1. Introduction
In an interview for “New Scientist” in February 2011, biological novelist Christian de Duve stated that the cost of human success on earth is the exhaustion of natural resources, leading to energy crises, climate change, pollution and the destruction of our habitat. If we continue in the same direction, humankind is heading for some frightful ordeals, if not extinction. He believes an inherent selfishness in human nature is responsible for this behaviour passed on through human genes. [
1]
This somewhat fatalistic statement raises an old philosophical question: are human beings able to act according to free will or are they pre-determined—pre-programmed—by the physical state of their brain, which is based on their genetic traits.
First of all, the set-up, results, and two main conclusions of the famous Libet-experiment [
2] have to be described in order to be able to shed light on the context of the thought-experiment:
The set-up of the experiment involves EEGs being attached to subjects’ brains, monitoring when their brains indicate a decision is made and comparing this to when subjects indicate being aware of having made a decision. The results show that the pre-conscious brain indicates a reliably predictive “readiness potential” signal approximately 0.33 s prior to test subjects reporting an awareness of having made a decision on their own. The two main interpretations are:
First, as the readiness potential reliably predicts the subsequent decision, Libet concluded that the brain has decided prior to having become aware of consciously making a decision. This implies that the conscious awareness of having made a decision is an epiphenomenon, which undermines the free will notion that volition is informed by conscious election.
Second, Libet was nonetheless of the opinion that this study does not rule out the possibility that individuals retain a “veto” option, that is to say they can override what the brain delivers, if they so choose, and veto the brain’s decision just prior to the moment of enacting it.
More recent work has established, first, that when test subjects were asked to press either a left-hand or right-hand lever, analyses of their brain states reliably predicted which hand would be chosen up to six seconds prior. Secondly, the readiness potential itself has been debunked as a sort of mathematical noise of the equations used to measure brain activity.
This paper links its interpretation of the thought experiment with Libet’s assertion that the conscious agent retains a veto power. We shall assume test subjects would wish to falsify such a prediction every now and then, supporting the existence of free human will.
2. A Thought-Experiment in Favour of Free Human Will
In preliminary matters, we need one axiom:
A system is considered to be determinate, as long as its state and therefore resulting future can in principle be known in advance. For the following thoughts, it is sufficient if the state and the further dynamic development of the system can be known at least two seconds or more into the future.
We start with the system in
Figure 1. The system consists of the following elements:
a human being, indicated in the figure by its brain and its eye;
a detecting probe with related software and representation on a screen, which allows for the full detection and representation of the complete physical/chemical/biological state of the brain;
an observer, usually a human being. The observer can also be placed outside the frame of
Figure 1, meaning that it is not decisive that they are part of the system
Figure 1, which is considered to be deterministic, or not;
a simple decision-process for the human being, indicated by the two cups A and B;
and the environment of the experiment, which can also be part of the deterministic system.
The whole system in
Figure 1 is considered to be pre-determined, a classical physical system without in-deterministic influences. The brain of the human being produces electrochemical results which “somehow” are related to subjective perception. Instantaneously, the whole objective system of the “brain” with all its signals is detected by a probe, interpreted by a computer and is displayed to an observer. The “somehow”-production of subjective impressions as well as the details of the detecting probe and the representation of the state of the brain, are not the focus of this paper.
The observer can, as a consequence of detection, interpretation and representation, know in advance what the electrochemical system “brain” intends to do, when its subjective correlate, the human consciousness, is confronted with a simple decision. The human has to decide between two options with almost the same level of priority, meaning that both are more or less equal for them. In our example, the human has to decide whether to drink from cup A which contains pure water, or from cup B which contains red wine. This is also the principal idea of Libet’s experiment.
The system “brain” is a determined physical/chemical/biological system, as are the rest of all elements in
Figure 1. In
Figure 1, the brain would make the decision prior to the human’s subjective perception where it actively decides between possibilities A and B. Therefore, the observer would know: “you decide to choose option A” and the human would follow. Everything remains in the predetermined world.
We turn the screen representing the inner “physical” state of the human brain around so that the eye of the human being, the brain—which is being detected and observed—is able to watch it (
Figure 2). Again, the whole system, as a hypothesis, is considered to be determined.
In this case the human being—again sketched as a brain and eye in
Figure 2—would learn about two seconds in advance which decision it is about to choose (A in our example). This again happens prior to the human’s subjective perception that it has actively decided between possibilities A and B. Is the human being now obliged to choose alternative A, as the representation of the inner physical state of his/her brain tells them via the screen that it is about to choose alternative A? Definitely not.
In
Figure 2 there is unquestionably something placed in the system which is able to refute any forecast of the deterministic system. Whenever the chain along brain-detection-representation and observation (b-d-r-o) mirrors a certain result, something in between is able to prove that this very result can also be different.
This “something in between” is the free, resistive will (libero arbitrio). The hypothesis represented in
Figure 2, that the whole system is a pre-determined system, is disproved.
It is important to keep the following in mind:
Even if there were to be a logical element between the representation of the inner state of the brain and the brain itself (meaning somewhere “within” the human being), which were able to produce the output non-A from input A (or carry out any other logical operation), this logical element itself would again be part of the pre-determined system within the frame of
Figure 2. Therefore, its state and its future development would both be known in advance. The same would occur if the brain itself were to merely produce this logical element. In a classical system, there is no principal hurdle against forecasting the whole state and the whole future development of the system in
Figure 1 and
Figure 2, deciding whether a human would select alternative A or B.
Both systems within the frames of
Figure 1 and
Figure 2 are classical systems in the way that quantum mechanical effects and related uncertainties do not play a role in them.
3. Conclusions
The critical element in
Figure 2, which holds the key, is the brain with its resistive will. This brain is both an object and at the same time a related subject. Simultaneously, the subject observes itself as an object. Determinists state that the object “somehow” produces the subject as a correlated epiphenomenal side-effect. The constellation of
Figure 2 shows, however, that the subject can disprove the state of its relating object by refuting its predicted future. It is able to disprove decisions that the object seems to have taken.
If anything that is predicted about the system can be refuted, the system turns into a non-predictable one.
In 1970, the philosopher Alvin I. Goldman [
3] proposed a thought-experiment of a perfectly informed, accurate deterministic predictive system, predicting that a subject will perform a certain action (say, raise her hand) at time
t. If the subject were aware of that prediction, they can simply refuse to raise their hand at
t. The thought experiment presented here is designed to support the same idea, by having the deterministic predictive system directly monitor brain and environment of a subject and feed the prediction back to them. It places the bases for the deterministic prediction inside the test subject’s own brain and provides the test subject with what counts as neurological biofeedback, together with deterministic knowledge about their own brain, thereby bringing the thought experiment much closer to home for our intuitions about ourselves and our brains in a way that relates more directly to Libet’s veto power claim.
4. Further Questions and Remarks
The hypothesis assumes, for the sake of its reductio ad absurdum approach, that the system is reliably deterministically predictive. If so, then the system would be able to know whether the test subject wishes to rebut its deterministic predictions and will integrate that information into its predictive processing algorithms. Again, it would mirror these predictions of the inner state of their brain to the human actor, and the human actor would again be able to react with obeying or refuting this prediction. Eventually the potential reaction-time between prediction, presentation and the reaction would become too short for a resistive reaction on the part of the human actor. Therefore, we must define a threshold period for the game of prediction and reaction of, say, half a second or two seconds.
Furthermore, the hypothesis assumes that a free human actor is characterized by the desire to now and then falsify reliable deterministic predictions about their forthcoming behaviour. There is no empirical evidence for that, and it would be hard to find one that avoids the trap of tautology. Rather, this resistive desire is taken as a definition for a free will.
It should be noted that this thought-experiment is akin to the famous Newcombe’s paradox with a perfect predictor. If we were to redesign Newcombe’s paradox in the way that a perfect predictor would, in addition to our knowledge of the content of the box containing a million dollars or nothing, predict the complete physical/chemical/biological state of the brain of the human player and mirror it back to this very player (as indicated in
Figure 2), it would be possible for this player to win the million dollars.