Examining the Continuity between Life and Mind: Is There a Continuity between Autopoietic Intentionality and Representationality?
Abstract
:1. Introduction
2. The Free Energy Principle in a Nutshell
3. Autopoietic Interpretations of the Free Energy Principle
3.1. Autopoiesis and Sense-Making under the Free Energy Principle
An autopoietic system is organized (defined as unity) as a network of processes of production (synthesis and destruction) of components such that these components:
- (i)
- continuously regenerate and realize the network that produces them, and
- (ii)
- constitute the system as a distinguishable unity in the domain in which they exist [80].
3.2. The Continuity between Life and Mind under Autopoietic Enactivist Interpretations of the Free Energy Principle
4. Representational Instrumentalism and the Continuity between Life and Mind
5. Representational Realism and the Continuity between Life and Mind
5.1. From Minimising Free Energy to Computational Realism
Notice finally that this account is distinct from any instrumentalist or teleosemantic notion, which would be the idea that systems minimize surprise in order to achieve the (known) goal of continued existence (or surviving, or achieving intermediate goals and rewards); [...]. The FEP account is fundamentally different from such other attempts [...] because the first step in its explanation is to analyse existence in terms of surprise minimization, rather than naturalistically explain one by appeal to the other.[37]
5.2. From Computational Realism to Representational Realism
5.3. Revisiting the Interface Problem
6. Conclusions
Author Contributions
Funding
Institutional Review Board Statement
Informed Consent Statement
Data Availability Statement
Acknowledgments
Conflicts of Interest
References
- Wiener, N. Cybernetics: Or Control and Communication in the Animal and the Machine; MIT Press: Cambridge, MA, USA, 1948. [Google Scholar]
- Walter, W.G. The Living Brain; Norton: New York, NY, USA, 1953. [Google Scholar]
- Ashby, W.R. Design for a Brain; Chapman and Hall: London, UK, 1952. [Google Scholar]
- Maturana, H.R.; Varela, F.J. Autopoiesis and Cognition: The Realization of the Living; D. Reidel: Dordrecht, The Netherlands, 1980. [Google Scholar]
- Maturana, H.R.; Varela, F.J. The Tree of Knowledge: The Biological Roots of Human Understanding; Shambhala Publications: Boston, MA, USA, 1987. [Google Scholar]
- Godfrey-Smith, P. Spencer and Dewey on Life and Mind. In The Philosophy of Artificial Life; Boden, M., Ed.; Oxford University Press: Oxford, UK, 1996; pp. 314–331. [Google Scholar]
- Clark, A. Mindware: An Introduction to the Philosophy of Cognitive Science; Oxford University Press: Oxford, UK, 2001. [Google Scholar]
- Ward, D.; Silverman, D.; Villalobos, M. Introduction: The Varieties of Enactivism. Topoi 2017, 36, 365–375. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
- Dewhurst, J. The cybernetic origins of enactivism and computationalism. In The Past, Present, and Future of Integrated History and Philosophy of Science; Routledge: Abingdon, UK, 2019; pp. 167–185. [Google Scholar]
- Seth, A.K. The cybernetic Bayesian brain: From interoceptive inference to sensorimotor contingencies. In Open MIND; Metzinger, T., Windt, J.M., Eds.; MIND Group: Frankfurt am Main, Germany, 2015; Chapter 35(T). [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Allen, M.; Friston, K.J. From cognitivism to autopoiesis: Towards a computational framework for the embodied mind. Synthese 2018, 195, 2459–2482. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
- Kirchhoff, M.; Parr, T.; Palacios, E.; Friston, K.; Kiverstein, J. The Markov blankets of life: Autonomy, active inference and the free energy principle. J. R. Soc. Interface 2018, 15. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed]
- Korbak, T. Computational enactivism under the free energy principle. Synthese 2019, 1–21. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
- Ramstead, M.J.; Kirchhoff, M.D.; Friston, K.J. A tale of two densities: Active inference is enactive inference. Adapt. Behav. 2020, 28, 225–239. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
- Friston, K.; FitzGerald, T.; Rigoli, F.; Schwartenbeck, P.; Pezzulo, G. Active Inference: A Process Theory. Neural Comput. 2017, 29, 1–49. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
- Clark, A. Surfing Uncertainty: Prediction, Action, and the Embodied Mind; Oxford University Press: New York, NY, USA, 2016. [Google Scholar]
- Hohwy, J. The Predictive Mind; Oxford University Press: Oxford, UK, 2013. [Google Scholar]
- Wiese, W.; Metzinger, T. Vanilla PP for Philosophers: A Primer on Predictive Processing. In Philosophy and Predictive Processing; Metzinger, T., Wiese, W., Eds.; MIND Group: Frankfurt am Main, Germany, 2017; Chapter 1. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Costa, L.D.; Parr, T.; Sajid, N.; Veselic, S.; Neacsu, V.; Friston, K. Active Inference on Discrete State-Spaces: A Synthesis. J. Math. Psychol. 2020, 99, 102447. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Hohwy, J. New directions in predictive processing. Mind Lang. 2020, 35, 209–223. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Kirchhoff, M.D.; Froese, T. Where There is Life There is Mind: In Support of a Strong Life-Mind Continuity Thesis. Entropy 2017, 19, 169. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
- Brentano, F. Psychology from an Empirical Standpoint; Routledge: London, UK; New York, NY, USA, 2015. [Google Scholar]
- Yablo, S. Aboutness; Princeton University Press: Princeton, NJ, USA; Oxford, UK, 2014. [Google Scholar]
- Jacob, P. Intentionality. In The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, Winter 2019 ed.; Zalta, E.N., Ed.; Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University: Stanford, CA, USA, 2019. [Google Scholar]
- Thompson, E. Mind in Life: Biology, Phenomenology, and the Sciences of Mind; Harvard University Press: Cambridge, MA, USA, 2007. [Google Scholar]
- Hutto, D.D. Folk Psychological Narratives: The Sociocultural Basis of Understanding Reasons; MIT Press: Cambridge, MA, USA, 2008. [Google Scholar]
- Hutto, D.D.; Satne, G. The Natural Origins of Content. Philosophia 2015, 43, 521–536. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Schlicht, T. Does Separating Intentionality From Mental Representation Imply Radical Enactivism? Front. Psychol. 2018, 9, 1497. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Schlicht, T.; Starzak, T. Prospects of enactivist approaches to intentionality and cognition. Synthese 2019, 1–25. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Thompson, E. Review of Daniel D. Hutto and Erik Myin, evolving enactivism: Basic minds meet content. Notre Dame Philos. Rev. 2018, 11. [Google Scholar]
- Wheeler, M. Cognition’s coming home: The reunion of life and mind. In Open MIND; Metzinger, T., Windt, J.M., Eds.; MIND Group: Frankfurt am Main, Germany, 2015; Chapter 35(T). [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Fitch, W.T. Nano-intentionality: A defense of intrinsic intentionality. Biol. Philos. 2008, 23, 157–177. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Froese, T.; Paolo, E.A.D. Sociality and the life–mind continuity thesis. Phenomenol. Cogn. Sci. 2009, 8, 439–463. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
- Myin, E.; van den Herik, J.C. A twofold tale of one mind: Revisiting REC’s multi-storey story. Synthese 2020, 1–19. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Friston, K. The free-energy principle: A unified brain theory? Nat. Rev. Neurosci. 2010, 11, 127–138. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Ramstead, M.J.D.; Badcock, P.B.; Friston, K.J. Answering Schrodinger’s question: A free-energy formulation. Phys. Life Rev. 2018, 24, 1–16. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Hohwy, J. Self-supervision, normativity and the free energy principle. Synthese 2020, 1–25. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Friston, K. A free energy principle for a particular physics. arXiv 2019, arXiv:1906.10184. [Google Scholar]
- Kirchhoff, M.D. Autopoiesis, free energy, and the life–mind continuity thesis. Synthese 2018, 195, 2519–2540. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Wiese, W.; Friston, K. The Neural Correlates of Consciousness under the Free Energy Principle: From Computational Correlates to Computational Explanation. 2020. Available online: https://psyarxiv.com/7gefk/ (accessed on 10 February 2021).
- Friston, K.J.; Wiese, W.; Hobson, J.A. Sentience and the Origins of Consciousness: From Cartesian Duality to Markovian Monism. Entropy 2020, 22, 516. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Andrews, M. The Math is not the Territory: Navigating the Free Energy Principle. 2020. Available online: http://philsci-archive.pitt.edu/18315/ (accessed on 10 February 2021).
- Ramstead, M.J.D.; Friston, K.J.; Hipólito, I. Is the Free-Energy Principle a Formal Theory of Semantics? From Variational Density Dynamics to Neural and Phenotypic Representations. Entropy 2020, 22, 889. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed]
- Ramstead, M.J.; Hesp, C.; Tschantz, A.; Smith, R.; Constant, A.; Friston, K. Neural and phenotypic representation under the free-energy principle. Neurosci. Biobehav. Rev. 2021, 120, 109–122. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed]
- Ao, P. Emerging of Stochastic Dynamical Equalities and Steady State Thermodynamics. Commun. Theor. Phys. 2008, 49, 1073–1090. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
- Seifert, U. Stochastic thermodynamics, fluctuation theorems and molecular machines. Rep. Prog. Phys. 2012, 75, 126001. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
- Sekimoto, K. Langevin Equation and Thermodynamics. Prog. Theor. Phys. Suppl. 1998, 130, 17–27. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
- Pearl, J. Probabilistic Reasoning in Intelligent Systems: Networks of Plausible Inference; Morgan Kaufmann Publishers: San Francisco, CA, USA, 1988. [Google Scholar]
- Clark, A. How to Knit Your Own Markov Blanket. In Philosophy and Predictive Processing; Metzinger, T.K., Wiese, W., Eds.; MIND Group: Frankfurt am Main, Germany, 2017; Chapter 3. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Palacios, E.R.; Razi, A.; Parr, T.; Kirchhoff, M.; Friston, K. Biological Self-organisation and Markov blankets. bioRxiv 2017. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
- Parr, T.; Da Costa, L.; Friston, K. Markov blankets, information geometry and stochastic thermodynamics. Philos. Trans. A Math. Phys. Eng. Sci. 2020, 378, 20190159. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed] [Green Version]
- Pellet, J.P.; Elisseeff, A. Using Markov blankets for causal structure learning. J. Mach. Learn. Res. 2008, 9, 1295–1342. [Google Scholar]
- Friston, K. Life as we know it. J. R. Soc. Interface 2013, 10. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
- Rosas, F.E.; Mediano, P.A.M.; Biehl, M.; Chandaria, S.; Polani, D. Causal Blankets: Theory and Algorithmic Framework. In Active Inference. IWAI 2020. Communications in Computer and Information Science; Verbelen, T., Lanillos, P., Buckley, C.L., De Boom, C., Eds.; Springer: Cham, Switzerland, 2020; Volume 1326. [Google Scholar]
- Friston, K.; Costa, L.D.; Parr, T. Some Interesting Observations on the Free Energy Principle. 2020. Available online: https://arxiv.org/abs/2002.04501 (accessed on 10 February 2021).
- Friston, K.J.; Fagerholm, E.D.; Zarghami, T.S.; Parr, T.; Hipólito, I.; Magrou, L.; Razi, A. Parcels and Particles: Markov Blankets in the Brain. Netw. Neurosci. 2020. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Bruineberg, J.; Dolega, K.; Dewhurst, J.; Baltieri, M. The Emperor’s New Markov Blankets. 2020. Available online: http://philsci-archive.pitt.edu/18467/ (accessed on 10 February 2021).
- Ramstead, M.J.D.; Kirchhoff, M.D.; Constant, A.; Friston, K.J. Multiscale Integration: Beyond Internalism and Externalism. Synthese 2019, 1–30. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
- Van Es, T. Living models or life modelled? On the use of models in the free energy principle. Adapt. Behav. 2020, 1–15. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Sprevak, M. Two kinds of information processing in cognition. Rev. Philos. Psychol. 2020, 11, 591–611. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
- Kiefer, A.B. Psychophysical identity and free energy. J. R. Soc. Interface 2020, 17, 20200370. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed]
- Beni, M.D. A critical analysis of Markovian monism. Synthese 2021, 1–21. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Kiefer, A.; Hohwy, J. Content and misrepresentation in hierarchical generative models. Synthese 2018, 195, 2387–2415. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Hohwy, J. The Self-Evidencing Brain. Noûs 2016, 50, 259–285. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Gładziejewski, P. Predictive coding and representationalism. Synthese 2016, 559–582. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
- Dołega, K. Moderate Predictive Processing. In Philosophy and Predictive Processing; Metzinger, T., Wiese, W., Eds.; MIND Group: Frankfurt am Main, Germany, 2017. [Google Scholar]
- Williams, D. Predictive Processing and the Representation Wars. Minds Mach. 2018, 28, 141–172. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed]
- Bruineberg, J.; Kiverstein, J.; Rietveld, E. The anticipating brain is not a scientist: The free-energy principle from an ecological-enactive perspective. Synthese 2018, 195, 2417–2444. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed] [Green Version]
- Kirchhoff, M.D.; Robertson, I. Enactivism and predictive processing: A non-representational view. Philos. Explor. 2018, 21, 264–281. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Downey, A. Predictive processing and the representation wars: A victory for the eliminativist (via fictionalism). Synthese 2018, 195, 5115–5139. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed] [Green Version]
- Hutto, D.D. Getting into predictive processing’s great guessing game: Bootstrap heaven or hell? Synthese 2018, 195, 2445–2458. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Van Es, T. Minimizing prediction errors in predictive processing: From inconsistency to non-representationalism. Phenomenol. Cogn. Sci. 2019, 1–21. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Korbak, T. Scaffolded Minds And The Evolution of Content In Signaling Pathways. Stud. Logic Gramm. Rhetor. 2015, 41, 89–103. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
- Hutto, D.D.; Myin, E. Radicalizing Enactivism: Basic Minds without Content; MIT Press: Cambridge, MA, USA, 2012. [Google Scholar]
- Egan, F. How to think about mental content. Philos. Stud. 2014, 170, 115–135. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Milkowski, M. Explaining the Computational Mind; MIT Press: Cambridge, MA, USA, 2013. [Google Scholar]
- Piccinini, G. Physical Computation: A Mechanistic Account; Oxford University Press: Oxford, UK, 2015. [Google Scholar]
- Piccinini, G. Neurocognitive Mechanisms; Oxford University Press: Oxford, UK, 2020. [Google Scholar]
- Coelho Mollo, D. Functional individuation, mechanistic implementation: The proper way of seeing the mechanistic view of concrete computation. Synthese 2018, 195, 3477–3497. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
- Varela, F.J. Patterns of life: Intertwining identity and cognition. Brain Cogn. 1997, 34, 72–87. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
- Di Paolo, E.A. Autopoiesis, adaptivity, teleology, agency. Phenomenol. Cogn. Sci. 2005, 4, 429–452. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Di Paolo, E. Extended life. Topoi 2009, 28, 9–21. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Weber, A.; Varela, F.J. Life after Kant: Natural purposes and the autopoietic foundations of biological individuality. Phenomenol. Cogn. Sci. 2002, 1, 97–125. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Dębowski, J. Information Theory Meets Power Laws: Stochastic Processes and Language Models; John Wiley & Sons: Hoboken, NJ, USA, 2020. [Google Scholar]
- Friston, K.; Adams, R.; Montague, R. What is value—Accumulated reward or evidence? Front. Neurorobotics 2012, 6, 11. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed] [Green Version]
- Butterfill, S.A.; Sinigaglia, C. Intention and Motor Representation in Purposive Action. Philos. Phenomenol. Res. 2014, 88, 119–145. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Weichold, M. Evolving enactivism: Basic minds meet content. Philos. Psychol. 2018, 31, 1265–1268. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- de Bruin, L.C.; Kästner, L. Dynamic Embodied Cognition. Phenomenol. Cogn. Sci. 2012, 11, 541–563. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- McGregor, S. The Bayesian stance: Equations for ‘as-if’ sensorimotor agency. Adapt. Behav. 2017, 25, 72–82. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Egan, F. In Defence of Narrow Mindedness. Mind Lang. 1999, 14, 177–194. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Egan, F. Is there a role for representational content in scientific psychology. In Stich: And His Critics; Murphy, D., Bishop, M.A., Eds.; Wiley Online Library: Hoboken, NJ, USA, 2009; pp. 14–29. [Google Scholar]
- Egan, F. Computational models: A modest role for content. Stud. Hist. Philos. Sci. Part A 2010, 41, 253–259. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Wiese, W. What are the contents of representations in predictive processing? Phenomenol. Cogn. Sci. 2017, 16, 715–736. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Friston, K.; Costa, L.D.; Hafner, D.; Hesp, C.; Parr, T. Sophisticated Inference. 2020. Available online: https://arxiv.org/abs/2006.04120 (accessed on 10 February 2021).
- Ritchie, J.B.; Piccinini, G. Computational Implementation. In The Routledge Handbook of the Computational Mind; Sprevak, M., Colombo, M., Eds.; Routledge: Abingdon, Oxon, UK, 2018; pp. 192–204. [Google Scholar]
- Fresco, N. Objective computation versus subjective computation. Erkenntnis 2015, 80, 1031–1053. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
- Dewhurst, J. Computing mechanisms without proper functions. Minds Mach. 2018, 28, 569–588. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
- Coelho Mollo, D. Are there teleological functions to compute? Philos. Sci. 2019, 86, 431–452. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Maley, C.J.; Piccinini, G. A Unified Mechanistic Account of Teleological Functions for Psychology and Neuroscience. In Explanation and Integration in Mind and Brain Science; Kaplan, D.M., Ed.; Oxford University Press: Oxford, UK, 2017; pp. 236–257. [Google Scholar]
- Baltieri, M.; Buckley, C.L.; Bruineberg, J. Predictions in the eye of the beholder: An active inference account of Watt governors. Artif. Life Conf. Proc. 2020, 121–129. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Friston, K.; Daunizeau, J.; Kilner, J.; Kiebel, S.J. Action and behavior: A free-energy formulation. Biol. Cybern. 2010, 102, 227–260. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
- Hesp, C.; Smith, R.; Parr, T.; Allen, M.; Friston, K.J.; Ramstead, M.J.D. Deeply Felt Affect: The Emergence of Valence in Deep Active Inference. Neural Comput. 2020, 33, 1–49. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Williams, D. Pragmatism and the predictive mind. Phenomenol. Cogn. Sci. 2018, 17, 835–859. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
- Maley, C.J. Analog and digital, continuous and discrete. Philos. Stud. 2011, 155, 117–131. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
- Maley, C.J. Toward Analog Neural Computation. Minds Mach. 2018, 28, 77–91. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Pezzulo, G.; Rigoli, F.; Friston, K.J. Hierarchical Active Inference: A Theory of Motivated Control. Trends Cogn. Sci. 2018, 22, 294–306. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed] [Green Version]
1. | Note that we do not wish to imply that these notion are equivalent. For instance, Evan Thompson [30] emphasises important differences between phenomenological and enactive notions of intentionality (which typically involve non-representational content) and Hutto’s and Myin’s notion of basic intentionality, which does not involve content, because Hutto and Myin equate content with correctness conditions. |
2. | |
3. | |
4. | More specifically, the blanket is determined in terms of the sparsity structure of the coupling between states. At any scale, blankets are constructed by looking at the (Hessian of the) adjacency matrix and noting which partial derivatives are zero with respect to which other variables, and this forms the basis of the partition. |
5. | A non-equilibrium steady-state density must exist before a Markov blanket can be identified in terms of the ensuing conditional dependencies. |
6. | |
7. | A generative model is a probability density over external and particular states that suffices to equate the gradients of variational free energy with the gradient flows on self-information , that can be described as self-evidencing at NESS. See Equation (2). A particle is said to entail a generative model in the sense that its dynamics can be described as a gradient flow on a free energy functional of a generative model and a density that is parameterised by internal states (see [14]). |
8. | Bayesian belief is read here as a conditional probability distribution. |
9. | In fact, all self-organising systems at NESS can be cast as minimising prediction error, on average. This is because the gradients that subtends the gradient flow or systemic dynamics can always be written as a prediction error, in the form of a Kullback-Leibler divergence. |
10. | The distinction between parametric and temporal depth speaks to the hierarchical form of generative models entailed by particular dynamics. The parametric depth [102] corresponds to the depth of the hierarchy in which internal states parameterise probability distributions over the parameters of hierarchically subordinate probability distributions. Note that this implies Markov blankets within the internal states, leading to the notion of functional segregation in systems like the brain (e.g., visual cortical hierarchies). Temporal depth may be crucial when accounting for autopoietic intentionality, in the sense that generative models have to cover the consequences of an intended action—that can only be realised in the future. In other words, temporal depth accounts for the dynamics of internal states that look as if they are planning, anticipating and remembering. |
11. | Note that there may be a sense in which at least some cognitive contents are ‘free lunch’ under the free-energy principle: internal states can be regarded as carrying mathematical contents. According to this interpretation, under the normal ecological operating conditions of a free-energy minimizing device, these mathematical contents become semantic contents, or the ontology that the system brings to bear to parse its flow of sensory data. The variational free-energy becomes a measure of how plausible is a specific semantic interpretation of sensory flow. A surviving organism thus has internal representations with mathematical contents that are accurate in representing the ‘real world out there’ to the extent that they minimise variational free energy in the long run. In this interpretation, even the most deflationary account of contents as mathematical contents leads to an intrinsic semantics, in the sense that the mathematical contents themselves are sufficient to ground representationality given the right environment. This is equivalent to saying that it inhabits certain environments and enters states that are conducive to its continued existence. In other words, its viability conditions are the truth or accuracy conditions of (at least some of its) representations with cognitive contents. We are grateful to Maxwell Ramstead for pointing this out. |
12. | One could object that it may be necessary to refer to additional features to explain representations with cognitive contents that are not organism-relative, which would suggest a conceptual discontinuity with some types of representation, see [103]—we leave this as an open question for future research. |
Publisher’s Note: MDPI stays neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations. |
© 2021 by the authors. Licensee MDPI, Basel, Switzerland. This article is an open access article distributed under the terms and conditions of the Creative Commons Attribution (CC BY) license (http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/).
Share and Cite
Wiese, W.; Friston, K.J. Examining the Continuity between Life and Mind: Is There a Continuity between Autopoietic Intentionality and Representationality? Philosophies 2021, 6, 18. https://doi.org/10.3390/philosophies6010018
Wiese W, Friston KJ. Examining the Continuity between Life and Mind: Is There a Continuity between Autopoietic Intentionality and Representationality? Philosophies. 2021; 6(1):18. https://doi.org/10.3390/philosophies6010018
Chicago/Turabian StyleWiese, Wanja, and Karl J. Friston. 2021. "Examining the Continuity between Life and Mind: Is There a Continuity between Autopoietic Intentionality and Representationality?" Philosophies 6, no. 1: 18. https://doi.org/10.3390/philosophies6010018
APA StyleWiese, W., & Friston, K. J. (2021). Examining the Continuity between Life and Mind: Is There a Continuity between Autopoietic Intentionality and Representationality? Philosophies, 6(1), 18. https://doi.org/10.3390/philosophies6010018