2. Data Set
Evaluation of the existence of the broken-heart syndrome effect requires data which details the time of death of both members of a couple. Survey data collected at the University of Ghana is used to motivate the model proposed in this paper. Questions relating to the grandparents of a sample of students at the university include their number of children, living situation and the circumstances of their death in addition to the date at which they died.
Data processing revealed the full data set comprises 246 couples, 38 couples failing to have experienced at least one death were removed from the sample since the waiting time between deaths is the variable of interest. Couples corresponding to errors within the data collection were removed, in addition to outliers and those with incomplete data in regard to time of death. This leaves a total of 145 couples consisting of 61 double deaths and 84 single deaths, with 37 and 52 male first deaths, respectively. Since a number of bereaved spouses survived the observation period determined by the survey completion date, the data are said to be right-censored. The survival curve for the sample is displayed in
Figure 1, with censored data points indicated.
Figure 2a,b show the distribution of male and female death times within a couple, whilst
Figure 2c illustrates the number of deaths per year of bereavement. A total of eight bereaved spouses died within the first year of bereavement, corresponding to 13.1% of bereaved individuals in the sample. Although the death rate decreased to 5 out of the 61 bereaved spouses in the second year of bereavement, eight deaths were again observed in year five. Couples along the red line in
Figure 2b are those exhibiting the classical features of broken-heart syndrome, with survival time less than one year.
The Pearson correlation between male and female deaths is 0.362773 when considering the whole sample; however, since year of birth range for the male spouse subset is approximately 55 years, the data were split into two cohorts to test for existence of a generational effect.
Figure 3 and
Figure 4 correspond to the cohorts of paired lives such that male year of birth falls in the intervals 1899–1926 and 1927–1954, respectively. After removal of outliers and couples with incomplete date of birth, 29 couples remained in cohort one and 28 couples in cohort two.
During the first year of bereavement, five surviving spouses died in cohort one, representing 17.2% of the bereaved sample. Following a drop in the number of deaths upon survival of the first year, a second peak of four deaths was observed in year four. The proportion of bereaved deaths experienced in the second cohort was 10.7% during the first year of bereavement with the deaths of three bereaved spouses, and reached a maximum of 21.4% with six deaths in year five. In addition to the differing patterns of bereaved deaths observed in
Figure 3 and
Figure 4, with the older cohort achieving its peak frequency much later, the Pearson correlation between male and female deaths within the sub-samples varies significantly. Correlation coefficients are −0.008397 and 0.4188 in the first and second cohorts respectively, suggesting the existence of a potential change in reactions to bereavement across generations.
A second data set was collected at the African Institute for Mathematical Sciences in Rwanda. Following exclusion of couples within which either one or both spouses were alive, the sample consisted of 38 couples from a total of 12 African countries. Due to construction of the survey in this case, the data collected reveals only intervals within which the survival time corresponding to each couple lies, although the maximum number of deaths once more occurs within the first period of bereavement.
Taking interval extremes and considering the upper bound of survival time, 23.7% of the bereaved sample died in the third year of bereavement with a second peak of 15.8% in year six, whilst 26.3% of the bereaved sample died in the first year when assuming the lower bound of survival time followed by 18.4% in year two, with no further peaks. The Pearson correlation between male and female deaths was fairly low with values of −0.2250 and −0.06755 for the upper and lower bounds, respectively, initiating consideration of the existence of country specific trends. Within this analysis, couples of Cameroonian and Ghanaian origin appear to behave in a similar fashion, whilst paired death times corresponding to Rwandese couples are widely distributed. The occurrence of mass death events such as the Rwandan genocide in 1994 may be proposed as potential causes of disruption in the general mortality pattern. Although the results perhaps imply the impact of broken-heart syndrome differs across developing countries, further analysis is required in relation to this hypothesis since it is difficult to draw such a conclusion from a data set of this size.
Previous investigations into the impacts of the effect have to the best of our knowledge regarded a group originating from a developed country as their sample population.
Rees and Lutkins (
1967) discuss their findings following an investigation into the mortality of bereaved close relatives. The number of deaths documented vary significantly from the control group in the first year of bereavement, with 11.6% of deaths followed by the death of a close relative in comparison to just 1.6% in the control. Subsequent to this, the percentage of total deaths in the bereaved group falls to a rate of 1.99%, not differing significantly from the comparative non-bereaved rate.
Focusing specifically on the effect of a death within a married couple,
Rees and Lutkins (
1967) found that fitting with the general trend of the data the severity of increases in mortality were greatest during the first year of bereavement, after which the magnitude of rate elevation diminishes. The mortality rate of widowers within the year following the loss of the deceased was 19.6%, a value sizeably greater than the same rate for widows (8.5%). In the case of widowers, the pattern of changing mortality differs slightly from the general findings of the investigation, 13.7% of widowers at risk died within the first six months following the bereavement whilst just 5.9% died in the second, a difference in mortality found to be significant at the 1% level.
Although Ghanaian survey data supports the suggestion that broken-heart syndrome exists in countries of all levels of development, comparison with existing literature prompts the proposal behaviour under broken-heart syndrome may differ. The significant decrease in mortality following survival of the first year of bereavement is a characteristic prevalent in much of the research in this area; however, the decreasing trend of mortality with increasing year since bereavement, although apparent, cannot be identified with such high initial concentration and decay rate in the Ghanaian data. Such dissimilarities lead us to define a mortality model representing the impact of a dependence with less immediate significance. In the following section, we introduce the model proposed before considering the impact of assumption of dependence on the pricing of joint-life insurance products in
Section 4.
3. Model Description
Inclusion of the probabilistic framework in the stochastic mortality model proposed by
Jevtić and Hurd (
2017) prompted the decision to implement a similar model within our investigation. Whilst multiple state models such as the semi-Markov chain model applied by
Ji et al. (
2011) offer transparency and the ability to observe whether the level of risk changes following a death event, the probabilistic mechanism also enables incorporation of the health of both members of a couple prior to the primary death. This feature increases the accuracy of the dependence model by permitting varied responses to the initial death, where dependence may be irregular across the population, determined by the health circumstances of each couple under consideration. Although we focus on the short-term dependence of coupled lives, the model proposed is capable of addressing both short- and long-term structures, with the ability to encompass any existence of dependence between two lifetimes before the death of one spouse. In this section, we propose an adaptation of the stochastic mortality model with probabilistic framework described by
Jevtić and Hurd (
2017), first defining a number of important concepts for survival analysis.
Fundamental in modelling mortality risk, the survival function of an individual aged
x, referred to as
, specifies the probability the individual survives for at least
t years and is defined by
where
is the remaining lifetime of
. Manipulation of this function allows for calculation of the force of mortality, such that
where
is the force of mortality of
for
, describing the instantaneous rate at which the individual experiences death. The force of mortality of an individual
at time 0 is given by
Analagous to the pricing at time
t of a default-free zero-coupon bond with maturity
, under the assumption of a credit risk setting, the conditional probability of a stopping time
exceeding some arbitrary time
, where
is doubly stochastic with intensity
, can be shown to satisfy
where
represents the information at time
t. When implemented in mortality modelling, the stopping time
often represents the remaining lifetime of an individual.
3.1. Probabilistic Mechanism
Let be a complete probability space where is a filtration satisfying the usual conditions of right continuity and completeness, large enough to carry a d-dimensional Brownian motion W, two exponentially distributed random variables and , and a single uniformly distributed random variable U. Within this space, the set is fully independent, with a realisation of the time of death of each partner following from every realisation of the randomly generated elements. Allowing T to represent a finite time horizon of suitable length, the Brownian filtration is defined over the interval and is given by for , where is a sub-filtration of . When applying the model to a sizeable population, an index , where N is the number of couples in the sample, should be added to every element whose properties are specific to a particular pair.
Consider two coupled lives aged x and y at time 0 with future lifetimes and , respectively. The instantaneous forces of mortality at time t given by for , are predictable -adapted processes driven by the Brownian motion W. The spouse whose death occurs first is identified as the deceased partner and denoted . Equivalently, the spouse who survives the first death is denoted q and labelled the bereaved partner. The remaining lifetime of spouse p, conditional on the information set , is the first jump-time of a nonexplosive inhomogeneous Poisson counting process N with parameter , where counts the number of deaths at time t, for . The remaining lifetime of spouse q is defined in an analogous manner, with both doubly stochastic stopping times representing and driven by the sub-filtration .
The first time of death
is therefore given by
whilst the uniform random variable
U allows for identification of the deceased spouse through comparison with a function of the forces of mortality at the instant of the primary death. Recalling that
p is the label given to the partner who dies first, we have
In line with the belief the loss of a spouse has an impact on the mortality of the surviving spouse,
is defined for
as the mortality intensity of the bereaved partner following the initial death. This force of mortality is an adjustment of the original
and the association between the two rates reflects the influence losing a partner has on the bereaved spouse’s health and hence their remaining lifetime. The bereavement effect is described by
the change in mortality process, where the modified process
is inclusive of a structural break at
representing the instant effect on the bereaved spouse’s mortality. The instantaneous rise at the first death time is given by a linear combination of the mortality of each spouse at time
directly before the death, such that
where coefficients
and
are assumed to be non-negative. Intuitively, the mortality jump reflects the short-term dependence structure of broken-heart syndrome and modification of
the adaptations in the mortality intensity of the surviving spouse due to adjustments in the life circumstances of the bereaved. Inclusion of the mortality intensity of both spouses in the estimation of the bereavement jump given in Equation (
5) allows for incorporation of unobserved shared frailties.
Determined using a similar approach to the first time of death
, the second time of death
is given by
The model proposed is a variation of the reduced form modelling approach frequently used in the study of credit risk to model default as a stopping time whose occurrence is unexpected. Implementation of this method in regard to dependencies of bereaved partners suggests a change in the remaining lifetime of the bereaved spouse does not occur following the primary death, since random variables used in the determination of the time of death of each spouse , are required to be independent across the index. Inclusion of the modified intensity resolves this limitation.
Determination of the structure of dependence across a population may be of interest in addition to dependence between a particular couple. To model the dependence relationship amongst a whole population, risk factors experienced commonly by all individuals and risks specific to each member of the population should be considered. These factors are labelled systematic and idiosyncratic risks, respectively, and are an independent collection of factors by construction, with correlation between individuals induced by the risks shared among those under consideration.
The objective of the probabilistic mechanism is to determine the joint probability density function for the times of death of two coupled lives
. Theorem 1 provides an expression for the joint density proposed with proof in
Jevtić and Hurd (
2017), where expectations are taken under the probability measure
and it is assumed the death events do not occur simultaneously.
Theorem 1 - 1.
The joint probability density function for the time of death of two coupled lives is given by the reduced form expression - 2.
The marginal probability density function for the time of the first occurring death isfor
3.2. Stochastic Mortality Model with Non-Mean-Reverting Cox–Ingersoll–Ross Mortality Processes
It is common practice in financial modelling to assume the stochastic mortality intensity
to be an affine process, due to their analytical tractability. Under sufficient technical conditions, the affine assumption gives rise to the expression
where
and
are unique functions satisfying generalised Riccati ordinary differential equations. Owing to the convenience of affine jump-diffusions, we propose a stochastic mortality model under the assumption of affine mortality intensities, assuming a cohort of single-life mortality models in continuous time with correlated, non-mean-reverting Cox–Ingersoll–Ross (CIR) processes representing the paired mortality intensities
and
. For further discussion and treatment of affine processes, see
Duffie et al. (
2003).
The adapted CIR processes are defined by
where the parameters
,
, and
are positive. Let
be a three-dimensional Brownian motion; each Brownian motion
and
can then be considered as a linear combination of two independent Brownian motions such that
which gives
Here, and represent the random idiosyncratic risk factors specific to each member of the couple and reflects the random couple specific risk factors commonly experienced by both members of the pair, an example of which is the mutual living environment often shared by coupled lives. Weights and are selected in order to satisfy , where and is the Pearson correlation between and . Introducing correlation between the two Brownian motions in this way allows for dependence prior to the initial death and enables the capturing of unobserved heterogeneities assumed to be shared between coupled lives.
Remark 1. Selection of population specific risk factors for representation in the component of the Brownian motions and rather than the couple specific risks assumed in this paper initiates a non-diversifiable risk to insurers, creating with certainty, a long-term effect for companies which should be considered in the pricing and valuation of insurance products.
The final step in establishing the model is to define the bereavement effect explicitly, since determination of the second death time requires inclusion of the modified process
, for
. With correlation between coupled lives reflected in the paired Brownian motions, the bereavement model explains the causal relation between remaining lifetimes and the true contagion effect of the loss of a spouse. Specification of the bereavement process determines the dependence structure assumed to exist between the lives of interest, such flexibility in the model allows for consideration of all dependence classifications as required.
Jevtić and Hurd (
2017) define
as a deterministic function with dynamics given by
for values of
t greater than the initial time of death
. In the deterministic case, the law of large numbers implies diversification of the risk associated with the loss of a spouse, we therefore propose an alternative approach to modelling the bereavement jump facilitating the existence of a non-diversifiable bereavement risk such that the associated premium must account for the change in mortality experienced after the first death. We fix coefficients
and
of Equation (
5) at zero for computational simplicity; however, selection of positive values for
and
allows for incorporation of the mortality intensities of both lives prior to the first death in the initial value of the bereavement effect at time
.
Definition 1. The change in mortality process has dynamics given by an Ornstein–Uhlenbeck process such thatwhere is an independent d-dimensional Brownian motion, and .The explicit solution of the bereavement process for is We assume the bereavement process defined in Definition 1 to be of affine type to allow for computation of the joint probability density function.
Remark 2. The volatility of the bereavement process driven by the Brownian motion in Equation (12) is a determining feature of the nature of dependence. Fixing across the whole population infers the occurrence of an event experienced individually by all bereaved spouses at some future point in time. Such an event induces a non-diversifiable risk, posing a significant threat to the insurance industry in practice and creating the need for premiums which account for the observed change in mortality. On the other hand, assumption of a couple specific value for means the future event risk is diversifiable, through the insuring of a large and varied sample of couples. Selection of as either fixed or varying should be determined through observation of data. Establishing a more detailed underwriting process would help in the identification of unobserved heterogeneities, reducing the dependence risk associated with this component of the bereavement process. Estimation of the volatility in Equations (9) and (11) may also be facilitated through increased data collection; however, since the existence of a future event common to all lives is not apparent in the data set analysed, we assume to be couple specific, acknowledging the possibility that a more populated data set may support the need for a change in this assumption. When pricing a reversionary annuity in Section 4, the volatility coefficient does not appear in the indifference price. Since the risks associated with the correlated Brownian motions are diversifiable through inclusion of only couple specific risk factors, this independence of is of no concern in our case. In the non-diversifiable case discussed in Remark 1, however, the initial value of the bereavement effect given in Equation (11) should be redefined in order to incorporate both and the causal dependence between the members of each couple, to ensure the price of the insurance product covers the risk associated with a spousal loss. Remark 3. The Brownian motion of the bereavement process is assumed to be independent of the paired Brownian motions associated with mortality intensity. If the Brownian motion in Equation (11) is instead given by , the change in mortality of the surviving spouse upon the death of their partner is assumed to be correlated with their mortality before the primary death. The independence assumption adopted in this paper increases the importance of random risks, such as environmental factors, in determination of the impact of the loss, rather than historical mortality. The existence of dependence between the bereavement process and the mortality of the surviving spouse before the death at time , although an interesting concept, is not considered in this paper. In the Ornstein-Uhleneck model of bereavement proposed, the mean reversion parameter is fixed at zero due to the decreasing significance of the mortality gap over time associated with the subsiding nature of the mortality elevation, characteristic of broken-heart syndrome. In contrast to the exponential model of bereavement assumed in
Jevtić and Hurd (
2017), mean reversion allows for the process to take both positive and negative values, accounting for instances when the mortality of the bereaved improves in comparison to a non-widowed mortality.
After establishing the structure of the bereavement effect, expectations required for the joint probability density and survival function calculations can be computed through application of the affine framework with term structure equation determined by the Feynman–Kac formula. The conditional formula whose specific form is used in the calculation of bond prices (see, for example,
Grasselli and Hurd (
2015)), is given by
where
and
are constant and
for
.
Proposition 1. Application of the Feynman–Kac Formula to Equation (13) for non-mean-reverting Cox–Ingersoll–Ross processes givesandwhere . The derivative of Equation (13) with respect to is thenwhere and are given by and , respectively, such thatand Three corollaries follow Proposition 1 whose proof is detailed in
Appendix A. The explicit form of the expectations of interest under conditions appropriate in the mortality context are given in Corollary 1, whilst Corollaries 2 and 3 provide expressions for the joint probability density and survival functions, respectively. For proof of Corollary 2, see
Appendix B.
Corollary 1. The specific form of the conditional formula required for calculation of both the probability density and survival functions occurs when constants and are fixed at 1 and 0, respectively, which givesandwhereand Throughout the remainder of the paper, we will refer to functions and as and , respectively.
Corollary 2. The joint probability density function for death times and with bereavement process of Ornstein–Uhlenbeck type is given by the expressionfor , where , and are as defined in Corollary 1, and and are unique functions satisfying the generalised Riccati ordinary differential equations for the Ornstein–Uhlenbeck bereavement process , such thatandEvaluating the derivatives of and with respect to in line with Proposition 1 and Corollary 2, givesand For further details on calculation of the joint probability density function, refer to Appendix B. and are as computed in Jevtić and Hurd (2017). Remark 4. The joint probability density function for the case is analogous to Corollary 2, with indices interchanged.
Under the assumption of independent coupled lives, the convenience of the affine environment allows for the survival probability of an individual aged
x to be given by
Due to the changing mortality of the bereaved spouse upon the initial death at time
, consideration of dependent lives requires the redefinition of the survival function in Equation (
28). We instead regard the survival function for
to be the product of two survival functions, split at the first jump time
such that
Therefore, in accordance with the affine process selection for mortality intensity, the expression
holds for
, whilst the survival probability for
is determined through application of the law of total probability, which leads to Corollary 3.
Corollary 3. The survival probability of an individual assuming a mortality intensity of non-mean reverting Cox–Ingersoll–Ross type is given bywhere is defined by Equation (21). Remark 5. The survival probability of spouse is analogous to the survival probability of spouse detailed in Corollary 3, with indices interchanged.
One example of incorporating the model proposed in the pricing of a joint-life insurance contract using the indifference pricing principle approach is given in the following section.
4. Indifference Price Calculation for a Joint-Life Insurance Product
When pricing in the incomplete financial market setting, the utility indifference principle is an approach introduced by
Hodges and Neuberger (
1989) which compares the maximal expected utilities of an investor with and without taking a risk. Initially implemented in the pricing of European options and motivated by the unrealistic assumption of no transaction costs in the pure Black–Scholes model, extensions of the method have since been developed by
Davis et al. (
1993) and
Ludkovski and Young (
2008) among others, with the latter considering mortality contingent claims in a fully stochastic setting. In relation to life insurance, such an approach involves equating the expected utility of an insurer when a certain number of insurance policies are written to the expected utility when such policies are not written. The indifference premium of interest to our research is the change in premium which should be charged when dependence of coupled lives is assumed.
Various articles detail application of the indifference principle to pricing in the life insurance sector.
Young and Zariphopoulou (
2002) implement the approach in the valuation of insurance risks in the dynamic financial market setting. Extensions of their results are presented by
Delong (
2009) and
Liang and Lu (
2017) who follow similar procedures in order to determine indifference premiums.
Liang and Lu (
2017) apply a jump-diffusion model of Black–Scholes type to model the stochastic price of a risky asset with jumps given by a shot-noise process, whilst
Delong (
2009) makes use of a Lévy process in order to drive price dynamics. In both cases, the mortality intensity is assumed to be a stochastic process of diffusion type. Further distinction between the two papers appears in the definition of the policyholder benefits, with
Delong (
2009) defining benefits as fixed rates and
Liang and Lu (
2017) proposing the indifference premium for an equity-linked life insurance contract with benefits dependent on the value of the underlying asset.
Choi (
2016) adapts further work by
Young (
2003) in line with
Liang and Lu (
2017) through implementation of the equivalent utility principle for valuation of equity-linked life insurance in order to obtain the indifference price of an insurance contract in both the deterministic and stochastic mortality cases. Solution of a stochastic optimisation problem determined through solving the associated Hamilton–Jacobi–Bellman equation enables calculation of the indifference premium in each of
Delong (
2009);
Choi (
2016) and
Liang and Lu (
2017). Explicit solutions of the optimisation are then found under the assumption of an exponential utility function.
Blanchet-Scalliet et al. (
2019) consider the indifference principle in pricing life insurance portfolios under the assumption of contingent lives, with dependence introduced through correlation of policyholders’ lifetimes with a Farlie–Gumbel–Morgenstern copula. Medical breakthroughs and environmental features are suggested factors associated with dependence structures between the lifetimes of individuals within a population. When restricting the model by
Blanchet-Scalliet et al. (
2019) to consider just two policyholders, the surviving policyholder is said to experience a jump in mortality intensity when the other dies, in line with the assumption of the model proposed in this paper.
We now give one example of the pricing of a life insurance product under the assumption of dependence between coupled lives involved in a contract, implementing the indifference principle in order to obtain the result. To illustrate how dependence between coupled lives influences the pricing and valuation of insurance products involving mortality assumptions, consider a reversionary annuity which insures the life of an individual . The annuity pays a value of 1 to individual at the end of each year with the initial payment due at the end of the year of ’s death, where the beneficiary is the surviving spouse of . The contract terminates on the final payment at the end of the year preceding ’s death. If the individual dies before , the contract terminates before any payment is made.
In order to compute the price of such an annuity we first introduce the classical model by
Merton (
1969), which optimises the investment strategies of an individual seeking to maximise their expected utility of terminal wealth given some value of initial wealth. The insurer may trade between a risky asset and a risk-free asset. A geometric Brownian motion is used to model the price of the risky asset such that
for some
, where
t is fixed and
gives the price of the risky asset at time
s. The mean rate of return
and volatility
are positive constants and the process
is a standard Brownian motion on a probability space
with probability measure
and filtration
containing information about the financial market. The price of the risk-free asset
with rate of return
r at some time
is modelled such that
where it is assumed
.
Suppose the insurer trades dynamically between the risky asset and the risk-free asset given initial wealth
at time
. Defining
as the wealth of the insurer for
, where
is the terminal time, the insurer invests
in the risk-free asset and
in the risky asset such that
at time
s. The wealth process then satisfies the dynamics
Under the assumption of an absence of any additional insurance risk, the investor wishes to maximise the expected utility of terminal wealth such that the value function
satisfies
where
is the set of admissible policies and
is the utility function assumed to be increasing, concave and smooth. The value function without insurance risk has been shown by
Björk (
2009) to satisfy the Hamilton–Jacobi–Bellman (HJB) equation
which has optimal investment process given by
The maximum of the HJB equation exists due to the linearity of the wealth process dynamics with respect to the wealth and portfolio process and the concavity of the utility function u, which is inherited by the value function.
Assumption of an exponential utility function reduces technical difficulties associated with general utility functions and so enables determination of the indifference price. We therefore consider an exponential utility function of the form
, where
and
is the coefficient of risk aversion, giving the closed form solution
Suppose the insurer has the opportunity to insure an individual aged
x. If the insured individual
dies in the interval
, the insurer pays the expected present value (EPV) of the reversionary annuity to the surviving spouse
at the end of the year of the primary death at time
, where
is the first death time within the couple as defined in the model proposed in
Section 3. The expected present value of the annuity is given by
where
is the death time of the surviving spouse under the assumption of dependent coupled lives. The expectation of the expected present value given
represents the remaining lifetime of
is then
since the insurance contract terminates if the beneficiary dies before the insured. Using the survival functions derived in
Section 3, we can express the expectation of the expected present value of the reversionary annuity such that
where by (
2)
and the value charged at time
t to cover this payout is
Since the insurance contract remains standing if the individual
survives until time
and continues under the value function without the claim if
dies between time
t and
, the insurer’s optimisation problem is defined by
where
is the wealth of the insurer under the optimal strategy
for
. Under assumption of the appropriate conditions of regularity and integrability on the value functions discussed by
Björk (
2009), we obtain the corresponding HJB equation given by the expression:
where the investment process is optimal in the interval
if and only if the optimisation problem has an equality. Details of the derivation of the HJB in Equation (42) are given in
Appendix C.
Supposing we again assume the exponential utility
for some
, we consider the solution of the HJB equation to be of the form
as in
Young and Zariphopoulou (
2002), where
. By substitution, we then obtain
which reduces to
as
satisfies the HJB equation for the value function under no additional insurance risk given by Equation (35). Since it is possible to show
further simplification gives a first order ordinary differential equation with respect to
, which can be solved explicitly under application of the boundary condition
such that
where
and
is the survival function of the insured individual
given by Equation (
30)a and (30)b.
The minimum premium the insurer should charge in order to insure the individual
at time
t, for a reversionary annuity which pays in arrears from the moment of death of
until the death of
, is the indifference price
which satisfies
where
by substitution. Then,
where the EPV is given by Equation (
38). Observe that the indifference price is independent of the wealth of the insurer. Specification of an exponential utility enables this desirable property due to the constant absolute risk aversion incorporated in the optimal investment process. Dependence on risk aversion, however, cannot be eliminated when applying the indifference principle approach, unlike with Black–Scholes pricing. Intuitively, this makes sense as it is impossible to completely hedge the risks priced due to the inexistence of a relationship between tradable assets and the associated uncertainties in relation to mortality.
Remark 6. Note that, in the indifference pricing setting, the maximum premium the buyer of insurance should be willing to pay is given by solution of the expressionwith respect to , the indifference price of the insurance buyer. Although unrealistic, in the event of an equality of the risk aversion of insurer and buyer, the indifference prices and will be equivalent in this case, with price increasing with increasing risk aversion. Under the assumption of independent lifetimes, the minimum premium to be charged by an insurer is again in the form of Equation (
48); however, the mortality process incorporated in the expected present value is unadapted and independent of the mortality intensity of the deceased spouse such that
where
and
are the remaining lifetimes of individuals
and
, respectively, and
is the mortality intensity of
, given the independence of coupled lives. The difference in premium the insurer should charge when incorporating dependence between coupled lives and thus covering the risk of unexpected claim rates during the first period of bereavement is therefore given by
where
and the premium
is the difference between the indifference price for dependent and independent coupled lives assuming constant risk aversion.
Numerical Simulation Results
Having obtained an expression for the indifference price of a reversionnary annuity, we now present numerical results to illustrate the significance of the dependence assumption.
Luciano and Vigna (
2008) calibrate a non-mean reverting Cox–Ingersoll–Ross or Feller process to a number of generations in the UK population. Comparison of historical Ghanaian life expectancies with those of the UK populations considered by
Luciano and Vigna (
2008) in addition to observing the parameter choices of
Jevtić and Hurd (
2017), allows for selection of the parameters of the paired mortality processes. Parameters
and
determining the nature of the bereavement effect were chosen through sensitivity analysis, utilising observations in the Ghanaian dataset to inform the selection.
Table 1 presents numerical results for the indifference price of the insurance product discussed for three levels of risk aversion.
For each level of risk aversion in
Table 1, we observe a reduced indifference price under the assumption of dependent coupled lives. Increasing the risk aversion coefficient to compare the risk neutral and risk averse insurance standpoints reveals increasing variation in the two prices. This should be expected since a risk averse insurer would consider the impact of dependence on mortality more significantly than a risk neutral insurer, hence charging at a more extreme rate.
During the simulation process, we also observed cases which priced higher under the dependence assumption. Due to the size of the sample, it is possible the difference between death interarrival times of a number of couples is larger in the dependent case, with not all bereaved spouses experiencing such a significant mortality jump in relation to the causal nature of broken-heart syndrome. Consideration of potential improvements in mortality following the loss of a spouse due to factors such as the stress associated with caring for an ill partner supports the occurrence of such findings in reality. Although limitation on the accurate estimation of parameters due to the size of the dataset may have an influence on the results obtained, observation of the need for a change in price under the assumption of dependent lives was consistent throughout all simulations.