.19.2.1 ad 1, and II.2.1.1. However, cf. ST I.10.5 ad 1, Quodl. X.2, and De pot. 4.2 ad 19, where Aquinas contrasts the angels’ natural aeviternity with their supernatural participation in eternity via the beatific vision. Porro notes that Aquinas uses aevum and aeternitas participata synonymously more frequently in his earlier works (Porro 1996, p. 147, fn. 214; Porro 2001, p. 145), though it should be noted that Quodl. V.4, where the terms are used synonymously, is generally regarded as later than Quodl. X.2, where they are distinguished. For the dating of the Quodlibets, see Torrell (2005, pp. 208–11). |
21 | See, for example, ST I.10.5 and In Sent. II.2.1.1 (which uses both the language of “participation” and “intermediate”). |
22 | Indeed, this is the sole significant difference between aeviternity and eternity that Aquinas discusses in In Sent. I.8.2.2 and I.19.2.1 (c. and ad 5), and one of two central differences in In Sent. II.2.1.1 (the other being the closely related point that the divine esse measured by eternity is subsistent, while the angelic esse measured by aeviternity is distinct from the angelic supposit, the quod est). It is, however, notably absent from ST I.10.5, which puts all the emphasis on another difference absent from the Sentences commentary: aeviternity’s “annexation” to time, to be discussed below. (The same is true of De pot. 3.14 ad s.c. 9.) To my knowledge, only Quodl. X.2 ad 4 and De pot. 3.17 ad 23 present both differences (namely, that aeviternity measures a received existence and that it can be annexed to time). |
23 | For this use of the term “duration,” see, for example, In Sent. II.1.1.5 ad s.c. 9 (Aquinas 1929–1947, vol. 2, p. 40): “duratio autem significat quamdam permanentiam.” |
24 | Indeed, Aquinas twice considers the related view that aeviternity is distinguished by actually having a beginning but no end, and rejects it as merely an accidental difference; see In Sent. I.19.2.1 and ST I.10.5. (In Quodl. X.2 ad 4 Aquinas does accept “having a beginning but not an ending” as a characteristic of aeviternity, without adding qualifiers; but it is the last of the characteristics he lists, and he does not address whether it is a necessary or contingent characteristic.) The reason for this rejection is simple enough: Aquinas is committed to the metaphysical possibility of a beginningless created universe (see esp. Aquinas’s De aeternitate mundi; cf. ST I.46.2, In Sent. II.1.1.5, SCG II.38 nn. 1142–50, and De pot. 3.14), as well as of the annihilation of any creature. |
25 | For Aquinas’s claim that angels did not exist from all eternity but rather that their existence has a beginning, see esp. ST I.61.2; cf. his acceptance of the claim that aeviternity does, in fact (though not necessarily), have a beginning in In Sent. I.19.2.1, ST I.10.5, and Quodl. X.2 ad 4. See also In Sent. II.2.1.3, ST I.61.3, and De pot. 3.18 (c. and ad 20), though these texts are primarily focused on whether the angels were created before the physical universe. |
26 | For Aquinas’s claim that God can annihilate existing angels, see In Sent. II.2.1.1 ad 7; ST I.10.5 (c. and ad 3) and I.50.5 ad 3; Quodl. X.2 ad 1; and De pot. 5.3. For God’s power to annihilate creatures in general (both corruptible and incorruptible), see also ST I.9.2 and I.104.3–4; De pot. 5.3; Quodl. IV.3.1; De ver. 5.2 ad 6; and QD de an. 14 ad 19. |
27 | See Aquinas, In Sent. I.19.2.2 ad 1 and II.2.1.1. |
28 | Aquinas, In Sent. I.19.2.2 ad 1 (Aquinas 1929–1947, vol. 1, p. 471): “Non est idem nunc aeternitatis, temporis et aevi; et quando dicitur: Quando est motus, est angelus et Deus, potest significari tripliciter: nunc vel aeternitatis, vel aevi, vel temporis. Si significetur nunc temporis; tunc dicetur motus esse in illo, sicut in propria mensura; angelus autem et Deus, non secundum rationem mensurationis, sed magis secundum concomitantiam quamdam, prout aeternitas et aevum cum tempore simul sunt, nec sibi deficiunt. Si autem significetur nunc aeternitatis, tunc dicitur Deus esse in illo sicut in mensura propria et adaequata; angelus autem et mobile, sicut in mensura excedenti. Si autem significetur nunc aevi, respondebit angelo sicut mensura adaequata, et Deo secundum concomitantiam, et mobili sicut mensura excedens” (emphasis added). For this claim that a higher measure of duration—usually eternity—can be a mensura excedens of lesser durations, see also In Sent. I.19.2.1 ad 2 and I.19.2.2 ad 2 and In De div. nom. 2.5 n. 203. For other passages that claim that eternity can be simultaneous with time due to their being different kinds of measures, but without using the phrase “mensura excedens,” see In Sent. I.40.3.1 ad 5 and ST I.10.4 ad 1. |
29 | Aquinas describes the single “now” of aeviternity as “including” (includat) all time at In Sent. I.37.4.3 ad 7. He applies the same language of “inclusion” to eternity’s “now” at ST I.10.2 ad 4 and I.13.1 ad 3; De ver. 2.12 and 3.3 ad s.c. 1; Super Io. 16.3 n. 2104. Cf. In Sent. I.8.2.3 ad 1. |
30 | For this contrast between possessing duration (in the sense of the subject’s proper actuality) in full vs. in part, analogically applied to both the time-aeviternity contrast and the aeviternity-eternity contrast, see esp. In Sent. I.8.2.2. |
31 | Given Einstein’s relativity theory, it might be impossible to assert that any two separate physical objects share the same “now,” simply speaking, without additionally specifying the frame of reference from which this assertion is made. Even granting this, however, would not affect the broader sense of “simultaneity” that obtains between higher and lower measures of duration (e.g., between physical time and angelic aeviternity or angelic discrete time). Moreover, it is not clear that even Aquinas’s narrow (“proper and adequate measure”) sense of “simultaneity” is necessarily incompatible with the qualification that whether or not two physical objects share a “now” is determined by the frame of reference, especially since arguably even on relativity’s terms there is still an objective ontological basis (the speed of light) for the differences in simultaneity across different frames of reference. For discussion, see Moreno (1981, pp. 62–79). |
32 | See esp. Quodl. X.2 ad 1 (Aquinas 1882ff, vol. 25/1, p. 129b, lines 101–20): “[R]ei eterne uel euiterne aliquid potest attribui dupliciter. Vno modo ratione sui ipsius; et sic non attribuitur ei nec fuisse nec futurum esse, set solum esse, quia in preterito et futuro implicatur prius et posterius, non autem in presenti. Alio modo ratione mensure adiacentis uel subiacentis, id est ratione temporis; et sic attribuitur ei fuisse per concomitanciam ad tempus preteritum, et futurum esse per concomitanciam ad futurum: ipsum enim momentum eternitatis adest toti tempori, unde dicit Augustinus de Deo quod fuit, quia nunquam defuit, erit, quia nunquam deerit. Sic igitur Deus non potest facere angelum non fuisse, quia non potest facere quin tempus preteritum simul cum esse angeli fuerit; potest autem facere angelum non esse, quia potest facere ut esse angeli non sit simul cum tempore quod presens est nunc uel erit in futuro. Et sic ista diuersitas magis pendet ex modo locutionis quam ex natura rei” (emphasis original). Cf. the parallel argument at ST I.10.5 ad 3. However, at In Sent. II.2.1.1 ad 7 [Mandonnet 2:65], Aquinas had earlier answered a similar objection differently, arguing that God can make an angel not be (facere angelum non esse) only in the sense that God might have made the angel not be—not in the sense of making him not be given that he exists (ut simul sit et non sit). For discussion, see Porro (1996, pp. 235–37). |
33 | For Aquinas’s claim that angels were created simultaneously with the physical universe, see In Sent. II.2.1.3, ST I.61.3, and De pot. 3.18–19; for his appeal to physical “imaginary time” to explain the possibility of angels existing “before” the physical universe, see specifically In Sent. II.2.1.3 ad s.c. 2 and De pot. 3.19 ad 5. For his more general appeal to “imaginary time” to explain how God can be said to “preexist” the world and why we can say that he could have made the universe “earlier” than he did, see In Sent. II.1.1.5 ad 7 & ad 13; SCG II.36 n. 1126; ST I.46.1 ad 8; De pot. 3.1 ad 10, 3.2, 3.14 ad 6, and 3.17 ad 20; Comp. theol. I.98; In Phys. VIII.2 n. 20; and In duodecim libros Metaphysicorum Aristotelis expositio [In Met.] XII.5 n. 2498 (Aquinas 1971). |
34 | See Aquinas’s arguments that angels, unlike God, cannot know other things through their own essence but rather require additional intelligible species: ST I.55.1 and I.57.1, In Sent. II.3.3.1, SCG II.98 nn. 1834–36, and De ver. 8.7–8. See also his arguments that lower angels require more intelligible species than higher ones do: ST I.55.3, In Sent. II.3.3.2, SCG II.98 nn. 1836–45, and De ver. 8.10. |
35 | For Aquinas’s claim that angelic natural knowledge cannot happen all at once but rather requires temporal succession, see esp. ST I.58.2, De ver. 8.14, In Sent. II.3.3.4, De malo 16.4, and SCG II.101 nn. 1858–59. See also, for example, In Sent. I.35.1.2 arg. 3 and ad 3, I.37.4.1, and III.14.1.2.4; ST I.12.10 and I.85.4; SCG I.55 nn. 456–57; and Quodl. VII.1.2 and IX.4.2. For discussion of this claim, see esp. Dubouclez (2014, pp. 333–37); see also John of St. Thomas, Cursus theologicus 42.4 nn. 1–41 (John of St. Thomas 1931–1953, vol. 4, pp. 667a–79a); Cajetan, Commentaria in Summam theologiae [In ST] I.58.2 (Cajetan 1888–1906, vol. 5, pp. 82a–83b); Goris (2012, pp. 167–69); Suarez-Nani (2002, pp. 63–65); and Bonino (2016, p. 149). For Aquinas’s claim that the succession of angelic cognitive acts is non-continuous, see also the texts cited below in note 45. |
36 | For Aquinas’s claim that aeviternity is “conjoined” to a kind of time and that this is its main difference from eternity, see esp. ST I.10.5 (c. and ad 1–2), De pot. 3.14 ad s.c. 9, and Quodl. X.2 (esp. ad 4). For other places where he also claims that angels are measured by time with respect to their actions, but without identifying this as a difference between aeviternity and eternity, see ST I.57.3 ad 2 and I-II.113.7 ad 5; In Sent. II.2.1.1 ad 4; De ver. 8.4 ad 14–15 and 8.14 ad 12; and De Div. nom. 4.3 n. 310. (Oddly, none of the Sentences commentary’s three thematic discussions of aeviternity identify its “conjunction” to time as a factor distinguishing it from eternity at all.) Aquinas frequently cites Augustine’s claim in De Genesi ad litteram VIII.26 n. 48 (Augustine of Hippo 1845, p. 391) that God “movet per tempus creaturam spiritualem” as an authority for measuring angelic operations by a kind of time; for Aquinas’s thematic discussion of this Augustinian formula, see Quodl. II.3. |
37 | For explanations of Aquinas’s theory of angelic discrete time, see esp. Porro (1996, pp. 297–306, 316–20; 2001, pp. 150–58), Jocelyn (1946, pp. 39–57), and Suarez-Nani (1989, pp. 23–44), who, as noted in note 14, focuses on Nicholas of Strasburg but highlights Aquinas’s influence. For briefer explanations, see also Peter (1964, pp. 30, 34–35, 38, 68, 71–76), Goris (2012, pp. 168, 180), Bonino (2016, p. 124), and Suarez-Nani (2002, p. 57, fn. 1). For critical discussion, see Fox (2006, pp. 273–78), Cross (2012, pp. 141–46), and MacIntosh (1995). |
38 | Aquinas, In Sent. I.37.4.1 (Aquinas 1929–1947, vol. 1, pp. 779–80): “Secundus motus [angeli] est per tempus; quem assignat ei Augustinus, ut habetur in Littera; et quia tempus est mensura successivorum, ideo omnem successionem nominat motum per tempus. Invenitur autem successio in intellectu angeli: quod sic patet. Omnis intellectus qui cognoscit diversa per diversas species, non potest simul actu illa cognoscere, ut ex praedeterminatis patet [I.35.1.2 ad 3; Mandonnet erroneously gives the reference as I.25.1.2]. Intellectus autem angeli potest cognoscere res dupliciter, sive duplici specie: scilicet vel in consideratione Verbi, quod est una similitudo omnium rerum, et sic simul potest multa videre; vel per species innatas, vel concreatas rerum, quae sibi inditae sunt, quae plures plurium sunt; unde oportet quod secundum illas species non cognoscat plura simul. Unde secundum hoc est successio in intellectu angeli; et ista successio largo modo dicitur motus. Differt tamen a motu proprie dicto in duobus ad minus. Primo, quia non est de potentia in actum, sed de actu in actum. Secundo quia non est continuus: continuus enim motus est ex continuitate ejus super quod est motus, ut in Lib. V Physic. probatur. Sed inter duas species intellectas non est aliqua continuatio, sed successio tantum; et haec eadem successio motus dicitur; et similis ratio est de successione affectionum. “Tertius motus est secundum locum... Et quia moveri in loco sequitur ad esse in loco, ideo eodem modo convenit angelo moveri in loco sicut esse in loco: et utrumque est aequivoce respectu corporalium. Dicitur enim angelus esse in loco inquantum applicatur loco per operationem; et quia non simul est in diversis locis, ideo successio talium operationum per quas in diversis locis esse dicitur, motus ejus vocatur. Unde sicut conceptiones intellectus consequenter se habent sine continuatione, ita et operationes ejus; unde motus localis angeli non est continuus; sed ipsae operationes ejus consequenter se habentes circa diversa loca, secundum quas in illis esse dicitur, localis motus ejus vocantur.” See also ST I.53.1–2 and Quodl. I.3.2 ad 1. |
39 | For Aquinas’s claim that continuous motion requires a continuous magnitude to move through, see esp. In Phys. IV.17 nn. 6–7, IV.18 nn. 4 and 11, IV.19 n. 7, V.5 n. 4, VI.2 n. 2, and VIII.17 n. 7. See also ST I.53.1, In Sent. I.8.3.3 c. and ad 4 and I.37.4.3, Quodl. IX.4.4, and In Met. V.15 n. 985 and XI.10 n. 2354. |
40 | See In Sent. I.37.3.1, ST I.52.1, and Quodl. I.3.1; cf. In Sent. II.6.1.3 and De pot. 3.19 ad 2. |
41 | Even in this early work, Aquinas thinks this claim that angelic locomotion is necessarily non-continuous is compatible with the claim he makes in the following article (In Sent. I.37.4.2) that an angel’s locomotion can pass through all the intermediate places if he so wishes. However, as Aquinas recognizes in the later ST I.53.2 and Quodl. I.3.2, the latter claim seems to imply some sort of continuity on the part of the angel’s locomotion; see discussion of these passages below. |
42 | For Aquinas’s view on the subtle connection between the categories of time and quantity, see esp. In Met. V.15 nn. 985–96. For discussion of different interpretations of Aristotle’s view on the matter, focused on the possible difference between Aristotle’s “time” (χρόνος) and “when” (ποτέ) with respect to quantity, see Porro (1996, ch. 4). In particular, see p. 389 for a good formulation of the problem: why does Aristotle identify “when” (ποτέ) as a category in its own right while subsuming “time” (χρόνος) under the category of quantity? |
43 | For this definition of time and the claim that it derives its continuity from what it measures, see esp. In Phys. IV.17 nn. 10–11. Cf. In Phys. IV.19 nn. 2–4; In Sent. I.8.3.3 (c. and ad 4), I.19.2.1, II.2.1.1 ad 4 (cf. II.2.1.2 on time as the numerus numeratus of motion), and II.3.2.1 ad 5; ST I.10.6 and I.53.3; De ver. 28.2 ad 10; In Met. XI.10 n. 2354; and Quodl. II.3, IX.4.4 and XI.4. |
44 | In Sent. I.37.4.3 (Aquinas 1929–1947, vol. 1, pp. 889–90): “In tempore enim est aliquid quasi formale, quod tenet se ex parte quantitatis discretae, scilicet numerus prioris et posterioris; et aliquid materiale, per quod est continuum, quia continuitatem habet ex motu in quo est sicut in subjecto et primo mensurato, scilicet motu caeli, ut dicitur IV Phys. [text. 99]. Motus autem ille habet continuitatem ex magnitudine. Unde cum motus Angeli non sit continuus, quia non est secundum necessitatem conditiones habens magnitudinis per quam transit, sicut est in illis quae sunt sic nata in loco esse ut eorum substantia sit commensurata terminis loci, scilicet corporibus, sed per successionem operationum, in quibus nulla est ratio continuitatis; ideo tempus illud non est continuum, sed est compositum ex ‘nunc’ succedentibus sibi ut numerus ipsarum operationum succedentium sibi tempus vocetur, sicut ipsa successio operationum dicitur motus: et quot sunt operationes ex quibus componitur motus secundum diversa loca, tot erunt ‘nunc,’ ex quibus componitur tempus” (emphasis added). All translations of Aquinas are my own. For Aquinas’s parallel treatments of the discrete time measuring the succession of spiritual operations, see In Sent. I.8.3.3 c. and ad 4, I.19.2.1, II.2.1.1 ad 4, and II.3.2.1 ad 5; ST I.53.3 (c., ad 1, and ad 3), I.61.2 ad 2, I.62.5 ad 2, I.63.6 ad 4, I.85.4 ad 1, and I-II.113.7 ad 5; Quodl. II.3, IX.4.4, and XI.4; De malo 16.3 and 16.7 ad 3; and De ver. 28.2 ad 10. |
45 | De ver. 8.14 ad 12 (Aquinas 1882ff, vol. 22/2, p. 266b, lines 308–23): “operationes vero quae statim habent suam speciem completam, non mensurantur tempore nisi per accidens, sicut intelligere, sentire et huiusmodi, unde Philosophus dicit in X Ethicorum quod delectari non est in tempore; per accidens autem in tempore possunt esse tales operationes in quantum motui coniunguntur in natura tempori subiecta existentes, quae est natura corporea generabilis et corruptibilis qua ut organo potentiae sensitivae utuntur a quibus etiam noster intellectus accipit. Unde patet quod ipsum intelligere angeli neque per se neque per accidens cadit sub tempore; unde in una eius operatione qua intelligit unum intelligibile, non est prius et posterius” (emphasis added). See also In Sent. II.6.1.2 and IV.49.3.1.3; De substantiis separatis 20 ad fin. (though this text is essentially presenting an objection to which Aquinas never wrote a reply, this being an unfinished work); SCG II.96 n. 1820; Quodl. V.4; and In De causis, 7 and 31 (commenting on Liber de causis, 6 and 30, on which several of the foregoing texts rely). In De causis 31 and Quodl. V.4 are especially striking texts in which Aquinas asserts that angelic operations, no less than their substantial being, are in momento aeternitatis, i.e., measured by aeviternity. However, in Quodl. V.4 he restricts the claim to the angels’ proper operation. This “proper operation” is arguably the angels’ natural knowledge of self and God through their own essence, which (unlike their knowledge of other things through concreated species) is unceasing; see Porro (1996, pp. 203–5) and Peter (1964, pp. 5–8, 62). (See also In Sent. II.2.1.1 ad 4 and Quodl. X.2, where Aquinas seems to reserve aeviternity to the supernatural operation of beatitude.) Still, it seems to me that Aquinas at least could have said that even successive angelic acts are measured by aeviternity with respect to their own timeless inner duration, while still being measured by discrete time with respect to their succession. After all, Aquinas states at ST I.61.2 ad 2 that even the angels’ being, although intrinsically measured by aeviternity, is nonetheless measured by a kind of time inasmuch as it “succeeds” non-being (given the doctrine of their creation ex nihilo); and he explicitly compares this succession of the angels’ aeviternal being to the succession of their operations. |
46 | De ver. 8.9 ad 3 (Aquinas 1882ff, vol. 22/2, p. 251, lines 217–36): “Cum enim cognitio sit per assimilationem cognoscentis ad cognitum, hoc modo contingit novam cognitionem de aliquo accipere, quomodo contingit de novo aliquid alicui assimilari; quod quidem contingit dupliciter: uno modo per motum suum, alio modo per motum alterius ad formam quam ipse iam habet; et similiter aliquis incipit aliquid de novo cognoscere uno modo per hoc quod cognoscens de novo accipit formam cogniti, sicut in nobis accidit, alio modo per hoc quod cognitum de novo pervenit ad formam quae est in cognoscente. Et hoc modo angeli de novo cognoscunt praesentia quae prius fuerunt futura, ut puta si aliquid nondum erat homo, ei non assimilabatur intellectus angelicus per formam hominis quam habet apud se, sed cum incipit esse homo, secundum eandem formam incipit intellectus angelicus sibi assimilari sine aliqua mutatione facta circa ipsum” (emphasis added). See also esp. Quodl. VII.1.3 ad 2 (Aquinas 1882ff, vol. 25/1, p. 15a, lines 194–99): “Quando aliquid incipit esse presens, angelus de nouo cognoscit illud, non facta aliqua innouatione in ipso angelo, set in re cognoscibili, in qua est aliquid quod prius non fuit, quod simul ea cognita cognoscitur” (emphasis added), and cf. ad 1. For other instances of Aquinas’s claim that angels know changing events without any intrinsic change, see De ver. 8.11 ad 9, 8.12 ad 1 and ad 7–8, and 8.15 ad 4 and ad 7; ST I.57.3 ad 3 (cf. ad 4) and I.64.1 ad 5; and De malo 16.7 ad 6, ad 9, and ad 13. Cf. QD de an. 20 ad 4 and In Sent. II.7.2.1 ad 4 and II.11.2.4. For discussion of this claim, see, for example, John of St. Thomas, Cursus theologicus, 42.2, esp. nn. 1, 8, and 25–32 (John of St. Thomas 1931–1953, vol. 4); Cajetan, In ST I.57.2 n. 18 and I.58.5 n. 3 (Cajetan 1888–1906, vol. 5); Goris (2012, p. 181); Bonino (2016, p. 146, fn. 42); and Collins (1947, pp. 230–31). |
47 | In the afterlife, prior to the resurrection, Aquinas thinks the separated soul takes on an angel-like mode of knowing to replace the loss of its senses. However, he denies that the separated soul has natural knowledge of even present contingent events in the physical world on account of lacking the intellectual strength to use its newly infused intelligible species for this purpose; its natural knowledge of contingent things is now limited to the spiritual world. (Indeed, Aquinas is even uncertain if the separated souls of the blessed have supernatural knowledge of physical contingent events through the beatific vision.) See, for example, ST I.89.8, relying on I.89.1 and I.89.4. Hence, our puzzle of synchronizing discrete time with continuous time strictly concerns the angels, not separated souls, whose acts have no bearing on our continuous time. |
48 | ST I.58.4 (Aquinas 1882ff, vol. 5, p. 85a–b): “si intellectus statim in apprehensione quidditatis subiecti haberet notitiam de omnibus quae possunt attribui subiecto vel removeri ab eo, nunquam intelligeret componendo et dividendo, sed solum intelligendo quod quid est. Sic igitur patet quod ex eodem provenit quod intellectus noster intelligit discurrendo, et componendo et dividendo: ex hoc scilicet, quod non statim in prima apprehensione alicuius primi apprehensi, potest inspicere quidquid in eo virtute continetur. Quod contingit ex debilitate luminis intellectualis in nobis, sicut dictum est. Unde cum in angelo sit lumen intellectuale perfectum…; relinquitur quod angelus, sicut non intelligit ratiocinando, ita non intelligit componendo et dividendo. Nihilominus tamen compositionem et divisionem enuntiationum intelligit, sicut et ratiocinationem syllogismorum: intelligit enim composita simpliciter, et mobilia immobiliter, et materialia immaterialiter.” See also ST I.58.5 and I.85.5, and De malo 16.6 c. and ad s.c. 1. For discussion of angelic non-propositional knowledge of reality, see Feingold (2024), Bonino (2016, pp. 150–51), Goris (2012, pp. 171–73), Suarez-Nani (2002, pp. 65–68), Collins (1947, pp. 180–84), and Pegis (1940, p. 168). For more extensive treatments, see Cajetan, In ST I.58.4–5 (Cajetan 1888–1906, vol. 5, pp. 85–88) and John of St. Thomas, Cursus theologicus, 42.4 nn. 42–50 (John of St. Thomas 1931–1953, vol. 4, pp. 679a–81b). |
49 | De malo 16.6 ad s.c. 1 (Aquinas 1882ff, vol. 23, p. 312b, lines 449–52): “Vnde angelus per simplicem apprehensionem subiecti cognoscit esse uel non esse sicut et nos componendo et diuidendo.” |
50 | See also Aquinas’s discussions of the changelessness of God’s knowledge at ST I.14.15 ad 3 and De ver. 2.13 ad 7. The fact that God, like the angels, knows states of affairs (enuntiabilia) without needing to form propositions (“composing and dividing”) is, for Aquinas, a necessary condition for enabling God’s knowledge of changing events to be changeless and so timeless. |
51 | Aquinas, In Sent. I.37.4.3 ad 3 (Aquinas 1929–1947, vol. 1, p. 890): “Ad tertium dicendum, quod non potest accipi aliqua proportio temporis in quo movetur corpus, ad tempus in quo movetur Angelus, quia tempus quo movetur Angelus, non est divisibile divisione continui, sed discreti in plura instantia finita; in tempore autem quo movetur corpus, sunt infinita instantia in potentia; et ita nulla est proportio, sicut nec infiniti ad finitum” (emphasis added). For this claim that discrete and continuous time are incommensurable—that is, share no common measure—see also Quodl. II.3 (Aquinas 1882ff, vol. 25/2, p. 219b, lines 57–60): “Discretorum autem et continuorum non potest esse una mensura communis, cum sint diuersorum generum in quantum sunt mensurabilia.” Cf. ST I.53.3 ad 1 (Aquinas 1882ff, vol. 5, p. 35b): “si tempus motus angeli non sit continuum, sed successio quaedam ipsorum nunc, non habebit proportionem ad tempus quod mensurat motum corporalium, quod est continuum: cum non sit eiusdem rationis” (though, as we will see, Aquinas’s position in this text is more circumspect than in the Sentences commentary). |
52 | See the texts cited in note 43, esp. In Phys. IV.17 nn. 10–11. |
53 | See In Phys. IV.15 n. 5; cf. IV.16 n. 2 and IV.17 n. 3. Sharing a single time is unnecessary for simultaneity only when one of the two simultaneous things is an “exceeding measure” of the other, which is not the case for any physical motions. |
54 | For the causal role in earthly events that Aquinas attributes to the heavenly bodies, see, for example, ST I.115.3–6; SCG III.82 & 84–86; In Sent. II.15.1.2–3; De ver. 5.9–10; & Comp. theol. I.127–28. |
55 | For this argument that time is an accident inhering in a substance in motion, and that, therefore, the unity of physical time is due to the fact that all physical motions can be measured by the number of a single first motion, see: In Phys. IV.23 nn. 2 and 13 (cf. IV.17 nn. 2–4), ST I.10.6 (c. and ad 4), Quodl. II.3, In Sent. II.2.1.2 (c. and ad 1) and II.12.1.5 ad 2, and QD de spir. creat. 9 ad 11; cf. In Met. X.2 n. 1947. (See also Aquinas’s parallel argument at Quodl. V.4 for the need for a unifying primary angelic duration to allow angels to share the same aeviternity.) It should be noted, though, that for Aquinas, the absence of the first heavenly sphere would not spell the fragmentation of physical time; rather, as he argues at ST I.66.4 ad 3, in that case its time-unifying role would be taken over by whatever other motion was now the “first motion.” For discussion, see, for example, Moreno (1981, pp. 73–76). |
56 | For this suggestion, see Moreno (1981, pp. 76–79). The rationale for transferring the first sphere’s unifying role to light’s movement would be that modern relativity theory asserts that light’s movement is the maximum movement possible and, indeed, that the passage of time for any given thing is measured by how closely the thing approximates light’s movement. Given this, it does not seem implausible that the numbering of light’s movement should also serve as an extrinsic measure for the movement of all other things. |
57 | For Aquinas’s claim in other contexts that angels are unaffected by the heavenly bodies’ movement, see ST I.115.5 and De pot. 6.10. |
58 | For this argument against the possibility of any unifying measure for physical and angelic motion, see esp. In Sent. I.19.2.1 and I.37.4.3, ST I.53.3, and Quodl. II.3, IX.4.4, and XI.4. |
59 | Aquinas, ST I.53.1 (Aquinas 1882ff, vol. 5, p. 30a–b): “Quia enim angelus non est in loco nisi secundum contactum virtutis, ut dictum est, necesse est quod motus angeli in loco nihil aliud sit quam diversi contactus diversorum locorum successive et non simul: quia angelus non potest simul esse in pluribus locis, ut supra dictum est. Huiusmodi autem contactus non est necessarium esse continuos. Potest tamen in huiusmodi contactibus continuitas quaedam inveniri. Quia, ut dictum est, nihil prohibet angelo assignare locum divisibilem, per contactum suae virtutis; sicut corpori assignatur locus divisibilis, per contactum suae magnitudinis. Unde sicut corpus successive, et non simul, dimittit locum in quo prius erat, et ex hoc causatur continuitas in motu locali eius; ita etiam angelus potest dimittere successive locum divisibilem in quo prius erat, et sic motus eius erit continuus. Et potest etiam totum locum simul dimittere, et toti alteri loco simul se applicare: et sic motus eius non erit continuus” (emphasis added). See also the immediately ensuing ST I.53.2. |
60 | ST I.53.3 (Aquinas 1882ff, vol. 5, p. 35a): “Unde relinquitur quod motus angeli sit in tempore. In continuo quidem tempore, si sit motus eius continuus; in non continuo autem, si motus sit non continuus (utroque enim modo contingit esse motum angeli, ut dictum est): continuitas enim temporis est ex continuate motus, ut dicitur in IV Physic.” (emphasis added). |
61 | ST I.53.3 ad 1 (Aquinas 1882ff, vol. 5, p. 35b): “si tempus motus angeli non sit continuum, sed successio quaedam ipsorum nunc, non habebit proportionem ad tempus quod mensurat motum corporalium, quod est continuum: cum non sit eiusdem rationis. Si vero sit continuum, est quidem proportionabile, non quidem propter proportionem moventis et mobilis, sed propter proportionem magnitudinum in quibus est motus.” |
62 | ST I.53.3 (Aquinas 1882ff, vol. 5, p. 35a): “Sed istud tempus, sive sit tempus continuum sive non, non est idem cum tempore quod mensurat motum caeli, et quo mensurantur omnia corporalia, quae habent mutabilitatem ex motu caeli. Motus enim angeli non dependet ex motu caeli” (emphasis added). |
63 | ST I.63.6 ad 4 (Aquinas 1882ff, vol. 5, p. 133a–b): “inter quaelibet duo instantia esse tempus medium, habet veritatem inquantum tempus est continuum, ut probatur in VI Physic. [VI.1.231b9]. Sed in angelis, qui non sunt subiecti caelesti motui, qui primo per tempus continuum mensuratur, tempus accipitur pro ipsa successione operationum intellectus, vel etiam affectus.” Cf. ST I.61.2 ad 2 and I.62.5 ad 2. |
64 | ST I-II.113.7 ad 5 (Aquinas 1882ff, vol. 8, p. 339a–b): “Si qua enim successio sit ibi affectuum vel intellectualium conceptionum, puta in Angelis, talis successio non mensuratur tempore continuo, sed tempore discreto, sicut et ipsa quae mensurantur non sunt continua, ut in Primo habitum est. Unde in talibus est dandum ultimum instans in quo primum fuit, et primum instans in quo est id quod sequitur: nec oportet esse tempus medium, quia non est ibi continuitas temporis, quae hoc requirebat” (emphasis added). |
65 | Quodl. II.3 (Aquinas 1882ff, vol. 25/2, p. 219b, lines 64–74): “Manifestum est autem quod motus spiritualium creaturarum … non sunt motus continui, set uicissitudines quedam discrete... Vnde manifestum est quod, cum tempus non habeat continuitatem nisi ex motu, quod tale tempus non est continuum et quod est aliud a tempore corporalium rerum.” For the dates of the Prima Pars and this Quodlibet see Torrell (2005, pp. 146 and 211, respectively). |
66 | In Sent. I.37.4.2 (Aquinas 1929–1947, vol. 1, p. 884): “secundum quod habet aliquid operari vel in omnibus mediis locis, vel in aliquibus vel in nullo, secundum hoc potest pertransire omnia media vel quaedam vel nullum.” |
67 | In Sent. I.37.4.2 ad 5 (Aquinas 1929–1947, vol. 1, pp. 884–85): “angelus potest pertransire per omnia media; non tamen oportet quod numeret infinita puncta existentia in linea: quia locus in quo est angelus, non semper est indivisibilis, sed quandoque divisibilis, ut dictum est; et cum nullum spatium dividatur in infinita divisibilia actu accepta, constat quod omnia media pertransire potest.” |
68 | Quodl. I.3.2 ad s.c. (Aquinas 1882ff, vol. 25/2, pp. 182b–83a, lines 63–71): “angelus non est in loco per commensurationem, set per applicationem sue uirtutis ad locum, que quidem potest esse indifferenter et ad locum diuisibilem et ad indiuisibilem; unde potest continue moueri, sicut aliquid in loco diusibili existens, continue intercipiendo spacium; secundum uero quod est in loco indiuisibili, non potest eius motus esse continuus, nec pertransire omnia media” (emphasis added). |
69 | See note 59 above. |
70 | See, for example, In Sent. I.37.4.1 (Aquinas 1929–1947, vol. 1, p. 880), where he explicitly defines the angel’s locomotion as the “successio talium operationum per quas in diversis locis esse dicitur” (emphasis added). |
71 | See ST I.53.1 (Aquinas 1882ff, vol. 5, p. 30b), where he instead defines the angel’s locomotion as “diversi contactus diversorum locum successive et non simul” (emphasis added). |
72 | In Sent. I.37.4.2 (Aquinas 1929–1947, vol. 1, p. 884): “essentia angeli… non definitur ad locum nisi per operationem; non autem per operationem secundum quod exit ab essentia, sed secundum quod terminatur ad operatum in loco” (emphasis added). |
73 | This point that locomotion is not a change in the angel is, I take it, part of what Aquinas meant by insisting in ST I.53.1 (Aquinas 1882ff, vol. 5, p. 30a) that “angelus non est in loco ut commensuratus et contentus, sed magis ut continens.” |
74 | For a similar account of Aquinas’s apparently conflicting texts on whether the time measuring angelic locomotion time can be continuous (indeed barely noting the conflict at all), see Porro (1996, pp. 300–305; 2001, pp. 155–56). John of St. Thomas, by contrast, thinks that Aquinas changed his mind in a notable way; see Cursus theologicus 40.4 n. 14 (John of St. Thomas 1931–1953, vol. 4, p. 524a). |
75 | Aquinas, De malo 16.7 arg. 3 (Aquinas 1882ff, vol. 23, p. 313a, lines 16–26): “Si demones sunt substantie incorporee, oportet quod secundum substantiam et operationem sint supra tempus, secundum illud uod dicitur in libro De causis, quod intelligentie substantia et operatio est supra tempus; set presens, preteritum et futurum sunt differentie temporis; ergo quantum ad cognitionem demonis non differt utrum sit aliquid presens, preteritum aut futurum. Set demones possunt cognoscere presentia et preterita. Ergo etiam possunt cognoscere futura.” |
76 | Aquinas, De malo 16.7 ad 3 (Aquinas 1882ff, vol. 23, p. 316a, lines 274–80): “substantia et operatio demonis est quidem supra tempus quod est numerus motus caeli; tamen in eius operatione adiungitur tempus, secundum quod non omnia simul actu intelligit. Quod quidem tempus est uicissitudo quedam affectionum et conceptionum intelligibilium.” This is also the gist of the parallel response at ST I.57.3 ad 2 (Aquinas 1882ff, vol. 5, p. 75b), which is similarly unhelpful for our purposes: “licet intellectus angeli sit supra tempus quo mensurantur corporales motus, est tamen in intellectu angeli tempus secundum successionem intelligibilium conceptionum... Et ita, cum sit successio in intellectu angeli, non omnia quae aguntur per totum tempus, sunt ei praesentia.” |
77 | Aquinas, De malo 16.7 arg. 4 (Aquinas 1882ff, vol. 23, p. 313a–b, lines 27–35): “Set dicebat quod ad hoc quod aliquid possit cognosci non solum requiritur quod cognoscens sit presentialiter et in actu, set etiam cognitum.—Set contra. Certior est cognitio Dei quam cognitio demonis. Si ergo ad certitudinem cognitionis demonis requiritur quod cognitum sit presentialiter in actu, multo magis hoc requiretur ad cognitionem Dei; et sic nec Deus futura cognosceret. Quod est inconueniens.”—Ad 4 (Aquinas 1882ff, vol. 23, p. 316a, lines 283–87): “Ad quartum dicendum quod alia ratio est de Deo, qui totum tempus presentialiter intuetur eo quod eius intellectus est omnino liber a tempore et sic respicit futurum ut existens; quod non potest dici de angelo uel demone.” The reply to the eighth objection (Aquinas 1882ff, vol. 23, p. 316b, lines 329–38) makes a similar point: “licet species que sunt in intellectu angelico sint utcumque similes rationibus ydealibus intellectus diuini, non tamen possunt eas adequare, ut uidelicet ad omnia se extendant ad que se extendunt rationes ydeales intellectus diuini. Vnde licet ydeales rationes intellectus diuini, que penitus sunt supra tempus, se habeant indifferenter ad presens, praeteritum et futurum, non sequitur quod eodem modo se habeat de speciebus intellectus angelici.” See also QD de spir. creat. 5 ad 7 for this contrast between the divine and angelic intellects. |
78 | Aquinas, De malo 16.7 arg. 5 (Aquinas 1882ff, vol. 23, p. 313b, lines 39–42): “Cum igitur intellectus abstrahat ab hic et nunc, uidetur quod non differat quantum ad cognitionem demonis utrum aliquid sit presens, preteritum uel futurum.”—Ad 5 (Aquinas 1882ff, vol. 23, p. 316b, lines 295–303): “Intellectus autem angeli boni uel mali abstrahit ab hic et nunc quantum ad ipsas species intelligibiles, que sunt immateriales et uniuersales, non autem quantum ad ipsa cognita: cognoscit enim per species intelligibiles propter earum efficaciam non solum uniuersalia set etiam singularia; et ita differt in cognitione demonis cognoscere presentia uel futura.” See also the parallel response at De ver. 8.12 ad 8. |
79 | See note 46 above. |
80 | Aquinas, De malo 16.7 ad 6 (Aquinas 1882ff, vol. 23, p. 316b, lines 304–21): “angeli non cognoscunt singularia, quando fiunt in actu, per species de nouo acquisitas set per species quas prius habebant, per quas tamen non cognoscebant ea prout erant futura. Cuius ratio est quia omnis cognitio fit per quamdam assimilationem cognoscentis et cogniti; species autem intelligibiles que sunt in intellectu angelico sunt directe similitudines respicientes naturas specierum; per quas tamen singularia cognoscere possunt, non tamen nisi in quantum participant naturam specierum, quod non est antequam sint in actu: et ideo statim quando sunt in actu cognoscuntur ab angelo, sicut e conuerso accidit apud nos quod oculus statim quod accipit speciem lapidis cognoscit lapidem preexistentem; forme enim intellectus angelici preexistunt rebus temporalibus sicut forme rerum preexistunt sensibus nostris.” See also the reply to the ninth objection (Aquinas 1882ff, vol. 23, p. 317a, lines 345–50): “species intellectus angelici secundum seipsas semper eodem modo se habent, set ex transmutatione indiuiduorum naturalium prouenit quod quandoque assimilantur speciebus existentibus in intellectu angeli, quandoque autem non assimilantur.” The reply to the thirteenth objection (Aquinas 1882ff, vol. 23, p. 317a–b, lines 377–82) also hinges on this principle that a changeless species only serves as a medium for knowledge of a changeable thing when that changeable thing has, in fact, begun to participate in the represented nature: “hoc quod demon non cognoscit id quod est futurum, non prouenit ex eo quod intellectus suus sit in potentia, set ex eo quod singulare futurum nondum participat formam speciei cuius similitudo actu preexistit in intellectu demonis.” The parallel response at ST I.57.3 ad 3 (Aquinas 1882ff, vol. 5, p. 75b) follows the same lines as De malo 16.7 ad 6: “licet species quae sunt in intellectu angeli, quantum est de se, aequaliter se habeant ad praesentia, praeterita et futura; tamen praesentia, praeterita et futura non aequaliter se habent ad rationes. Quia ea quae praesentia sunt, habent naturam per quam assimilantur speciebus quae sunt in mente angeli: et sic per eas cognosci possunt. Sed quae futura sunt, nondum habent naturam per quam illis assimilentur: unde per eas cognosci non possunt.” See also De ver. 8.12 ad 1 & ad 8 (as well as 8.9 ad 3); Quodl. VII.1.3 ad 1; QD de spir. creat. 5 ad 7; and QD de an. 20 ad 4. |
81 | Aquinas, In Sent. I.37.4.3 arg. 7 (Aquinas 1929–1947, vol. 1, p. 887): “moveatur angelus de A in B, ita quod in hoc instanti quod est C, sit in A, et in hoc instanti quod est D, sit in B. Item ponatur quod aliquod corpus sit G, et moveatur similiter de A in B, et incipiat simul moveri cum angelo, scilicet in C. Inde sic. Angelus citius pervenit ad B, quam corpus G. Ergo in instanti D corpus nondum pervenit ad B; sed erit citra B. Et sit ille locus R. Inde sic. G movetur de A in R, in tempore CD. Sed spatium AR est divisibile. Dividatur ergo in puncto H [following the Parma edition (6:309a); Mandonnet mistakenly has “G” instead of “H”]. Inde sic. Corpus illud, scilicet G, in instanti C est in A, et in instanti D est in R. Ergo H erit in aliquo alio instanti medio inter illa duo, et sit illud N. In N ergo Angelus vel erit in A vel in B, vel in medio. Sed non in A, quia sic in duobus instantibus esset in eodem ubi; et eadem ratione non est in B. Ergo oportet quod in instanti N sit in medio: et sic semper procedendo, invenitur inter quaelibet duo instantia instans et tempus. Ergo oportet quod motus angeli sit in tempore continuo.” |
82 | See John Pecham, Quodl. II.10 n. 6 (Pecham 1989, p. 99, lines 22–36): “Item, quod [angeli] in primo instanti fuerunt boni et statim immediate fuerunt mali, impossibile videtur. Quoniam inter quaelibet duo instantia cadit tempus medium, et instans instanti non est continuum nec contiguum, nec consequenter ens.—Sed dicunt quod est tempus quod est continuum et mensura continui, et tempus aliud quod est discretum et compositum ex instantibus quod mensurat operationes angelorum instantaneas, et de hoc non est verum.—Sed contra: Accipiamus unum instans temporis discreti in quo fuit bonus, et dicatur a, et al.iud instans in quo fuit malus, et dicatur b. A instans est simul cum aliquo instanti temporis continui, quia etiam aetemitas Dei est simul cum tempore; sit c. Item, b est simul cum aliquo instanti illius communis temporis; sit d. Aut ergo c et d sunt unum instans aut duo. Si unum, in eadem ergo instanti fuit angelus bonus et malus. Si duo, sed inter quaelibet instantia illius temporis [scil. temporis continui] cadit tempus medium, ergo aliqua erat pars temporis in quo vel cum quo angelus nec erat bonus nec malus.” For discussion and endorsement of this argument, see Fox (2006, pp. 276–77) and following him Cross (2012, p. 143). |
83 | For the origin of this principle, which Aquinas relies on in all his treatments of instantaneous change, see Aristotle Physics VI.6.237a34–b21 (Aristotle 1984); cf. Aquinas, In Phys. VI.8 nn. 9 and 15. |
84 | Besides In Sent. I.37.4.3 c. & arg. 8–9/ad 8–9, see also esp. ST I.53.3 (which, like In Sent. I.37.4.3 arg. 8, focuses on the “quies” of the angel in the original place in non-continuous locomotion), as well as Quodl. IX.4.4 and XI.4. |
85 | Again, following the Parma edition; see note 18. |
86 | Aquinas, In Sent. I.37.4.3 ad 7 (Aquinas 1929–1947, vol. 1, p. 891): “si ponatur motus angeli et corporis simul incipere, quando angelus erit in alio termino secundum aliud instans sui temporis, corpus etiam erit in alio termino secundum aliud instans sui temporis. Inter duo autem instantia temporis istius corporis est tempus medium in eo quod motus ejus est continuus; unde est ibi signare medium instans. Sed inter duo instantia angeli non est tempus medium. Unde nec medium instans oportet ibi signari, sed contingit signari, si in tribus locis successive sit, quia ita etiam tempus ex tribus ‘nunc’ componetur; unde unum erit medium; et illa duo instantia possunt includere omnia instantia temporis, cum etiam unum nunc et instans [Parm: “aevi stans”] includat omne tempus: et ita non est inconveniens quod dum motus angeli est in duobus tantum instantibus, motus corporis sit in infinitis; quamvis quantumcumque duret motus corporis, tantumdem etiam duret motus angeli, et quamvis utrumque non sit indivisibile. Et praeterea contingit quod quando corpus est in medio instanti, angelus in nullo loco sit, cum non sit necessarium, eum semper esse in loco, ut dictum est [I.37.4.1]; et ita secundum coordinationem illius temporis nullum ‘nunc’ angelo respondeat, sed tantum aevum” (emphasis added). |
87 | That “including” in this context means merely “surrounding” rather than “being simultaneous with the whole duration” is even clearer in the preceding reply to the fifth objection (In Sent. I.37.4.3 ad 5). |
88 | Cf. Porro’s similar discussion of In Sent. I.37.4.3 ad 7 (Porro 1996, pp. 318–20, 327). |
89 | See note 82. |
90 | See esp. In Phys. II.6 n. 9, In Met. V.3 n. 794, and Expositio libri Posteriorum II.10 (Aquinas 1882ff, vol. 1*/2, p. 212a, lines 40–54); for discussion, see Frost (2022, pp. 52–57). |
91 | See, for example, John of St. Thomas, Cursus theologicus 10.3 n. 2 and 40.4 n. 36 (John of St. Thomas 1931–1953, vol. 2, p. 98; vol. 4, p. 530a). For this reason, in the latter text he calls angelic instants “virtualiter divisibiles.” Cf. Jocelyn (1946, p. 52). |
92 | See the texts cited above in notes 45–46 and 80. |
93 | See ST I.53.1–3, Quodl. I.3.2, and In Sent. I.37.4.2, discussed above. Cf. Aquinas’s claim that angels can move physical objects from one place to another, presumably by continuous motion, at, for example, ST I.110.3, De pot. 6.3, and Quodl. IX.4.5. |
94 | For a similar argument, see John of St. Thomas, Cursus theologicus 40.4 n. 17 (John of St. Thomas 1931–1953, vol. 4, pp. 524b–25a). |
95 | For the text of In Sent. I.19.2.2 ad 1, see note 28 above. |
96 | For Aquinas’s explicit claim that eternity “includes” (includit) all times, see, for example, ST I.10.2 ad 4 and I.13.1 ad 3; De ver. 2.12 and 3.3 ad s.c. 1; and Super Io. 16.3. |
97 | See the texts cited above in note 84. |
98 | For Aquinas’s defense of this assumption, see, for example, ST I.52.2 (cf. I.8.2 ad 2 and I.112.1) and In Sent. I.37.3.2. |
99 | See ST III.75.7 (esp. ad 1), In Sent. IV.11.1.3.2, and Quodl. VII.4.2. |
100 | See De ver. 28.9 (cf. 28.2 ad 10), ST I-II.113.7 (esp. ad 5), and In Sent. IV.17.1.5.2–3. |
101 | See ST I-II.113.7 ad 5. |
102 | De ver. 28.9 (Aquinas 1882ff, vol. 22/3, pp. 846b–47a, lines 192–99): “oportet quod transitus de uno in alterum sit in instanti,—quamvis causa huius privationis successive tollatur, vel secundum quod homo cogitando disponit se ad gratiam, vel saltem secundum quod tempus praeterit post quod Deus se gratiam daturum praeordinavit –, et sic gratiae infusio fit in instanti” (emphasis added). |
103 | MacIntosh, surprisingly, does not consider this aspect of Aquinas’s view. As a result, while he rightly argues that Aquinas could have allowed the physical time measuring the angel’s action on the original place to be an “open interval” extending up to, but not including, the first instant of the angel’s action on the destination, he wrongly infers that Aquinas could, therefore, have done away with the discreteness of the angel’s time as well (MacIntosh 1995, pp. 564–75). |
104 | Bernard Lonergan argues that Aquinas, in his early work, considered causal actions to be inherent in the agent, but that he later, at the time of writing the De potentia, the Summa theologiae’s Prima Pars, and the Physics commentary, shifted to the more faithfully Aristotelian view that such actions exist only in the effect (Lonergan 2000, pp. 66–73, 253–77). While I do not think that the difference between Aquinas’s early and mature views on this issue is as deep as Lonergan claims (in part because De pot. 8.2, a mature text, seems to reaffirm the early view), he is right at least to point to a shift in emphasis on Aquinas’s part. For a recent discussion of the problem of action’s ontological location in Aquinas, see Frost (2018, pp. 47–82; 2022, pp. 158–88). |
105 | In the continuous angelic locomotion Aquinas envisions in ST I.53.3, by contrast, it seems to me that there would be no succession of angelic instants at all, since there would only be one angelic action involved, not two. Thus, in this case, the only time measuring the locomotion would be the physical time measuring the continuous (and thus still not instantaneous) change in the place affected by the angel. |
106 | See, for example, Aristotle Physics VI.1.231a29–b9; cf. Aquinas In Phys. VI.1 nn. 4–5. |
107 | This move allows us, for example, to avoid Godfrey of Fontaines’s argument all angelic indivisible instants must correspond to a stretch of physical time on the grounds that two different angelic acts—even ones that had nothing to do with the physical world—would require two parallel physical instants with the accompanying intermediate physical time because, otherwise, two contradictory things would be true at the same physical instant. See his Quodlibet VI.13 (Godfrey of Fontaines 1914; for discussion, see Porro 1996, p. 344). Instead, I am suggesting that neither of those angelic acts occurs at any physical instant at all. |
108 | For Aquinas on instantaneous changes, see notes 99 and 100. |
109 | Presumably, this “beginning” would be the origin of the physical universe. However, as we saw earlier, God could, if he wished, create an angel “at” a later point in our history by making the angel’s aeviternity simultaneous only with a certain part of our history. In that case, the “beginning” for this angel would be the first moment of physical history with which the angel’s existence is simultaneous. |
110 | For this view that it is up to the angel how much physical time should correspond to his changeless act, see John of St. Thomas, Cursus theologicus 40.4 n. 36 (John of St. Thomas 1931–1953, vol. 4, p. 530a); cf. Jocelyn (1946, pp. 53–54) and Porro (2008, p. 82). |
111 | While Aquinas does not explicitly discuss whether angels all share the same discrete time, he does frequently say that they all share the same aeviternity, namely that of the highest and simplest angel. See In Sent. II.2.1.2 (c. and ad 5), ST I.10.6, and esp. Quodl. V.4 (c. and ad 1), where Aquinas says that not only the highest angel’s being but also his equally aeviternal “proper operation” (arguably his natural knowledge of self and God; see note 45 above) measure the other angels’ aeviternity. (Aquinas brings in “proper operation” in this text to explain why Lucifer would not still be the measure of the blessed angels’ duration!) One might, therefore, reasonably suppose that, by the same token, they would all share the discrete time of the highest angel with the simplest and richest successive operations. See Jocelyn (1946, pp. 52–53), citing Cajetan In ST I.10.5 n. 13 (Cajetan 1888–1906, vol. 4, p.102b) and John of St. Thomas, Cursus theologicus 10.3 n. 4 (John of St. Thomas 1931–1953, vol. 2, p. 98). Nonetheless, even if there were no hierarchy here and thus no common discrete time, the different angels’ discrete instants would presumably still be simultaneous with each other; for, as we have seen, Aquinas thinks that even measures as radically different as aeviternity and physical time can still be simultaneous with each other. |
112 | The alternative would be to deny that angelic instants always align exactly with each other and hold instead that one angelic instant can “take longer” than another, such that one angel can traverse several instants while another remains motionless in a single instant. This is John of St. Thomas’s view; see Cursus theologicus 10.3 nn. 3 & 6 (John of St. Thomas 1931–1953, vol. 2, pp. 98–99), endorsed by Jocelyn ( 1946, pp. 54 and 56). On this alternative view, Angel B would not be able to converse with Angel A at all until he had “caught up” on the physical universe’s history. However, this alternative has the awkward consequence that it makes angelic time dependent on physical time as the real objective yardstick, and this, in turn, would give angelic acts intrinsic temporal extension like that of our own human spiritual acts, which is quite incompatible with discrete time. (To return to the recent example, if Angel B in his at2 wanted to ask Angel A about what Angel A had seen in the physical universe, he would have to wait—distending an angelic instant!—until Angel A “finished” his billion-year act of observation.) Moreover, Aquinas himself seems to assume that angelic instants do align exactly with each other in his discussions of Lucifer’s temptation of the other angels in their first instant; see in ST I.63.8 (cf. I.63.6 ad 4) and In Sent. II.6.1.2. This is perhaps not decisive, since Aquinas assumes that the angels in their first instant were considering themselves, not the physical world. Still, it at least strongly suggests that angelic instants are perfectly synchronous. |
113 | See esp. In Sent. I.38.1.5; see also the preceding In Sent. I.38.1.4, ST I.14.9 and I.14.13, De ver. 2.12, De malo 16.7, Expositio libri Peryermeneias [In Pery.] I.14 (Aquinas 1882ff, vol. 1*/1), De rationibus fidei ad cantorem Antiochenum [De rat. fid.] 10 (Aquinas 1882ff, vol. 40/B), Quodl. IX.3, Comp. theol. I.133, and SCG I.66 nn. 543 and 546 and I.67 nn. 557–58 and 564. |
114 | For Aquinas’s use of this illustration, see ST I.14.13 ad 3, In Pery. I.14 (Aquinas 1882ff, vol. 1*/1, p. 77b, lines 379–93), Quodl. XI.3, De malo 16.7, De rat. fid. 10, and Comp. theol. I.132. |
115 | See, for example, ST I.19.1 (for the identity of God’s willing to his existence), 4 ad 4 (for the identity of God’s will to his intellect), and 7 (for the changelessness of God’s will to intervene at various points in history); cf. II-II.83.2 (on why petitionary prayer does not “change God’s mind”). |
116 | For the causality of God’s knowledge, see ST I.14.8, In Sent. I.38.1.1, and De ver. 2.14. It is perhaps worth noting that one can hold the “causal knowledge” claim without holding the stronger claim that God knows by preordaining what will happen. It is true that Luis de Molina, one of the foremost opponents of the “preordaining” claim, does think this position requires rejecting the “causal knowledge” claim, too, at least with respect to contingent realities; see Concordia I.1 nn. 5–6 (de Molina 1876). Jacques Maritain, however, another well-known opponent of the “preordaining” claim, nonetheless vigorously affirms the “causal knowledge” claim even regarding contingent realities insofar as they are positive beings (see for example Maritain 1948, pp. 105–13). Maritain can do so because he holds that free creatures “nullify” God’s causal action when they sin; thus, even though God knows by causing, what he actually causes is subject to the free creature’s “nullification” rather than preordained. On this view, then, one could reject the “preordaining” claim and still hold that angels, unlike God, would have to will creatures in an act subsequent to their knowledge. |
117 | See notes 46 and 80 above. |
118 | See esp. ST I.14.8 ad 1 and De ver. 2.14 ad 1. |
119 | See ST I.58.3, where Aquinas denies that angels engage in discursive reasoning, and I.59.3 ad 1, where he infers that, therefore, angelic free choice does not require deliberation. |
120 | See De malo 16.4, as well as ST I.63.5. |
121 | Again, see notes 46 and 80 above. |
122 | Aquinas elaborates this theory of the numerical identity of relations primarily in texts on whether Christ has one or two relations of “sonship”: ST III.35.5, Quodl. I.2.1 (cf. IX.2.3), and In Sent. III.8.1.5. |
123 | See esp. In Phys. V.3 nn. 7–8; see also De pot. 7.8 (c. and ad 5) and 7.9 ad 7, and In Sent. I.26.2.1 ad 3 and I.30.1.1 (though it is less clear that this last text is specifically about real relations). For discussion, see esp. Henninger (1989, pp. 19–23). |
124 | See In Sent. II.2.1.1, Quodl. X.2, and ST I.10.5 for Aquinas’s adamantine insistence that one cannot admit “before” and “after” (prius et posterius) into a duration without also admitting sequential temporal parts. The context in these passages is Aquinas’s rejection of Bonaventure’s view, which he states at In Sent. II.2.1.1.3 (Bonaventure 1885) that aeviternity can lack “newness” or “aging” (innovatio and inveteratio) yet still be extended into “before” and “after”; but the principle would equally exclude “before” and “after” from a partless, non-successive instant. |
125 | For a clear statement of this causal criterion of per accidens causation, see, for example, In Sent. IV.17.2.1.3 ad 3 (Aquinas 1856–1858, vol. 7, p. 784a): “quamvis motus intellectus et voluntatis habeat totam suam speciem in uno instanti, sicut res permanens; tamen secundum accidens mensuratur tempore, secundum quod causae suae variabiles sunt per tempus” (emphasis added). I follow the Parma edition in reading “permanens” instead of “permanent,” as Moos has it (Aquinas 1929–1947, vol. 4, p. 862). For Aquinas’s notion of per accidens divisibility in general, see, for example, In Phys. VI.7 n. 8 (in the context of motion); cf. ST I.76.8 (in the context of the soul). |
126 | For the per accidens temporal extension of physical existence, see In Sent. IV.17.1.5.2 ad 3, IV.17.1.5.3 ad 1, IV.17.2.1.3 ad 3, and IV.49.3.1.3; ST I-II.31.2; Quodl. IV.3.2; De pot. 5.1 ad 2 and 5.4 ad 1; SCG I.20 n. 175; and In Phys. VIII.21 n. 15. The last three texts are noteworthy in that Aquinas there considers whether to apply the notion of per accidens temporal extension also to the incorruptible heavenly bodies; interestingly, he answers affirmatively in the earlier SCG text but negatively in the later De Pot. and In Phys. texts. The fact that, for Aquinas, causal dependence on motion is central to per accidens temporal extension is also presumably why Aquinas never applies the notion of per accidens temporal extension to aeviternity, even though it would otherwise seem plausible that the angel’s aeviternal existence should be per accidens distended by the sequence of his acts: for his existence is in no way dependent on his acts or their sequence. Porro critiques this claim of Aquinas that substantial sublunar existence is in time only per accidens (Porro 2008, pp. 82–83), though perhaps without giving sufficient weight to the causal dependence aspect on which the claim rests. |
127 | For the per accidens temporal extension of sensory acts based on the physical change of the sense organ, see In Sent. IV.17.1.5.2 ad 3 and De ver. 8.14 ad 12; for the same claim based instead on the sense act’s physical, mutable object, see In Sent. IV.49.3.1.3 (c. & ad 3) and ST I-II.31.2 c. (cf. ad 1). See also In Sent. I.8.3.3 ad 4, which ascribes per accidens temporality to any act of the soul that is in some way connected to the body, and IV.17.1.5.3 ad 1, which attributes per accidens temporality to sensory acts without giving a reason. |
128 | For the phantasm-based per accidens temporal extension of human spiritual acts, see In Sent. IV.17.1.5.2 ad 3, IV.17.2.1.3 ad 3, and IV.49.3.1.3; SCG I.102 n. 846; ST I.107.4, I-II.31.2 ad 1, and I-II.113.7 ad 5; De ver. 8.14 ad 12; De substantiis separatis 20 ad fin.; and In Pery. I.14 (Aquinas 1882ff, vol. 1*/1, pp. 77b–78a, lines 393–97). For the same point without explicitly using the term “per accidens,” see also ST I.85.5 ad 2, SCG II.96 n. 1820, and In Sent. I.38.1.3 ad 3. For the role that the phantasm plays in Aquinas’s theory of human intellectual knowledge, see, for example, ST I.84.7–8. |
129 | See, for example, De ver. 2.14 (Aquinas 1882ff, vol. 22/2, p. 92a, lines 86–91), where Aquinas states that angelic knowledge is neither caused by the object like ours nor causes the object like God’s: “Sed scientia angelorum neque est causa rerum neque ab eis causata est sed utrumque est ab una causa: sicut enim Deus formas naturales influit rebus ut subsistant ita similitudines earum infundit mentibus angelorum ad cognoscendum res.” |
130 | For Aquinas’s contrast of the per accidens temporal extension of human spiritual acts with the absolute unextendedness of angelic acts, see esp. De ver. 8.14 ad 12 (quoted above in note 45); see also In Sent. IV.49.3.1.3, ST I.107.4 and I-II.113.7 ad 5, and De substantiis separatis 20 (Aquinas 1882ff, vol. 40/D, p. 79b, lines 298–307). John of St. Thomas claims to follow Aquinas in rejecting even per accidens temporal extension in angelic cognition; see Cursus theologicus 40.5 n. 37 (John of St. Thomas 1931–1953, vol. 4, pp. 542b–43a). Nonetheless, in practice, he actually seems to endorse something even stronger than per accidens extension, since he holds that the angel’s intelligible species itself—and therefore, presumably, also the cognitive act arising from that species—changes intrinsically insofar as it becomes applied to different individual objects (rather than merely depending on some extrinsic changing thing: either for the act’s existence, as with ordinary per accidens extension, or for its relations, as my “modest” model proposes). See this striking passage from Cursus theologicus 42.2 n. 56 (John of St. Thomas 1931–1953, vol. 4, p. 653b): “variatio intrinseca in specie [i.e., in the angel’s concreated intelligible species] non est essentialis seu formalis, sed modalis, seu determinatio quaedam virtualiter et implicite contenta in illa specie ex vi suae primae infusionis, nunc autem de novo explicata ex vi ejusdem infusionis ad positionem objecti singularis… Variatio autem modalis, seu determinatio materialis, consistit in applicatione aliqua eorum quae representabantur quasi in abstracto et quidditative, et modo determinate applicantur in exercitio hic et nunc, posita aliqua condicione quae ante non ponebatur” (emphasis added). If nothing else, this apparent inconsistency on the part of such a master of Aquinas’s angelic theory as John of St. Thomas indicates just how thorny the issue is. |
131 | See esp. De ver. 2.8, where the causality of God’s knowledge is the only explanation Aquinas gives for why that knowledge extends to future things, without mentioning God’s eternity. See also SCG I.66 nn. 543 & 546 and I.67 nn. 562–63, where the appeals to God’s causal knowledge to explain God’s foreknowledge are separate from parallel appeals to God’s eternity in the same chapters, and In Sent. I.38.1.5, where Aquinas brings up the causality of God’s knowledge first as an objection to God’s knowledge of future contingents, and then again only to instantly insist that this causal route is not God’s only way of knowing future contingents—“Deus ab aeterno non solum vidit ordinem sui ad rem, ex cujus potestate res erat futura, sed ipsum esse rei intuebatur” (Aquinas 1929–1947, vol. 1, p. 911; emphasis added)—spending the rest of the response instead on developing the “eternal present” approach. |
132 | In particular, see In Sent. I.38.1.5 (Aquinas 1929–1947, vol. 1, p. 911), where Aquinas claims that being able to observe different events at different times by a single non-successive act is a sufficient condition for seeing them all together “side by side,” as God does: “Sint quinque homines qui successive in quinque horis quinque contingentia facta videant. Possum ergo dicere, quod isti quinque vident haec contingentia succedentia praesentialiter. Si autem poneretur quod isti quinque actus cognoscentium essent actus unus, posset dici quod una cognitio esset praesentialiter de omnibus illis cognitis successivis. Cum ergo Deus uno aeterno intuitu, non successivo, omnia tempora videat, omnia contingentia in temporibus diversis ab aeterno praesentialiter videt” (emphasis added). Yet on the “modest” model the angel does precisely that, and nonetheless sees those events sequentially. |
133 | For texts on God’s eternity-based foreknowledge which do not mention the causality of God’s knowledge at all, see ST I.14.9 and I.14.13, In Sent. I.38.1.4, De ver. 2.12, De malo 16.7, In Pery. I.14 (Aquinas 1882ff, vol. 1*/1, pp. 77b–78b, lines 369–436, De rat. fid. 10, Quodl. IX.3, and Comp. theol. I.133. For eternity-based texts occurring alongside causality-based texts rather than in dependence on them, see SCG I.66 nn. 543 and 546 and I.67 n. 557–58 and 564; and see also In Sent. I.38.1.5, where, again, Aquinas’s preferred eternity-based approach is explicitly contrasted with the causality-based approach. |
134 | Aquinas may perhaps have been reluctant to ground God’s foreknowledge in the “causal knowledge” thesis in order to avoid appearing to eliminate created contingency and freedom by conflating God’s foreknowledge with a puppetmaster’s control-based foreknowledge. This appearance really stems, however, from holding the “causal knowledge” thesis in the first place (to which Aquinas is certainly committed), not from making that thesis the basis of foreknowledge. As previously noted, holding the “causal knowledge” thesis, even with its implication that God’s knowledge “already contains” the object in its determinate existence, need not, in fact, necessarily imply that God has “preordained” creatures’ free evil acts if, for example, Maritain is right that God allows his causation to be subject to the free creature’s “nullification”; see note 116. |
References
- Aquinas, Thomas. 1856–1858. Commentum in quatuor libros Sententiarum magistri Petri Lombardi. Vols. 6–7 of Sancti Thomae Aquinatis opera omnia. Parma: Typis Petri Fiaccadori. [Google Scholar]
- Aquinas, Thomas. 1882ff. Sancti Thomae Aquinatis Doctoris Angelici Opera omnia, iussu impensaque Leonis XIII P.M. edita. Leonine edition. Vol. 1*/1, Expositio libri Peryermeneias, 2nd ed. Vol. 1*/2, Expositio libri Posteriorum, 2nd ed. Vol. 2, Commentaria in octo libros Physicorum Aristotelis. Vols. 4–12, Summa theologiae. Vol. 22/1–3, Quaestiones disputatae De veritate. Vol. 23, Quaestiones disputatae De malo. Vol. 24/1, Quaestiones disputatae De anima. Vol. 24/2, Quaestiones disputatae De spiritualibus creaturis. Vol. 25/1–2, Quaestiones de quolibet. Vol. 28, Expositio super Isaiam ad litteram. Vol. 40/B, De rationibus fidei ad cantorem Antiochenum. Vol. 40/D, De substantiis separatis. Vol. 42, Compendium theologiae, Responsio de 30 articulis, Responsio de 36 articulis, etc. Vol. 43, De aeternitate mundi, De sortibus, etc. Rome: Typographia Polyglotta Vaticana. [Google Scholar]
- Aquinas, Thomas. 1929–1947. Scriptum super libros Sententiarum magistri Petri Lombardi Episcopi Parisiensis. Edited by Pierre Mandonnet (vols. 1–2) and Marie Fabien Moos (vols. 3–4). Paris: Lethielleux. [Google Scholar]
- Aquinas, Thomas. 1950. In librum Beati Dionysii De divinis nominibus expositio. Edited by Ceslao Pera, Pietro Caramello and Carlo Mazzantini. Turin and Rome: Marietti. [Google Scholar]
- Aquinas, Thomas. 1951. Super Evangelium S. Matthei lectura, 5th ed. Edited by Raffaele Cai. Turin and Rome: Marietti. [Google Scholar]
- Aquinas, Thomas. 1953. Super Epistolas S. Pauli lectura, 8th ed. Vol. 1, Super Epistolam ad Romanos Lectura, Super primam Epistolam ad Corinthios lectura, etc. Vol. 2, Super primam Epistolam ad Thessalonicenses Lectura, etc. Edited by Raffaele Cai. Turin and Rome: Marietti. [Google Scholar]
- Aquinas, Thomas. 1954. Super librum De Causis expositio. Edited by Henri-Dominique Saffrey. Fribourg: Société Philosophique. Louvain: Éditions E. Nauwelaerts. [Google Scholar]
- Aquinas, Thomas. 1961. Liber de Veritate Catholicae Fidei contra errores Infidelium seu Summa contra Gentiles. 3 vols. Edited by Ceslao Pera, Pietro Marc and Pietro Caramello. Turin and Rome: Marietti. [Google Scholar]
- Aquinas, Thomas. 1965. De potentia. In Quaestiones disputatae, 8th ed. Edited by Paul M. Pession. Turin and Rome: Marietti, vol. 2, pp. 1–276. [Google Scholar]
- Aquinas, Thomas. 1971. In duodecim libros Metaphysicorum Aristotelis expositio, 2nd ed. Edited by M.-R. Cathala and Raimondo M. Spiazzi. Turin and Rome: Marietti. [Google Scholar]
- Aquinas, Thomas. 1972. Super Evangelium S. Ioannis lectura, 6th ed. Edited by Raffaele Cai. Turin and Rome: Marietti. [Google Scholar]
- Aristotle. 1984. The Complete Works of Aristotle: The Revised Oxford Translation. 2 vols. Edited by Jonathan Barnes. Bollingen Series 71.2. Princeton: Princeton University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Augustine of Hippo. 1845. De Genesi ad litteram libri XII. Vol. 34 of Patrologiae cursus completus, Series Latina. Edited by Jaques-Paul Migne. Paris: Migne, pp. 245–486. [Google Scholar]
- Bonaventure. 1885. In Secundum Librum Sententiarum magistri Petri Lombardi. Vol. 2 of Opera omnia. Quaracchi: Editiones Collegii S. Bonaventurae ad Claras Aquas. [Google Scholar]
- Bonino, Serge-Thomas. 2016. Angels and Demons: A Catholic Introduction. Translated by Michael J. Miller. Washington, DC: The Catholic University of America Press. [Google Scholar]
- Cajetan, Thomas (Thomas de Vio). 1888–1906. Commentaria in Summam theologiae. In Sancti Thomae Aquinatis Doctoris Angelici Opera omnia, iussu impensaque Leonis XIII P.M. edita. Leonine edition. Rome: Typographia Polyglotta Vaticana, vols. 4–12. [Google Scholar]
- Collins, James. 1947. The Thomistic Philosophy of the Angels. Washington, DC: The Catholic University of America Press. [Google Scholar]
- Cross, Richard. 2012. Angelic Time and Motion: Bonaventure to Scotus. In A Companion to Angels in Medieval Philosophy. Edited by Tobias Hoffmann. Leiden: Brill, pp. 117–47. [Google Scholar]
- de Molina, Luis. 1876. Concordia liberi arbitrii cum gratiae donis, divina praescientia, providentia, praedestinatione et reprobatione. Paris: Lethielleux. [Google Scholar]
- Dubouclez, Olivier. 2014. Plura simul intelligere. Éléments pour une histoire du débat médiéval et renaissant sur la simultanéité des actes de l’intellect. Recherches de Théologie et Philosophie Médiévales 81: 331–67. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Feingold, Francis. 2024. Can Angels Know Being Without Judgment? In Summa Metaphysicae ad Mentem Sancti Thomae: Essays in Honor of John F. Wippel. Edited by Therese Scarpelli Cory and Gregory T. Doolan. Washington, DC: The Catholic University of America Press, pp. 227–75. [Google Scholar]
- Fox, Rory. 2006. Time and Eternity in Mid-Thirteenth-Century Thought. Oxford: Oxford University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Frost, Gloria. 2018. Aquinas’ Ontology of Transeunt Causal Activity. Vivarium 56: 47–82. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Frost, Gloria. 2022. Aquinas on Efficient Causation and Causal Powers. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Godfrey of Fontaines. 1914. Les Quodlibet cinq, six et sept de Godefroid de Fontaines. Edited by Maurice De Wulf and Jean Hoffmans. Les Philosophes Belges 3. Louvain: Institut Supérieur de Philosophie de l’Université. [Google Scholar]
- Goris, Harm. 2003. Interpreting Eternity in Thomas Aquinas. In Time and Eternity: The Medieval Discourse. Edited by Gerhard Jaritz and Gerson Moreno-Riaño. International Medieval Research 9. Turnhout: Brepols, pp. 193–202. [Google Scholar]
- Goris, Harm. 2012. Angelic Knowledge in Aquinas and Bonaventure. In A Companion to Angels in Medieval Philosophy. Edited by Tobias Hoffmann. Leiden: Brill, pp. 149–85. [Google Scholar]
- Henninger, Mark. 1989. Relations: Medieval Theories 1250–1325. Oxford: Clarendon Press. [Google Scholar]
- Jocelyn, Marie. 1946. Discrete Time and Illumination. Laval Théologique et Philosophique 2: 39–57. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- John of Saint Thomas. 1931–1953. Cursus theologici, opera et studio monachorum quorumdam solesmensium O.S.B. editus. Paris: Desclée, 4 vols. [Google Scholar]
- Lonergan, Bernard. 2000. Grace and Freedom: Operative Grace in the Thought of St Thomas Aquinas. Vol. 1 of Collected Works of Bernard Lonergan. Edited by Frederick E. Crowe and Robert M. Doran. Toronto: University of Toronto Press. [Google Scholar]
- MacIntosh, J. J. 1995. St. Thomas on Angelic Time and Motion. The Thomist 59: 547–75. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Maritain, Jacques. 1948. Existence and the Existent. Translated by Lewis Galantiere, and Gerald B. Phelan. New York: Pantheon. [Google Scholar]
- Moreno, Antonio. 1981. Time and Relativity: Some Philosophical Considerations. The Thomist 45: 62–79. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Oliva, Mirela. 2022. The Experience of Prophecy and the Metaphysics of Providence in Aquinas. Religions 13: 921. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Pecham, John. 1989. Fr. Ioannis Pecham quodlibeta quatuor. Edited by Girard J. Etzkorn. Bibliotheca Franciscana Scholastica Medii Aevi 25. Grottaferrata: Collegio S. Bonaventura Padri editori di Quaracchi. [Google Scholar]
- Pegis, Anton. 1940. In Umbra Intelligentiae. The New Scholasticism 14: 146–80. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Peter, Carl J. 1964. The Doctrine of Thomas Aquinas Regarding Eviternity in the Rational Soul and Separated Substances. Ph.D. dissertation, Pontificia Universitas S. Thomae de Urbe, Rome, Italy. [Google Scholar]
- Porro, Pasquale. 1996. Forme e modelli di durata nel pensiero medievale. L’aevum, il tempo discreto, la categoria “quando”. Louvain: Louvain University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Porro, Pasquale. 2001. Angelic Measures: Aevum and Discrete Time. In The Medieval Concept of Time: Studies on the Scholastic Debate and Its Reception in Early Modern Philosophy. Edited by Pasquale Porro. Leiden: Brill, pp. 131–59. [Google Scholar]
- Porro, Pasquale. 2002. Aevum. In Dictionnaire du Moyen Âge. Edited by Claude Gauvard, Alain de Libera and Michel Zink. Paris: Quadrige and PUF, pp. 12–14. [Google Scholar]
- Porro, Pasquale. 2008. The Duration of Being. In Das Sein der Dauer. Edited by Andreas Speer and David Wirmer. Miscellanea Mediaevalia 34. New York: De Gruyter, pp. 75–88. [Google Scholar]
- Suarez-Nani, Tiziana. 1989. Tempo ed essere nell’autunno del medioevo: Il De tempore di Nicola di Strasburgo eil dibattito sulla natura ed il senso del tempo agli inizi del XIV secolo. Amsterdam: B. R. Grüner. [Google Scholar]
- Suarez-Nani, Tiziana. 2002. Connaissance et langage des anges. Paris: J. Vrin. [Google Scholar]
- Torrell, Jean-Pierre. 2005. The Person and His Work. Vol. 1 of Saint Thomas Aquinas, rev. ed. Translated by Robert Royal. Washington, DC: The Catholic University of America Press. [Google Scholar]
Disclaimer/Publisher’s Note: The statements, opinions and data contained in all publications are solely those of the individual author(s) and contributor(s) and not of MDPI and/or the editor(s). MDPI and/or the editor(s) disclaim responsibility for any injury to people or property resulting from any ideas, methods, instructions or products referred to in the content. |
© 2024 by the author. Licensee MDPI, Basel, Switzerland. This article is an open access article distributed under the terms and conditions of the Creative Commons Attribution (CC BY) license (https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/).
Share and Cite
Feingold, F. Why Can’t Angels See Our Future? Aquinas’s View of the Relation between Continuous and Discrete Time. Religions 2024, 15, 441. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel15040441
Feingold F. Why Can’t Angels See Our Future? Aquinas’s View of the Relation between Continuous and Discrete Time. Religions. 2024; 15(4):441. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel15040441
Chicago/Turabian StyleFeingold, Francis. 2024. "Why Can’t Angels See Our Future? Aquinas’s View of the Relation between Continuous and Discrete Time" Religions 15, no. 4: 441. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel15040441
APA StyleFeingold, F. (2024). Why Can’t Angels See Our Future? Aquinas’s View of the Relation between Continuous and Discrete Time. Religions, 15(4), 441. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel15040441