2. Prophecy: Spinoza between Al-Farabî and Maimonides
Spinoza has with some justification been called a ‘Jewish philosopher;’ not, of course, in the sense of engaging with philosophical questions as a believing or professing Jew, but in the sense of engaging with a specifically Jewish philosophical tradition [
4,
5,
6]. More specifically, he is connected with this tradition in particular through Moses Maimonides’s
Guide of the Perplexed (
Dalâlat al-hâ’irîn), a book he possessed in Hebrew translation [
7]. To the extent that he does, however, he may also be argued to be engaging, at one remove, with the Islamic philosophical tradition from which Medieval Jewish philosophy had emerged [
8,
9]. These Islamic roots are quite clear in Maimonides’s philosophical work. Indeed, the
Guide is literally unthinkable without its Islamic philosophical background: it was originally written in Arabic, and its philosophical and theological vocabulary is largely the same as that of Maimonides’s Arabic Islamic predecessors. I will try to make the case for Spinoza’s Jewish and Islamic philosophical backgrounds by briefly discussing, first, his affinities with Maimonides, and second, his similarities with al-Farabî.
At first blush, it may seem overstated or misguided to credit Maimonides with any serious influence on Spinoza. After all, he comes in for harsh criticism in the TTP, where the latter rejects the very project of proving the philosophical respectability of Jewish Scripture as ‘ridiculous,’ and qualifying the attempt to derive ‘Aristotelian trifles’ (nugas Aristotelicas) from Scripture as ‘nonsense’ (I. 4). Despite these criticisms, however, Spinoza’s indebtedness to the Guide is obvious: it supplies, for example, both the thematic and the vocabulary for his own discussion of the relation between prophecy and philosophy. In fact, the opposition between philosophy as the realm of indubitable knowledge acquired by the intellect and prophecy as the realm of the law and the imagination appears to owe rather more to Maimonides, and more generally to the Jewish and Islamic traditions, than to Christian theology or philosophy. In the latter, prophecy and the law play a rather less central role than in the former two, for the obvious reason that the New Testament characterizes Christ not as a prophet but as the son of God; moreover, his teachings are said not so much to present or reaffirm the law as to ‘fulfill’ it (cf. Rom. 3.18).
Spinoza’s views on Christ do in fact bring him closer to Judaic and Islamic views than to Christianity. Thus, he surreptitiously characterizes Christ not as the son of God but as a prophet, albeit one with a vastly superior, perfect mind, “to whom the decrees of God… were
revealed not by words or visions but directly” (
Christum, cui Dei placita… sine verbis aut visionibus, sed immediate revelata sunt, 2.18; emph. added). Like Moses, that is, Christ is characterized here as a prophet who communicated
with God, rather than as an incarnation or hypostasis
of God. In one crucial respect, though, he is superior in prophecy even to Moses: like Maimonides, Spinoza reads the Old Testament as asserting that, whereas most prophets communicated with God indirectly (notably, as mediated by an angel), Moses directly heard the word of God himself; but to this he adds that the prophecy revealed to Christ was not mediated even by words, even if they were the words of God. Whereas Moses, unlike other prophets, “spoke with God face to face,” Spinoza elaborates, Christ “communicated with God mind to mind,” that is, not mediated by language. In other words, he represents Christ as a prophet who
receives God’s truth, albeit immediately, rather than as a hypostasis of God who
embodies that truth (
TTP, 1.18–19).
1To this, it might be objected that in 4.10, Spinoza appears to distinguish Christ from the prophets, adding that he was, much like the angels through whose mediation God had revealed things to mankind, “not so much a prophet as a mouth-piece of God” (Christus not tam propheta, quam os Dei fuit). By this, however, Spinoza appears to mean only that God has only revealed himself “to Christ or his soul” directly rather than by means of words, and that Christ’s mind was adapted to general and true notions valid for all humanity rather than only for the Jews (ibid.). Spinoza, that is, distinguishes Christ from the Biblical prophets not in ontological or soteriological terms, but only by the superiority of his understanding.
Further, Spinoza castigates Maimonides’s attempts to associate (some forms of) prophecy with the intellect rather than the imagination, and accordingly with philosophical knowledge: for him, prophetic revelation works through the imagination alone; and a man with a strong imagination inevitably has a weak intellect, and vice versa (I.4). In this respect, he turns out to stand rather closer to al-Farabî (d. 945CE), who in his main work, the
Virtuous City (
al-madîna al-fâdila), likewise defines prophecy as working through the imagination rather than the intellect (For an English translation and a (barely legible) Arabic text edition of the
Virtuous City see [
10].).
It may sound odd to associate Spinoza with an Islamic thinker from the tenth century of our era. There are no indications that Spinoza was familiar with any work of Islamic philosophy, with the possible exception of Ibn Tufayl’s Hayy ibn Yaqzan (This work, however, was published in Latin translation by Edward Pococke only in 1671 and in an anonymous Dutch translation in 1672, that is, after the completion and publication of the TTP.). Nevertheless, at one remove and mediated by Maimonides, Spinoza clearly rekindles the concepts and themes discussed by al-Farabî and other Islamic political philosophers. Maimonides held al-Farabî in the highest esteem, praising his works as “finer than sieved flour;” accordingly, the Guide is clearly indebted to al-Farabî’s analyses of the relation between philosophy and prophecy, and between mass and elite, even if it nowhere explicitly refers to the latter’s political writings (nor, incidentally, to those of any other Islamic philosopher).
Maimonides’s aims are not the same as al-Farabî’s, however; unlike the latter, who develops a Platonist political philosophy in a monotheistic setting, he defends a particular monotheistic faith against the temptations of philosophy. The ‘perplexity’ alluded to in his title is the apparent contradiction between (Judaic) Scripture and the philosophical insights yielded by the intellect and by demonstrative argument. The Guide attempts to present Scripture as philosophically respectable, and to resolve its apparent contradictions with philosophical knowledge. Rather more than al-Farabî, Maimonides thus appears keen to defend one particular revelation against the perplexing influence of philosophy.
Although Spinoza rejects Maimonides’s attempts to extract philosophical truths from Scripture, he agrees with the latter’s view that prophetic revelation is formulated in a simple and visual language that is accessible to the masses and easily understood, and that the abstract and learned discourse of philosophy is the exclusive preserve of a literate and educated elite. This distinction, too, can be found in al-Farabî–even more clearly, in fact, than in Maimonides. In chapter 14 of the Virtuous City, al-Farabî discusses the imaginative faculty (al-quwwa al-mutakhayyila). This faculty, he argues, imitates the rational faculty (al-quwwa al-nâtiqa) and the intelligibles (ma‘qûlât), by creating perceptual and pleasant images of abstract concepts (§14.6). According to this analysis, divination is comparable to dreaming, if on a higher level, since prophecy “is the most perfect rank which the imaginative faculty can reach” (§14.9).
Al-Farabî gives an almost completely naturalist account of prophecy, according to which prophecy is a feature of the imaginative faculty that all humans have, and argues that the prophet, i.e., the man endowed with the most perfect imagination, receives images from the active intellect, whether during sleep or while awake. This account is not entirely naturalist in so far as it is formulated in terms of emanation from, or actualization by, an active intellect that is external to the human soul; but it is not religious in a theist sense either, since it is (mostly) not formulated in terms of revelation (wahy) by a personal divinity or angel either. Thus, both al-Farabî and Maimonides talk about human knowledge, or rather intellection (that is, the actual thinking by the human intellect), in terms of emanation, or actualization, by an Active Intellect that is itself external to the human soul. Spinoza’s epistemology, of course, rejects these emanationist accounts; but despite appearances, it is not quite Cartesian either: for him, the nature of the human mind itself is the primary source of revelation, as it participates in God’s nature: “everything that we understand clearly and distinctly, is dictated to us… by the idea of God and by nature” (omnia, quae clare et distincte intelligimus, Dei idea… et natura nobis dictat, 1.4). Skeptical doubt, as noted, does not emerge as a serious problem in this characterization of knowledge of God.
In several respects, Spinoza stands closer to Maimonides than to al-Farabî; like the former but quite unlike the latter, he freely quotes from biblical Scripture in support of his arguments. The
TTP has been called a work of ‘applied’ or ‘practical’ philosophy [
1] (p. VIII); but its line of argumentation is generally based on Scriptural quotations rather than syllogistic arguments, and may accordingly be called theological rather than philosophical. ‘Theological’ is of course an unsatisfactory term here, given Spinoza’s stated aims of separating theology from philosophy, and of subordinating religion to the authority of the sovereign. Hence, we should return below to the question of what exactly is the character of the ‘philosophy’ espoused in the
TTP.
In fact, when we contrast him with Maimonides and Spinoza, it becomes clearer just how radical al-Farabî really is: nowhere in the Virtuous City does he quote the Qur’an even a single time in support of his argument, and nowhere does he mention Muhammad as the prophet of Islam. Instead, he generically speaks of prophets in the plural, and of the ‘first principle’ (al-sabab al-awwal) and of ‘divinity’ (ilâh) rather than the specifically Islamic God referred to by the proper name Allâh. In fact, that word appears only twice in the entire book (§15.19).
In chapter 17, the radical political implications of al-Farabî’s account become clearer. To begin with, al-Farabî makes the Platonist claim that philosophers should rule in the virtuous city, a claim both Spinoza and Maimonides stop short of. Even more daringly, he argues that in an ideal city, the ruler (
ra’îs) is both a philosopher, who has received the emanations from the active intellect through his intellect, and a prophet, who has received these emanations through his imaginative faculty (§15.10–11). Hence, for him, the philosopher has a superior kind of knowledge: whereas philosophers know things as they are, he continues, prophets only know them by imitation (
tamthîl); hence, unlike philosophers, who know things by means of demonstrative reasoning that leaves no room for doubt or debate, prophetic imitations do not yield certainty, that is, indubitable knowledge. Moreover, the one universally valid philosophical truth may be imitated by different symbols and images. That is, al-Farabî not only argues that prophetic imaginings are inferior to demonstrative philosophical knowledge, but also that
different rhetorical imitations of the same universally valid philosophical truths may exist, and hence that ‘it is possible that excellent nations and cities exist whose religions differ, although they all have as their goal one and the same felicity’ (§17.2). Put differently, he openly states that a virtuous or excellent city does not even need the specifically Islamic revelation. Spinoza, like Maimonides, falls far short of such an overtly non-religious
2 and non-confessional political philosophy that overtly–not to say defiantly–qualifies religious revelation as an inferior imitation of philosophical insights.
3. Piety: Spinoza between Thomas a Kempis and Erasmus
These differences between al-Farabî and Spinoza lead us to explore the political contents of the TTP anew. It has long been customary to read this work against the background of the canonical Western political thinkers who preceded him, in particular Hobbes, whose De Cive Spinoza is known to have read, and Machiavelli, whose Il Principe figures especially prominently in the posthumously published Tractatus Politicus. Here, however, I would like to draw attention to a number of antecedents and sources of inspiration that stem from other traditions.
To begin with, it has been argued by a number of authors that Spinoza’s work, in particular the
TTP, should be understood against the very specific political, religious, and intellectual background of the seventeenth-century Dutch Republic, which has been characterized as an unintended consequence of the revolt against the Habsburg empire ([
11], p. 49). The Republic was also something of an exception to the general trend towards centralized states and absolute rulers that could be witnessed in early modern Western Europe. Instead, the idea of a decentralized republic of autonomous provinces was both a political reality and a normative ideal, especially during the ‘stadholderless’ era (1650–1672). Partly as a result of this decentralization, it also knew a religious pluralism that was exceptional by seventeenth-century Western European standards, though not necessarily by those of premodern polities. It did have censorship laws, but these were not enforced very strictly, consistently, or even centrally. Nonetheless, the risks of publishing unorthodox views on religion were very real. As is well known, Spinoza had already run afoul of the Jewish Talmud Torah community in 1656; and when the
TTP was published—clandestinely and anonymously—in 1670, it caused such an uproar that Spinoza abstained from publishing anything else in his lifetime. In 1674, the book was banned by the states of Holland and by the Dutch States General. Subsequently, all of Spinoza’s writings would also be placed on the Inquisition’s list of prohibited books.
3Over the years, it has become increasingly clear that Spinoza’s philosophy, and in particular his political thought, is very much the result of this republican and relatively tolerant, but still dangerous, religious climate. Spinoza is even qualified a ‘Cartesian republican’ by Van Bunge because of his rejection of the Aristotelianism that constituted the school philosophy of his age [
11] (p. 36–37). Van Bunge readily acknowledges the oddity of this term, since Descartes consciously and deliberately abstained from developing any political philosophy. In the seventeenth-century Low Countries, however, Cartesianism had acquired a particular, and politicized, quality, not so much as the result of the ‘academic Cartesianism’ that was gradually gaining a foothold in the Dutch universities, but in the ‘lay Cartesianism’ expressed in the Dutch-language writings of authors like the De la Court brothers [
11] (p. 45). Below, it will appear that the question of the relation between the professionalized or school philosophy practiced by academic theologians and what–for want of a better term–one might call the ‘lay philosophy’ used by political pamphleteers is of particular relevance for Spinoza (cf. [
12]).
Famously, Spinoza argues in the
TTP that ‘the aim of the state is freedom’ (
Finis ergo Reipublicae revera libertas est, 20.6), and that there should be a ‘freedom to philosophize’ (
libertas philosophandi), because this freedom is not a threat to piety (
pietas) or political stability. However, what exactly do
pietas,
libertas, and
libertas philosophandi (and, for that matter,
philosophia) mean for him? He does not clearly define or describe any of these notions. Consequently, much ink has been spilled on the question of whether Spinoza’s notion of
libertas amounts to a form of ‘negative liberty,’ or ‘freedom-from,’ or rather to ‘positive liberty,’ or ‘freedom-to,’ as Isaiah Berlin calls it, or to a form of ‘republican liberty,’ as identified by Quentin Skinner [
13,
14,
15].
4 To the extent that Spinoza characterizes liberty in the
TTP, however, his notion appears to be closer to what today would be called ‘freedom of conscience,’ that is, the freedom of philosophical thought and religious belief, rather than any more political notion of freedom of action. Moreover, Theo Verbeek argues that Spinoza does not really demand freedom for philosophical activity in general, but more specifically for his
own philosophy [
16] (pp. 6–8).
Moreover, liberty in any political sense is difficult to square with Spinoza’s other key notion in the
TTP, that of
pietas, which—although no more defined precisely than
libertas—is generally characterized in terms of obedience, whether to a law or to a sovereign. Oddly, detailed discussion of
pietas is largely absent even from studies of the
TTP; to the extent that it is discussed, it is often linked to pagan and early Christian Roman thinkers, in particular, Stoics like Seneca. Thus, Melamed and Rosenthal do not discuss
pietas at all [
17]; Bagley largely identifies it with ‘faith’ or ‘faithfulness,’ but does not discuss it in detail [
18] (pp. 114–116); Nadler sees Spinoza’s ‘true piety,’ or the ‘inward worship of God,’ as an entirely personal matter, contrasting with the laws, which govern outward behavior [
19] (pp. 201–202); and Verbeek argues that we should take Spinoza’s
pietas in a practical sense, equivalent to the seventeenth-century Dutch ‘godzaligheid,’ adding that
pietas “is the Calvinist notion of ‘good works’” [
16] (p. 7).
5These characterizations, however, have two problems: on the one hand, they miss the overtly political dimension of Spinoza’s pietas; on the other, they misconstrue its background in the early modern forms of Christianity in the Low Countries. As I will argue below, it seems to have devotional rather than strictly Calvinist connotations. The political dimension of revealed faiths becomes clear from Spinoza’s remark that the laws revealed to particular prophets are not specific to particular peoples or cultures but to particular states (Preface, §10), and his notion of political sovereignty appears remarkably absolutist. Superficially, it may seem that for Spinoza, religious authority is textual rather than personal; on closer inspection, however, he appears to subordinate any religious authority to the political power of the sovereign, given his claims that “divine law depends solely upon the decree of the sovereign authorities” and “sovereign authorities are the [sole] interpreters of religion and piety” (19.9).
This association of piety with both political and religious obedience is rather problematic; at best, it shows an idealized concept of what true religion and true piety should amount to, not what it in fact is. Most importantly, it wrongly suggests that religious revolt and spiritual protest movements are only the result of oppression by the state. It is therefore no coincidence that Spinoza is cautious not to mention any revolts against religious authority, schismatic authors, or seditious movements of the recent past (Luther, Calvin, and the Reformation, for example, are conspicuously absent), let alone contemporary freethinkers like Koerbagh and Van den Enden. Thus, the TTP contains rather more examples from Biblical Hebrew and pagan Latin antiquity than from contemporary history; and it only briefly mentions the Dutch revolt against the Spanish king Philip II, the civil war in England, and the Remonstrant controversy that eventually led to the 1618 Orangist coup. Spinoza’s staunchly anti-revolutionary attitude even leads him to radically reinterpret recent Dutch history: since the States of Holland (Ordines Hollandiae) have never had a king, he argues, the revolt against king Philip was not an act of sedition or revolution against a legitimate monarch, but a legitimate move to recover the States’ original power (pristinum imperium) against the attempt by the ‘last count’ (ultimus comes, i.e., Philip) to usurp sovereignty (18.10; cf. 18.8, 20.15).
The second point concerns the general characteristics of early modern Dutch spiritual life. It may be tempting to seek the antecedents of Spinoza’s use of
pietas in the Reformation, and specifically in the Calvinism that dominated religious life in the seventeenth-century Republic; but one should not overemphasize these Calvinist influences. There are certainly affinities between some of Spinoza’s views and different aspects of the reformation, witness, for example, his own (dare I say Lutheran?) method of ‘Scripture alone’ (
sola scriptura I.6), i.e., of basing arguments and interpretations only on what is found in, or clearly derived from, Scripture (Preface, §10). It should be noted that this is also the argumentative style of the countless Protestant pamphlets that were published in the seventeenth-century Netherlands.
6 Against such readings, however, I would like to suggest that Spinoza’s view of religion, and in particular his conception of
pietas, is devotional and humanist rather than Calvinist. The ultimate source of this devotionalism, both in Spinoza and in the Dutch Reformation at large, is undoubtedly Thomas a Kempis (1380–1471), who had emerged out of the Brethren of the Common Life in Deventer and their the ‘modern devotion’ (
devotio moderna). In fact, it is difficult to overestimate Thomas’s importance for early modern Dutch spirituality at large, among both Catholics and Protestants, and even among Calvinists: thus, Jonathan Israel argues that Thomas “more than any other figure of the Dutch-Speaking lands of the Middle Ages remained an inspiration for the Dutch Reformed church of the seventeenth and eighteenth century, even among its most rigidly Calvinist spokesmen” [
22] (p. 42). In the seventeenth century, this devotionalist spirituality acted as a counterweight to the strict, severe, and law-oriented Calvinism of the theologians.
7In fact, Thomas a Kempis’s Imitatio Christi; is undoubtedly the historically most influential formulation of these devotional ideas: directly and indirectly, this text exerted a tremendous influence not only in the Low Countries but in Western Europe at large. Although Thomas’s inward-devotional piety does not contain any criticism of either the worldly authority of rulers or the spiritual authority of the Catholic church, it does react or protest against the late-Medieval Catholic high culture of scholastic learning, and against the professionalized philosophy of the scholastic theologians. Thus, in its emphasis on everyday spirituality and devotion, on poverty and simplicity, and on obedience out of love, the Imitatio explicitly contrasts the virtuous life of humility and devotion (caritas) with the scholastic study of the Bible and its concern with abstractions like genus and species and with cleverness (cauillacio) in debates (I.3.3–5). The latter, Thomas argues, is a ‘vain science’ (vana sciencia): it is not in itself wrong, but it is inferior to a virtuous life, and to the ‘highest study,’ which is meditating on the life of Christ (Summum igitur studium noster sit: in vita ihesu christi meditari, I.1.3). Although meditating on Christ is obviously less central to his concerns, Spinoza, too, rejects the pursuit of wealth, and contrasts the simple teaching of love (caritas) and justice in Scripture with scholastic attempts to turn religion into scientia (see esp. 13.2).
Thus, the Imitatio involves a devotional rather than law-oriented conception of faith much like Spinoza’s. This convergence becomes even clearer in Thomas’s conceptualization of obedience and submission. Throughout the Imitatio, the importance of obedience is emphasized, in particular the obedience to a spiritual authority (prelatus); but the core of this obedience is devotional love (caritas or amor), in particular for Jesus (cf. II.7). Hence, Thomas contrasts obedience out of necessity and obedience out of love; only the latter, he writes, yields inner quiet, and even freedom: only by subjecting oneself with all one’s heart and for the sake of God, he writes, does one acquire liberty of mind (Nec libertatem mentis acquirent: nisi ex toto corde propter deum se subiciant, I.9.3-4). That is, Thomas’s obedience involves not simply obeying out of necessity to a law, but obeying out of devotional love for a personalized God. Spinoza likewise emphasizes that obedience to God consists solely in justice and love, or love of one’s neighbor (obedientiam in sola Justitia et charitate sive amore erga proximum consistere, 14.10). Thus, the Imitatio may be said to have provided the broadly devotional background for Spinoza’s view of religion and piety.
Next, a devotional and humanist notion of
pietas appears explicitly, and quite frequently, in Erasmus, who from 1478 to 1485 had studied in the Latin school run by the Brethren in Deventer. Although Erasmus is critical of various aspects of the modern devotion as preached by his former teachers, preferring a more worldly devotional engagement (
pietas) to the latter’s inward-looking devotion of
Innicheit, he likewise recommends a life of humility and devotional love, free from vanity and jealousy. In his 1523 catalogue of his writings, he even lists his works promoting piety as a separate category.
8 The key term here, however, even more central than that of
pietas, is the notion of the ‘philosophy of Christ’ (
philosophia Christi), which is explicitly and systematically contrasted with the professionalized scholastic philosophy and theology. In works like the
Encheiridion and the
Paraclesis, not to mention the
Praise of Folly, Erasmus argues that this philosophy of Christ is simple, easy to understand, and formulated in the vernacular language; as such, it favorably contrasts with the scholastic
disputationes and verbal quibbles in Latin of philosophers like Ockham, Duns Scotus, and St Thomas.
Finally, in the Low Countries of Spinoza’s own age, there were various pietist movements, which likewise rejected (by now, predominantly Protestant) theological debate for a life of simple piety and devotion. This Protestant pietism had come to the Netherlands from England the late sixteenth century; the first to develop it for a specifically Dutch setting was the Middelburg-born Reformist pastor Willem Teellinck (1579–1629), whom the later pietist Gisbertus Voetius has called “a second, but Reformist, Thomas a Kempis.”
9As a work of spiritual guidance for the laity, the
Imitatio Christi enjoyed a tremendous popularity, both in handwritten and in printed forms, and both in Latin and in vernacular versions, and has rightly been called ‘early modern bestseller.’ In fact, its influence is so pervasive in early modern Dutch culture, and beyond, that it may be difficult to pinpoint or identify. To mention but one channel of such indirect influence: Ignatius of Loyola, the founder of the Jesuit order, is reported to have been particularly fond of the
Imitatio; and in fact, in his
Spiritual exercises, he explicitly recommends studying this work [
25] (p. 45).
10 It is an open question to what extent the Jesuit society appropriated and institutionalized the spirituality of the
Imitatio, for example in the
docta pietas (learned piety) as part of its 1599 plan of studies (
ratio studiorum)—a plan that Descartes, too, is likely to have followed in the years of his Jesuit education. It is equally uncertain whether Spinoza learned about the
Imitatio Christi, Erasmus and Jesuit
docta pietas through his teacher, the former Jesuit Franciscus van den Enden.
11 What is certain, however, is that there were various channels through which the
askèsis or spiritual exercise elaborated in the
Imitatio may have reached Spinoza, whether directly or indirectly.
Thus, some form of early modern Dutch devotionalism is more than likely to have been known to Spinoza, even if there is no direct evidence of him having read Thomas a Kempis any more than of his being familiar with al-Farabî. This background in devotionalism and humanism also gives Spinoza’s rejection of scholasticism a rather different flavor. Often, the reaction against scholasticism (and specifically against Aristotle’s philosophy) that we find in early modern philosophers like Descartes, Hobbes, and Spinoza has been characterized in primarily metaphysical and epistemological terms, whether in the guise of a reaction against final causes in the realm of nature, or against abstract essences or substantial forms; this, of course, fits within the narrative of the gradual professionalization of philosophy. However, in late Medieval and early modern Northern Europe, one witnesses another and rather wider reaction against scholasticism, or more precisely against the academic theological learning shaped by Aristotelianism and the high culture of Latinity that was developed in the institutions of the Catholic church and in the universities. As has long been known, the popular devotional mysticism of authors like Jan van Ruusbroec, the ‘modern devotion’ of the Brethren of the Common Life in Deventer, Luther’s translation of the Bible into the vernacular, and in a sense, the Reformation at large, may all be seen as more or less overt criticisms of this dominant Church culture, which was formulated in Latin rather than in a language the commoners (and especially women) could understand, and elaborated in a philosophical jargon that was increasingly exclusive to a small group of educated scholars eager to show off their cleverness in disputations.
Concerning the intellectual character of this devotion, however, Spinoza appears to mark a significant difference with respect to Thomas and Erasmus. He appears to agree with both in his claim that the only knowledge of God we need ‘is knowledge of His divine justice and love, that is, those attributes of God we imitate by a sound rationale of life’ (
cognitionem divinae suae justitiae et charitatis; hoc est, talia Dei attributa, quae homines certa vivendi ratione imitari possunt, 13.8).
12 Spinoza also appears to share Erasmus’s idea that the teachings of Scripture contain a simple message of devotional love. Erasmus’s expression
philosophia Christi, however, seems to suggest the opposite of what Spinoza is arguing, in so far as the latter precisely tries to
separate faith and theology from philosophy. Unlike Spinoza, Erasmus also recommends Biblical study and the acquisition of what he calls
docta pietas even for the uneducated masses and for women. He emphatically, indeed almost defiantly, calls the philosophy of Christ an ‘illiterate philosophy’ (
illiterata philosophia) or ‘vulgar’ philosophy (
philosophia plebeia), and argues that this philosophy is more effective than all the philosophical learning of sophisticated thinkers like Aristotle. Although Spinoza would agree with characterizing
pietas in terms of a simple practical ethics rather than scholastic cleverness, he resists the suggestion that the illiterate masses should be guided by devotional love; instead, for the
vulgus, he only preaches the strict obedience to the law—not so much the universal law of
pietas as the laws of specific states.
13 Like Thomas and Erasmus, Spinoza sees ‘philosophy’ as a way of life; but unlike them, he does not write for the edification of the common man (let alone woman). Thus, the ‘reader-philosopher’ he addresses in the Preface (
philosophe lector, §15) is emphatically not a commoner. Like Maimonides and al-Farabî, Spinoza maintains a strict distinction between the illiterate mass (Latin
vulgus, Arabic ‘
âmma) and educated elite (Ar.
khâssa), adding that the masses can be no more rid of their superstitions than of their irrational fear (
ibid.). In this context, his 1671 letter to Jarig Jelles warning against translating the
TTP from Latin into Dutch, the language of the masses, gains in significance.
There is also a major political difference between Spinoza and his devotionalist predecessors. To the extent that the early vernacular devotional movements embody a protest against scholastic theology, and more generally against the Latin-based theological high culture of the late-Medieval Catholic church, this popular spirituality also had an obvious political dimension: it involved a redefinition, or renegotiation, of the relation between the church and the laity, and between the illiterate mass and the educated elite. Oddly, however, Spinoza entirely ignores this popular protest implicit (or explicit) in various forms of devotional
pietas; instead, he emphatically argues that piety is identical to obedience and charity—albeit obedience to the laws of states and to the universal law of an abstract
religio catholica, rather than to a church or to a prelate. Is he merely being disingenuous here, choosing to conveniently overlook the oppositional element in the various religious and devotional movements of the recent past, not least the very Reformation out of which the Dutch Republic had emerged? Or is he really a conservative, if not an outright authoritarian, thinker, who actually believes that all religious and other sedition should be avoided, and that revealed religion is a useful and legitimate tool for controlling the masses? This point has recently been argued forcefully and provocatively by Kal [
27]; but whatever the answers to these questions, it is clear that Spinoza, with his strict and unbridgeable separation between philosophical elite and irrational religious mass, and with his downplaying of the potential for resistance in spirituality, marks a significant step
back with respect to the ideals of popular education, emancipation, and protest that had emerged in the early modern period.
These considerations finally allow for a differentiated answer to the question of Spinoza’s philosophical modernity. If the above argument concerning Spinoza’s indirect and implicit links to Islamic–Judaic philosophy and to early modern spirituality has any validity, his modernity is rather more ambivalent than some recent readings would have us believe. His emphasis on the distinction between mass and elite, and on prophetic revelation in terms of laws, correlates with Maimonides and al-Farabî; and his suggestion that the inner meaning of the law is devotional resonates with Thomas and Erasmus. We may therefore qualify Spinoza’s thought as a philosophy of askèsis as much as a philosophy of mathèsis—where askèsis is used not, of course, in the sense of austerity and self-renunciation, but in the ancient sense of training, practice, or exercise. It centers less around intellectual theoretical activity than around practical or spiritual exercise; it aims at making humans free not from doubt but from fear, and free in so far as they are guided by devotional love (caritas) and piety (pietas) rather than duty and obedience.
When looked at as a way of life to be achieved by spiritual exercises, Spinoza’s philosophy may appear to have more in common with devotional predecessors like Thomas a Kempis and Erasmus than with philosophical successors like Kant and Hegel. It also fits in better with the ‘lay Cartesianism’ preached by the popularizing pamphleteers of the Dutch Republic, some of whom were personal acquaintances of Spinoza’s. His strict elitism, however, is rather difficult to square with the ideals of these early modern predecessors, and in fact brings Spinoza rather closer to his Medieval sources of inspiration, Maimonides and al-Farabî.
4. Philosophy and Pietas as a Way of Life?
These considerations, finally, bring us to Pierre Hadot’s influential writings on philosophy as a way of life [
28,
29]. Famously, starting from obvious examples like Marcus Aurelius and Seneca and generalizing to thinkers like Socrates and Plato, Hadot argues that ancient philosophy was generally not an academic discipline but a form of spiritual exercise; it aimed not at creating a technical jargon for specialists, but at an art of living for all humans. It was only in the twelfth century, Hadot continues, that the idea of philosophy as a way of life was replaced by the idea of philosophy as an academic discipline. The setting for this professionalization of philosophy, of course, was the new institution of the university, where learned
disputatio replaced spiritual guidance. After this development, he argues, spiritual practices became the domain of Christian religion rather than professionalized philosophy; but even in early modern philosophers like Descartes and Spinoza, one can still see traces of the ancient conception. On these grounds, Hadot also criticizes what he sees as Foucault’s analysis of the rise of modern, academic, and/or scholastic philosophy. He reads the latter as arguing that, starting with Descartes, philosophy refocused from the spiritual practice of
askèsis, or care of the self (interpreted as a transformation
of the subject), to the theoretical questioning of the evidence given
to the subject, which itself is presumed to be given as well. Against this view, Hadot objects that both Descartes and Spinoza ‘remained faithful to the ancient definition: for them, philosophy was ‘the practice of wisdom’’ [
29] (p. 272).
14 In his 1982 lectures on the hermeneutics of the subject, however, Foucault rather more cautiously speaks of a ‘Cartesian
moment’ rather than a historical development starting with Descartes, recognizing that the
Meditations may also qualify as a form of spiritual exercise or ‘care of the self.’ More pertinent to our discussion, however, Foucault actually contrasts Spinoza with this Cartesian moment, in an off-the-cuff remark that, characteristically, is as suggestive as it is terse. For Descartes, he writes, knowledge alone is the condition for the subject’s access to the truth; but Spinoza’s
Treatise on the Improvement of the Intellect discusses how one has to
transform one’s being as a subject in order to have such access [
31] (pp. 17; 27–28). In other words, Foucault argues that even an early modern thinker like Spinoza sees philosophy in terms of spirituality rather than epistemology, and of askèsis rather than evidence. Especially in the first nine paragraphs of the
Treatise on the Improvement of the Intellect, he elaborates, Spinoza proceeds from the ‘properly spiritual question’ of how the subject should be transformed for it to have access to the truth. Put in these terms, the opposition between what one might call–in Foucault’s wake–the ‘Cartesian’ and the ‘Spinozian moment’ involves not so much a temporal or chronological development as a confrontation between what one may call a philosophy of knowledge, or
mathèsis, and a philosophy of spiritual exercise, or
askèsis.
15In fact, the idea of philosophy as a way of life is even more explicit in the Treatise on the Improvement of the Intellect than Foucault suggests. In the very first paragraph, Spinoza openly describes his search for a new ‘way of life’ (novum institutum) that will give one a lasting and highest joy in all eternity (continua ac summa in aeternum laetitia, §1). Arguing that the aims we pursue in our everyday lives, like wealth, honor, and sensual pleasures, are ‘vain and futile’ (vana et futilia), Spinoza argues that the highest good we can aim for is to transform our own and others’ human nature into a state of ‘knowledge of the unity that the mind has with the whole of nature’ (cognitionem unionis, quam mens cum tota Natura habet, §13). Thus, the human perfection that results from the spiritual (or, more precisely, intellectual) exercise of improving one’s understanding involves not so much correct or indubitable knowledge in itself as the ‘highest happiness’ (summa felicitas) that results from this knowledge. The certainty Spinoza aims for, that is, is ethical rather than epistemological, and Stoic rather than Cartesian; most importantly, it involves the transformation of, rather than a foundation in, one’s subjectivity.
Foucault’s claims are based exclusively on the early Treatise on the Improvement of the Intellect; but they find corroboration in the TTP, and in the Ethics. In the latter, Spinoza briefly discusses the best ‘way of living’ or ‘plan of living’ (vivendi institutum) that agrees both with his ethical principles and with common practice (communi praxi); in the former, as noted above, he speaks of the imitation of God as a ‘way of living’ or ‘rationale of life’ (ratio vivendi). Moreover, in the TTP, he explicitly states that the cultivation of piety is a precondition for access to (prophetic) truth: since the imagination does not involve clear and distinct ideas, he argues, it does not yield indubitable knowledge; instead, all prophetic certainty is founded upon the vividness of the imagining; upon a divine sign that confirms the receiver as a prophet; and, ‘most importantly’ (praecipuo), upon the fact ‘that they had only …their minds exclusively to what is right and good’ (quod animum ad solum aequum et bonum inclinatum habebant, 2.5). Put differently, Spinoza explicitly characterizes pietas as the most important precondition for prophetic certainty: ‘God… revealed things as they were to a pious man and did not forbid him to tell the truth’ (pio… rem, ut erat, revelavit, et vera praedicere non prohibuit, 2.4).
The exercise of piety, in other words, is a precondition for access to the truth. This implies that
pietas as characterized in the
TTP does indeed seem to amount to what Foucault means by spirituality, and to what Hadot means by spiritual exercises: it involves the attempt to change one’s own subjectivity in the hope of gaining access to the truth. We are far removed indeed here from cartesian epistemological concerns with evidence and skepticism.
16