Political Correctness between Wise Stoicism and Violent Hypocrisy
Abstract
:1. “The Trio of Chubby Girls Nearly Olympic Miracle”
- (1)
- the relationship between morality and violence, also linked to the so-called “fascist state of the mind”;
- (2)
- the concept of overmorality;
- (3)
- the stoic doctrine of indifference.
2. Political Correctness between Morality and Violence
3. Extreme Absence of Political Correctness: Intellectual Genocide
- (1)
- distortion of the opponent’s image, for example using a massive quantity of ad hominem;
- (2)
- decontextualization of the opposing view: this phenomenon is in turn linked to the scapegoat mechanism (which often relies on gossiping dynamics) that I have already illustrated in [7]. Bollas also adds that “The extreme of this act is the removal of a victim from his tribe, home (i.e., context), isolated for purposes of persecution” [18] (p. 208);
- (3)
- denigration, depicting the opponent’s position as ridiculous;
- (4)
- caricature, which helps delineate and identify the group or the ideas that have to be considered undesirable and so “killed”;
- (5)
- change of name: I just illustrated above speaking of Jews and Vietnamese people as an act of the elimination of proper names (“kikes” for Jews, “gooks” for Vietnamese people and of Berlusconi). It is pretty obvious that this elimination reverberates the subsequent potential elimination of the people/ideas from the socio-political scene and in the worst case from the very “community of living people”.7
- (6)
- categorization as aggregation, when the individual is transferred to a general category, usually with a bad connotation, in which he/she loses his/her identity and qualities: “he/she is a psychopath”, “he/she is an immigrant”, “he/she is a former alcoholic”.
(a) Incomplete or lack of relevant knowledge—so that no counter-arguments can be formulated against false, incomplete or biased assertions; (b) Fundamental norms, values and ideologies that cannot be denied or ignored; (c) Strong emotions, traumas, etc. that make people vulnerable; (d) Social positions, professions, status, etc. that induce people into tending to accept the discourses, arguments, etc. of elite persons, groups or organizations. These are typical conditions of the cognitive, emotional or social situation of the communicative event, and also part of the context models of the participants, i.e., controlling their interactions and discourses. […] [Moreover, discourse structures materialize suitable constraints which favor manipulations:] (a) Emphasize the position, power, authority or moral superiority of the speaker(s) or their sources—and, where relevant, the inferior position, lack of knowledge, etc. of the recipients; (b) Focus on the (new) beliefs that the manipulator wants the recipients to accept as knowledge, as well as on the arguments, proofs, etc. that make such beliefs more acceptable; (c) Discredit alternative (dissident, etc.) sources and beliefs; (d) Appeal to the relevant ideologies, attitudes and emotions of the recipients.[21] (pp. 375–376)
4. Overmorality: When Humans Are Too Politically Correct
- (1)
- hypocrisy; we just condemn almost innocent verbal intemperances and easily employ all our indignation (and all our moral energies) against the expression “The Trio of Chubby Girls nearly an Olympic Miracle”, forgetting that in Western society, women are killed and abused in more serious ways: when concretely faced with this problem, we have already spent all our moral energies in being politically correct, in punishing the uncorrect verbal abuser and, so, in feeling so morally proud, and also, pathetically, I have to say, in feeling ourselves exonerated from further commitment to defend the female gender. Political correctness is in this case a violent way of omitting to speak or to treat more urgent problems of violence and abuses, reaching a hypocritical pacifying state, as bluntly reported in a popular article entitled “Do we want to be politically correct or do we want to reduce partner violence in our community?” [22].9 Moreover, the pressure to appear politically correct can lead to the phenomenon of pluralistic ignorance, as reported by [11]. Pluralistic ignorance is the overestimation of a group endorsement of an attitude or a norm when, in fact, it enjoys little support among group members. Van Boven explains that the desire to appear politically correct in order to be deemed as ethically sensitive can indeed lead people to support affirmative action despite privately held doubt, increasing the erroneous perception that a particular norm is widely accepted in a group. This obviously also leads to the hypocritical acceptance and diffusion of controversial norms for politically-correct behavior;
- (2)
- abstractness and idealization: often, political correctness is related to too controversial new moral values, which do not necessarily represent an increase of dignity of the people involved. Indeed, it may cause episodes of “sweeter discrimination”, which is perceived less verbally aggressive, for the lexicon used, by the perpetrators, but it is still felt as absolutely discriminatory by the victims. In this perspective, politically-correct behaviors aim at favoring (and at the same time derive from) abstract and ideal discussions and debates about some minor “rights” to be preserved and defended, diverting attention from more serious moral issues of social, political and economic life.10
4.1. Overmorality
Husak exposes with clarity how a system characterized by overcriminalization puts at stake basic principles of the rule of law by making people unaware of what types of conduct are criminally proscribed; precluding them from having adequate notice of some of their legal obligations; and, ultimately, by undermining one of the main goals of the system of law, namely, to guide people’s behavior (p. 11). Overcriminalization also breaks principles of legality by making the criminal law outsource from non-criminal branches of the law (p. 13), which runs the serious risk of making the criminal law even less intelligible for the layperson and making its limits dependent on the limits of spheres of law that are beyond its proper domain. Despite these and other reasons to be worried about overcriminalization, Husak emphasizes—guided by “the peculiar American penal context” (p. 14)—that the principal reason to be troubled by having too much criminal law is that it produces too much punishment. That is the most urgent source of injustice on which the book focuses.
Since such things as health, wealth or reputation could not affect virtue, it made no difference to the wise man whether he had them or not, and he could not consider them good or evil. Zeno termed them all “indifferents”, but he called such things as health and wealth “according to nature” and the opposite of these “contrary to nature”. […] But even if the virtue of the wise man was not affected by the loss of property, it was necessary for him to earn his own living and to support his family. Zeno called actions of this kind “duties”, “acts of which a reasonable account can be given”. A man could be virtuous in sickness or poverty but from the practical point of view he had to pay enough attention to health to be a good soldier in the defense of his country and enough attention to money to earn his own living.[25] (pp. 152–153)
- (1)
- if we deprive “things” of their excessive moral value and reduce them to “preferable” or “not preferable” targets, which are related to merely “practical” duties, it is less likely they can trigger deep passion and unmanageable intra-personal and interpersonal conflicts, and we will certainly be less inclined to use them as a way of punishing ourselves and other human beings for not respecting our too many unquestionable moral commitments; less wrongdoing would help us, like Coeckelbergh [26] (p. 243) says, “[…] to set up institutions that prevent ‘interminable generations of prisoners’ and pay more attention to those who do good in spite of, and in response to, the tragic character of human action and human life”;
- (2)
- unfortunately, to espouse the doctrine of the indifferents is still a strong “moral option”, which can generate conflict with people who think those things you do not consider to be valuable are instead worthy of being endowed with some positive moral values and certainly not to be neglected from this point of view.
4.2. Is Silence Politically Correct?
Aside from the pressure to see and hear no evil, there is also a strong social pressure not to acknowledge the fact that we sometimes do indeed see or hear it. Not only are we expected to refrain from asking potentially embarrassing questions, we are also expected to pretend not to have heard potentially embarrassing “answers” even when we actually have. By not acknowledging what we have in fact seen or heard, we can “tactfully” pretend not to have noticed it.[27] (p. 30)
- (1)
- diffusion of responsibility (the larger the group, the less responsible and informed any individual member feels);
- (2)
- division of labor (which helps conceal responsibility and even the possibility of tracking and individuating the single responsibility as regards harm perpetrated);
- (3)
- exploitation of trust and loyalty (when, for example, people at the bottom trust the decision-makers at the top to do the right thing and unaware, become evildoers);
- (4)
- suppression of private doubts and inhibitions thanks to the immersion in groups (whatever their peaceful private feelings, people tend to express only the “correct” view imposed by a group they belong to, for example of strong hatred against an enemy).12
5. Conclusions
Acknowledgments
Conflicts of Interest
References
- Friedman, M.; Narveson, J. Political Correctness: For and Against; Rowman & Littlefield: Lanham, MD, USA, 1995. [Google Scholar]
- Schwartz, S. The Revolt of the Primitive: An Inquiry into the Roots of Political Correctness; Transaction Publishers: New Brunswick, NJ, USA, 2003. [Google Scholar]
- Geoffrey, H. Political Correctness: A History of Semantics and Culture; John Wiley & Sons: Malden, MA, USA, 2010. [Google Scholar]
- Herbert, K. The Politically Correct bypass: Multiculturalism and the Public Schools. Soc. Policy 1991, 22, 33–40. [Google Scholar]
- Anderson, C.B. Political correctness on college campuses: Freedom of speech v. doing the politically correct thing. SMUL Rev. 1993, 46, 171. [Google Scholar]
- Poole, D.L. Politically correct or culturally competent? Health Soc. Work 1998, 23, 163–166. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed]
- Magnani, L. Understanding Violence. The Intertwining of Morality, Religion, and Violence: A Philosophical Stance; Springer: Heidelberg/Berlin, Germany, 2011. [Google Scholar]
- Kelly, R.J.; Rubal-Lopez, A. Political correctness and multiculturalism: Who support PC? J. Soc. Distress Homeless 1996, 5, 111–137. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Žižek, S. The Ticklish Subject; Verso: New York, NY, USA, 1999. [Google Scholar]
- Chabot, D.R. Political correctness: Contributing to social distress? J. Soc. Distress Homeless 1996, 5, 143–147. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Van Boven, L. Pluralistic ignorance and political correctness: The case of Affirmative action. Int. Soc. Political Psychol. 2000, 21, 267–276. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Magnani, L.; Bertolotti, T. Cognitive bubbles and firewalls: Epistemic immunizations in human reasoning. In CogSci 2011, XXXIII Annual Conference of the Cognitive Science Society; Carlson, L., Hölscher, C., Shipley, T., Eds.; Cognitive Science Society: Boston, MA, USA, 2011. [Google Scholar]
- Arfini, S.; Magnani, L. An eco-cognitive model of ignorance immunization. In Philosophy and Cognitive Science II. Western & Eastern Studies; Magnani, L., Li, P., Park, W., Eds.; Springer: Heidelberg, Germany, 2015; Volume 20, pp. 59–75. [Google Scholar]
- Peterson, P.E. Classifying by Race; Princeton University Press: Princeton, NJ, USA, 2014. [Google Scholar]
- Bollas, C. Cracking Up: The Work of Unconscious Experience; Routledge: London, UK, 1995. [Google Scholar]
- Salmi, J. The different categories of violence. In Violence: A Philosophical Anthology; Bufacchi, V., Ed.; Palgrave Macmillan: Houndmills/Basingstoke, UK; New York, NY, USA, 2009; pp. 311–319. [Google Scholar]
- Bufacchi, V. (Ed.) Violence: A Philosophical Anthology; Palgrave Macmillan: Houndmills/Basingstoke, UK; New York, NY, USA, 2009.
- Bollas, C. Being a Character: Psychoanalysis and Self Experience; Routledge: London, UK, 1993; [1992]. [Google Scholar]
- Mandoki, K. Terror and aethestics: Nazi strategies for mass organization. Renaiss. Mod. Stud. 1999, 42, 4–81. [Google Scholar]
- McKinlay, A.; McVittie, C. Social Psychology and Discourse; John Wiley & Sons: Chichester, UK, 2008. [Google Scholar]
- Van Dijk, T.A. Discourse and manipulation. Discourse Soc. 2006, 17, 259–383. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Hamel, J. Do we want to be politically correct, or do we want to reduce partner violence in our communities? Partner Abuse 2010, 1, 82–91. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Husak, D. Overcriminalization. The Limits of the Criminal Law; Oxford University Press: Oxford, UK, 2008. [Google Scholar]
- Donoso, A.M. Review of Douglas Husak, Overcriminalization. The Limits of the Criminal Law. Crim. Law Philos. 2010, 4, 99–104. [Google Scholar]
- Reesor, M.E. The “indifferents” in the old and middle Stoa. Trans. Proc. Am. Philol. Assoc. 1951, 82, 102–110. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Coeckelbergh, M. Criminal or patients? Towards a tragic conception of moral and legal responsibility. Crim. Law Philos. 2010, 4, 233–244. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Zerubavel, E. The Elephant in the Room. Silence and Denial in Everyday Life; Oxford University Press: Oxford, UK, 2006. [Google Scholar]
- Proctor, R.N.; Schiebinger, L. (Eds.) Agnotology. The Making and Unmaking of Ignorance; Stanford University Press: Stanford, CA, USA, 2008.
- Tuana, N. The speculum of ignorance: The women’s health movement and epistemologies of ignorance. Hypatia 2013, 21, 1–19. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Sullivan, S.; Tuana, N. Race and Epistemologies of Ignorance; SUNY Press: New York, NY, USA, 2007. [Google Scholar]
- Foucault, M. Discipline and Punish: The Birth of the Prison; Sheridan, A., Translator; Vintage Books: New York, NY, USA, 1979; [1975]. [Google Scholar]
- Foucault, M. (Ed.) Ethics: Subjectivity and Truth (Essential Works of Foucault, 1954–1984); New Press: New York, NY, USA, 2006.
- Baumeister, R. Evil. Inside Human Violence and Cruelty; Freeman/Holt Paperbacks: New York, NY, USA, 1997. [Google Scholar]
- Karlsson, N.; Loewenstein, G.; Seppi, D. The ostrich effect: Selective attention to information. J. Risk Uncertain. 2009, 38, 95–115. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Brown, A.L.; Kagel, J.K. Behavior in a simplified stock market: The status quo bias, the disposition effect and the ostrich effect. Ann. Financ. 2009, 5, 1–14. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Bar On, B.A. The Subject of Violence: Arendtean Exercises in Understanding; Rowman and Littlefield: Lanham, MD, USA, 2002. [Google Scholar]
- 1.In the media, the term can be used as a pejorative, implying that these policies are always excessive. It is well known that in October 1990, the New York Times article by Richard Bernstein promoted a strong popularization of the term.
- 2.Being constitutively and easily unaware of our errors is very often intertwined with the self-conviction that we are not at all violent and aggressive, but just moral, in the argumentation we perform (and in our eventual related actions). A moral bubble, in which an agent is “trapped”, refers to the fact that we only see the moral side of our actions and not the possible violent effects. I have introduced and explained this concept in [7], Chapter Three.
- 3.For example, political correctness could lead to a patronization of people’s behavior from a philosophical point of view, which reflects the same effect of the blind enforcement of political correctness norms that, as already pointed out by Žižek, are “all the more humiliating inasmuch as they are masked as benevolence” [9]. Indeed, several studies pointed out how blind politically-correct measures provided much distress in some closed communities (such as universities, high schools, workplaces) than the previous enactment of less strict norms of behavior. Just to mention two cases, [10] testified how, in his clinical work as a family systems therapist, he had repeatedly encountered experiences of social distress in clients who attempted to deal with strong political correctness measures, and a study conducted by [11] reported how the pressure to appear politically correct in educational settings can create discrepancies between public behavior and private attitudes, generating phenomena of hypocritical acceptance of norms rather than multicultural comprehension.
- 4.On this interplay of violent/non-violent, cf. also [7], Chapter Four, Section “Nonviolent Moral Axiologies, Pacifism, and Violence”.
- 5.For a treatment of this subject in the perspective of the relationship between morality and violence, see my [7], Chapter 5.
- 6.Salmi [16] usefully lists the various effects of genocide under the category of alienating violence, when a person is deprived of her/his rights to emotional, cultural and intellectual growth, by means of racism, social ostracism and ethnocide. This has to be distinguished from repressive violence, which resorts to a mere deprivation of basic rights other than the right to survival and protection from injury, including civil, political and social rights [17] (p. 320).
- 7.Other processes of methodical “substitution” (especially active in the case of Nationalsozialistische Deutsche Arbeitepartei) were related to: (1) the substitution of religion by the instrumentalization of art; (2) the substitution of art by propaganda; (3) the substitution of propaganda by indoctrination; (4) the substitution of culture by monumentalism; (5) the substitution of politics by esthetics; (6) the substitution of esthetics by terror (masses, already transformed into a homogenous conglomeration where the elbow room that would enable any political or cultural relation is missing, are further weakened through the erasure of the very faces, metaphorically, aiming toward a total anonymization, and any sense of individual responsibility) [19].
- 8.[20], Chapter 8: “Dispute and aggression” also studies the role of insults as a precursor to physical aggression in their intertwining with arguments that can be used to establish sociability.
- 9.A paradoxical event that concerned political correctness has been the cancellation of the television program Politically Incorrect, a political talk show hosted by Bill Maher that aired from 1993 to 2002. Six days after the 11 September 2001 attacks, Dinesh D’Souza appeared on the program. He commented on the event by criticizing people who suggested terrorists were cowards by saying, “Look at what they did. You have a whole bunch of guys who were willing to give their life; none of them backed out. All of them slammed themselves into pieces of concrete. These are warriors”. Maher agreed with D’Souza’s comments and said, “We have been the cowards. Lobbing cruise missiles from two thousand miles away”. Maher’s comments ultimately led to advertisers ending their support and his show being canceled. This is a funny paradoxical story in which we can see both the moral and violent character of political correctness at work: there were subsequently comments in various media on the irony that a show called Politically Incorrect was canceled because its host had made a supposedly politically-incorrect comment (cf. Wikipedia, entries Politically Incorrect and Dinesh D’Souza.)
- 10.We have to say that, for example mass media, which are strong sustainers and promoters of political correctness, are instead, on multiple occasions, far from being politically correct, so promoting, for example, hate speech, unaware of the politically-incorrect use of language, images or cartoons that irritate or provoke religious groups and devotion to horrible politicians who, so to say, “cannot be criticized”.
- 11.The same consideration has been exposed by several authors of the so-called epistemology of ignorance [28,29,30]. Indeed, on several occasions, it is highlighted how feminist and anti-racist issues should be directly addressed without reserve and modesty in order to overcome the walls of silence that various cultural environments try to perpetuate with euphemistic labels, indirect comments or implicit references.
- 12.These cases are typical of what is called structural violence, which I have described in [7], Chapter 1, and reiterated with some aspects of the kinds of disengagement of morality described in the Chapter 5 of the same book.
- 14.Aspects of violence pertaining to the Holocaust in the perspective of Hannah Arendt and feminism are dealt with in [36].
- 15.More details concerning the general ethical and violent role of silence and the ostrich effect are illustrated in [7], Chapter 3.
© 2016 by the author; licensee MDPI, Basel, Switzerland. This article is an open access article distributed under the terms and conditions of the Creative Commons Attribution (CC-BY) license (http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/).
Share and Cite
Magnani, L. Political Correctness between Wise Stoicism and Violent Hypocrisy. Philosophies 2016, 1, 261-274. https://doi.org/10.3390/philosophies1030261
Magnani L. Political Correctness between Wise Stoicism and Violent Hypocrisy. Philosophies. 2016; 1(3):261-274. https://doi.org/10.3390/philosophies1030261
Chicago/Turabian StyleMagnani, Lorenzo. 2016. "Political Correctness between Wise Stoicism and Violent Hypocrisy" Philosophies 1, no. 3: 261-274. https://doi.org/10.3390/philosophies1030261
APA StyleMagnani, L. (2016). Political Correctness between Wise Stoicism and Violent Hypocrisy. Philosophies, 1(3), 261-274. https://doi.org/10.3390/philosophies1030261