Naturalistic Moral Realism and Evolutionary Biology
Abstract
:1. Introduction
Scientific realism is the doctrine that scientific theories should be understood as putative descriptions of real phenomena, that ordinary scientific methods constitute a reliable procedure for obtaining and improving (approximate) knowledge of the real phenomena which scientific theories describe, and that the reality described by scientific theories is largely independent of our theorizing… By “moral realism” I intend the analogous doctrine about moral judgments, moral statements and moral theories.[4] (p. 181)
Lack of capacity to reproduce is a defect in a human being. But choice of childlessness and even celibacy is not thereby shown to be defective choice, because human good is not the same as plant or animal good. The bearing and rearing of children is not an ultimate good in human life, because other elements of good such as the demands of work to be done may give a man or woman reason to renounce family life. And the great (if often troubling) good of having children has to do with the love and ambition of parents for children, the special role of grandparents, and many other things that simply do not belong to animal life.[5] (p. 42)
2. Function
3. Fitness
There is the important insight that individuals of identical fitness can differ in how successful they are at surviving and reproducing. The individuals have the same abilities, but good luck for some and bad luck for others can lead to unequal outcomes.[45] (p. 336)
4. Eudaimonia and Virtue
Eudaimonia: for any species X, a member of that species, x, is a eudaimon [is flourishing or thriving] if and only if x has developed to a high [excellent] degree the propensities for carrying out the organismic functions characteristic of X, which solve, in normal circumstances, the life problems characteristic of X.
Funding
Conflicts of Interest
1 | While criticisms are to follow of Foot, I trust my respect for and indebtedness to her philosophy is apparent. |
2 | She writes, “there is no change in the meaning of ‘good’ between the word as it appears in ‘good roots’ and as it appears in ‘good dispositions of the human will’” (italics in original) [5] (p. 39). |
3 | Why may we leave aside issues regarding voluntary action, free will? The answer is that naturalistic moral realists are committed to naturalism, so that whatever “volition” and “free will” turn out (not) to be, they will be construed naturalistically. Naturalistic moral realists are committed to there being facts about what is good and bad, right and wrong, and will say that these facts are determined by empirical human nature and what makes human life go well. How or if we are able to train our wills to do what we ought to do is a psychological issue, not a metaethical or metaphysical one. |
4 | Foot is wrong about the lack of role for grandparents in the animal world: Darwin explains the sterility of worker bees explicitly in terms of the relation between a Queen bee and her grand-offspring. See Sober [10]. |
5 | For an overview of the literature on biological functions that covers etiological theories, propensity theories, and Cummins functions, see D. Walsh and A. Ariew [11]. Walsh and Ariew do not discuss “learning theories” or “organizational theories”. For the former, see C. A. Mace [12]; I. Scheffler [13]; D. T. Campbell [14]; W. Wimsatt [15]; B. Enc and F. Adams [16]. For organizational theories, see G. Schlosser [17]; P. McLaughlin [18]; W. Christensen & M. Bickhard [19]; M. Weber [20]; M. Mossio, C. Saborido & A. Moreno [21]. |
6 | The classic statement of the explanandum of biological function is Wright [22]. |
7 | While normativity is taken up below, issues regarding the possible mysterious contributions of teleology are left behind, as we are assuming both naturalism and that biology, and the physical sciences generally, have the resources to fully explain biological function. For a current view of naturalized teleology, see D. Walsh [23]. |
8 | One famous attempt to reduce life is Erwin Schrodinger [28]. Schrodinger posited “anti-entropy” to explain the way that living organisms resisted the second law of thermodynamics, but this obviously just names the basic problem and does not solve it. |
9 | Do these ancient thoughts, with their roots in the ergon arguments of Plato [29] (352d–354c) and Aristotle [30] (1097b21–1098a20), contravene Hume’s dictum telling us that we can never derive an “ought” from an “is”? Yes, they do! But here we can side with Arthur Prior, who implicitly appealed to functions when he said that, “from the premise that ‘he is a sea captain’, we can conclude that ‘he ought to do whatever a sea captain ought to do’.” The biological analog is to infer from “it is a heart” to “it ought to do what hearts ought to do”: a heart ought to circulate the blood for reasons adduced above; a heart in acute myocardial infarction is not doing what it ought to do. This example is attributed to Prior without reference by Alasdair MacIntyre [31] (p. 57). For an expansion of Prior’s thought, though he does not discuss this example per se, see [32]. |
10 | See, for instance, see the website for EES at http://extendedevolutionarysynthesis.com/ (accessed on 6 August 2021). |
11 | This issue is complicated and somewhat vexed. There are prima facie concerns about how the development of organisms could be distinct from evolution, given that each organism is a member of the species which itself is the product of evolution. But there is no need to investigate these questions here. |
12 | |
13 | In fact, there is a theory of population genetics which fully rejects the idea of individual fitness, arguing that fitness is only a property of traits, considered on their own. This theory is called “statisticalism”, and if indeed it is the truth about fitness, then the naturalistic moral realist will not be able to appeal to fitness as it presently can. See, Mohan Matthen and André Ariew [48]; Denis Walsh, André Ariew, and Mohan Matthen [49]. |
14 | For the importance of seeing “one’s life as a whole” to the project of eudaimonism, see Julia Annas [51]. |
15 | For a comment on the nature of the responsibility we have for our characters, cf. footnote 7 above, re: free will and volition. |
16 | |
17 | For views of wisdom as a “metaheuristic” for solving problems endemic to the human condition, see the Berlin Wisdom Paradigm, as developed by the psychologists, Paul Baltes and Ursula Staudinger [59]; Paul Baltes, Judith Glück, and Ute Kunzmann [60]. For philosophical approaches to wisdom along similar lines, see Jason Swartwood [61] and Tsai [62]. |
18 | Indeed, this is part of the explanation for why bee hives have so many sterile workers. Cf. Note 8. |
19 | In personal communication (16 June 2018), the anthropologist Sandra Hrdy writes, “Relevant to your thesis that the ‘best human parents will be brave, well-tempered, fair, and wise, and the children of these parents will be most likely to survive and flourish themselves’ is the recent interest by anthropologists in child-rearing among African and other people still living as hunter-gatherers… In general, these findings are consistent with your thesis though I would add ‘tolerant’ [to the list of virtues].” A traditional virtue theoretic perspective would, I think, understand tolerance as an aspect of temperance. Hrdy cited [71,72,73]. |
20 | The idea that we can understand moral cognition by modeling it on linguistic has been entertained by many including Noam Chomsky and John Rawls, but for one way of developing this thought in detail, see, John Mikhail [74]. |
21 | There are some indications that, at least, Western parents do not play as important a role in the development of their children’s character as common sense says. For more on this see Judith Harris [75]. There are also some indications that, in fact, people abused as children are not more likely to be abusive parents than people not abused as children. Even if this is the case, it still seems likely that in a variety of characterological ways, children model their parents. See Cathy Spatz Wisdom, Sally Czaja, Kimberly DuMont [76]. |
References
- Quine, W.V.O. Two Dogmas of Empiricism. In From a Logical Point of View; Harvard University Press: Cambridge, UK, 1953. [Google Scholar]
- Quine, W.V.O. Word and Object; MIT Press: Cambridge, MA, USA, 1960. [Google Scholar]
- Quine, W.V.O. Carnap and Logical Truth. In The Philosophy of Rudolph Carnap; Schilpp, P., Ed.; Open Court: LaSalle, IL, USA, 1963. [Google Scholar]
- Boyd, R. How to be a Moral Realist. In Essays on Moral Realism; Sayre-McCord, G., Ed.; Cornell University Press: Ithaca, NY, USA, 1988. [Google Scholar]
- Foot, P. Natural Goodness; Clarendon Press: Oxford, UK, 2001. [Google Scholar]
- Thompson, M. The Representation of Life. In Virtues and Reasons; Hursthouse, R., Lawrence, G., Quinn, W., Eds.; Clarendon Press: Oxford, UK, 1995. [Google Scholar]
- Anscombe, G.E.M. On Promising and its Justice. Critica 1969, 3, 61–83. [Google Scholar]
- Kitcher, P. Ethics and Biology. In The Oxford Handbook of Ethical Theory; Copp, D., Ed.; Oxford University Press: New York, NY, USA, 2006. [Google Scholar]
- Hurka, T. Perfectionism; Oxford University Press: Oxford, UK, 1993. [Google Scholar]
- Sober, E. Did Darwin Write the Origin Backward? Prometheus: Buffalo, NY, USA, 2011. [Google Scholar]
- Walsh, D.; Ariew, A. A Taxonomy of Functions. Can. J. Philos. 1996, 26, 493–514. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Mace, C.A. Mechanical and Teleological Causation. In Readings in Philosophical Analysis; Fiegl, H., Sellers, W., Eds.; Appleton-Century-Crofts: New York, NY, USA, 1949. [Google Scholar]
- Scheffler, I. Thoughts on Teleology. Br. J. Philos. Sci. 1959, 9, 265–284. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Campbell, D.T. Blind variation and selective survival as a general strategy in knowledge processes. In Self-Organizing Systems; Cameron, M.C., Yovitz, S., Eds.; Pergamon Press: New York, NY, USA, 1960. [Google Scholar]
- Wimsatt, W. Teleology and the Logical Structure of Function Statements. Stud. Hist. Philos. Sci. 1972, 3, 1–80. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Enc, B.; Adams, F. Functions and Goal Directedness. Philos. Sci. 1992, 59, 635–654. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Schlosser, G. Self-re-production and functionality: A systems-theoretical approach to teleological explanation. Synthese 1998, 116, 303–354. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- McLaughlin, P. What Functions Explain: Functional Explanation and Self-Reproducing Systems; Cambridge University Press: Cambridge, UK, 2001. [Google Scholar]
- Christensen, W.; Bickhard, M. The process dynamics of normative function. Monist 2002, 85, 3–28. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Weber, M. Philosophy of Experimental Biology; Cambridge University Press: Cambridge, UK, 2005. [Google Scholar]
- Mossio, M.; Saborido, C.; Moreno, A. An organizational account of biological functions. Br. J. Philos. Sci. 2009, 60, 813–841. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
- Wright, L. Functions. Philos. Rev. 1973, 82, 139–168. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Walsh, D. Teleology. In The Oxford Handbook of Philosophy of Biology; Ruse, M., Ed.; Oxford University Press: Oxford, UK, 2008. [Google Scholar]
- Dawkins, R. The Selfish Gene; Oxford University Press: New York, NY, USA, 1976. [Google Scholar]
- Lloyd, E. Units and Levels of Selection. In The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy; Center for the Study of Language and Information, Stanford University: Stanford, CA, USA, 2017. [Google Scholar]
- Sober, E.; Wilson, D.S. Unto Others; Harvard University Press: Cambridge, MA, USA, 1999. [Google Scholar]
- Okasha, S. Evolution and the Levels of Selection; Oxford University Press: New York, NY, USA, 2006. [Google Scholar]
- Schrodinger, E. What is Life? Cambridge University Press: Cambridge, UK, 1944. [Google Scholar]
- Plato. Republic; Oxford University Press: Oxford, UK, 1993. [Google Scholar]
- Aristotle. Nicomachean Ethics; Cambridge University Press: Cambridge, UK, 2014. [Google Scholar]
- MacIntyre, A. After Virtue; Notre Dame University Press: Paris, France, 1984. [Google Scholar]
- Prior, A.N. The Autonomy of Ethics. Australas. J. Philos. 1960, 38, 199–206. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Plantinga, A. Warrant and Proper Function; Oxford University Press: Oxford, UK, 1993. [Google Scholar]
- Burge, T. Origins of Objectivity; Oxford University Press: Oxford, UK, 2010. [Google Scholar]
- Millikan, R. Language, Thought, and Other Biological Categories; Bradford Books, MIT Press: Cambridge, MA, USA, 1984. [Google Scholar]
- Becker, L. A New Stoicism; Princeton University Press: Princeton, NJ, USA, 1998. [Google Scholar]
- Becker, L. Habilitation, Health, and Agency; Oxford University Press: Oxford, UK, 2012. [Google Scholar]
- Bloomfield, P. Moral Reality; Oxford University Press: New York, NY, USA, 2001. [Google Scholar]
- Thomson, J. Goodness and Advice; Gutmann, A., Ed.; Princeton University Press: Princeton, NJ, USA, 2003. [Google Scholar]
- Moosavi, P. Neo-Aristotelian Naturalism and the Evolutionary Objection. In Philippa Foot on Goodness and Virtue; Hacker-Wright, J., Ed.; Palgrave MacMillian: New York, NY, USA, 2018. [Google Scholar]
- Moosavi, P. From Biological Functions to Natural Goodness. Philos. Impr. 2019, 19, 1–20. [Google Scholar]
- Laubichler, M. Evo-Devo: Historical and Conceptual Reflections. In Form and Function in Developmental Evolution; Laubichler, M., Maienschein, J., Eds.; Cambridge University Press: Cambridge, UK, 2009. [Google Scholar]
- Müller, G.B. Evo-Devo: Extending the Evolutionary Synthesis. Nat. Rev. Genet. 2007, 8, 943–949. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Mills, S.; Beatty, J. The Propensity Interpretation of Fitness. Philos. Sci. 1979, 46, 263–286. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
- Sober, E. Trait Fitness is Not a Propensity, but Fitness Variation Is. Stud. Hist. Philos. of Sci. Part C Stud. Hist. Philos. Biol. Biomed. Sci. 2013, 44, 336–341. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed]
- Sober, E. The Nature of Selection; University of Chicago Press: Chicago, IL, USA, 1993. [Google Scholar]
- Scriven, M. Explanation and Prediction in Evolutionary Theory. Science 1959, 130, 477–482. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Matthen, M.; Ariew, A. Two Ways of Thinking about Fitness and Natural Selection. J. Philos. 2002, 99, 55–83. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
- Walsh, D.; Ariew, A.; Matthen, M. Four Pillars of Statisticalism. Philos. Theory Pract. Biol. 2017, 9, 1–18. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
- Burge, T. Primitive Agency and Natural Norms. Philos. Phenomenol. Res. 2009, 79, 251–278. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Annas, J. The Morality of Happiness; Oxford University Press: Oxford, UK, 1993. [Google Scholar]
- Pervin, L.A. A Critical Analysis of Current Trait Theory. Psychol. Inq. 1994, 5, 103–113. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Miller, C. Character and Moral Psychology; Oxford University Press: Oxford, UK, 2014. [Google Scholar]
- Nussbaum, M. Non-Relative Virtues: An Aristotelian Approach. Midwest Stud. Philos. 1988, 13, 32–53. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Strawson, P.F. Freedom and Resentment. Proc. Br. Acad. 1962, 48, 187–211. [Google Scholar]
- Hampton, J. Feminist Contractarianism. In A Mind of One’s Own; Antony, L., Witt, C., Eds.; Westview Press: Boulder, CO, USA, 1993. [Google Scholar]
- Hampton, J. Selflessness and Loss of Self. Soc. Philos. Policy 1993, 1, 135–165. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
- Bloomfield, P. Justice as a Self-Regarding Virtue. Philos. Phenomenol. Res. 2011, 82, 46–64. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Baltes, P.; Ursula Staudinger, U. Wisdom: A Metaheuristic (Pragmatic) to Orchestrate Mind and Virtue Toward Excellence. Am. Psychol. 2000, 55, 122–136. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Baltes, P.; Glück, J.; Kunzmann, U. Wisdom: Its Structure and Function in Regulating Successful Life Span Development. In Handbook of Positive Psychology; Snyder, C.R., Lopez, S.J., Eds.; Oxford University Press: Oxford, UK, 2005. [Google Scholar]
- Swartwood, J. Wisdom as an Expert Skill. Ethical Theory Moral Pract. 2013, 16, 511–528. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Tsai, C. Phronesis and Techne: The Skill Model of Wisdom Defended. Australas. J. Philos. 2020, 98, 234–247. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Foot, P. Moral Beliefs. In Virtues and Vices; University of California Press: Berkeley, CA, USA, 1978. [Google Scholar]
- Bloomfield, P. The Virtues of Happiness; Oxford University Press: New York, NY, USA, 2014. [Google Scholar]
- Bloomfield, P. Morality is Necessary for Happiness. Philos. Stud. 2017, 174, 2613–2628. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Lawrence, G. Acquiring Character. In Moral Psychology and Human Action in Aristotle; Pakaluk, M., Pearson, G., Eds.; Oxford University Press: Oxford, UK, 2011. [Google Scholar]
- Sober, E. The Nature of Selection; MIT Press: Cambridge, MA, USA, 1984. [Google Scholar]
- Dillon Ripley, S. Competition between Sunbird and Honeyeater Species in the Moluccan Islands. Am. Nat. 1959, 93, 127–132. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Hutchinson, G.E.; MacArthur, R.H. Appendix on the Theoretical Significance of Aggressive Neglect in Interspecific Competition. Am. Nat. 1959, 93, 133–134. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Dillon Ripley, S. Aggressive Neglect as a Factor in Interspecific Competition in Birds. Auk 1961, 78, 366–371. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Hewlett, B.; Lamb, M. Hunter Gatherer Childhood; Transaction Publishers: New Brunswick, NJ, USA, 2005. [Google Scholar]
- Konner, M. Evolution of Childhood; Belknap Press: Cambridge, MA, USA, 2010. [Google Scholar]
- Meehan, C.; Crittenden, A. Childhood: Origin, Implications and Evolution; University of New Mexico Press: Albuquerque, NM, USA, 2016. [Google Scholar]
- Mikhail, J. Elements of Moral Cognition; Cambridge University Press: Cambridge, UK, 2011. [Google Scholar]
- Harris, J. The Nurture Assumption; Free Press: New York, NY, USA, 2009. [Google Scholar]
- Wisdom, C.S.; Czaja, S.; DuMont, K. Intergenerational Transmission of Child Abuse and Neglect. Science 2015, 347, 1480–1485. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed] [Green Version]
Publisher’s Note: MDPI stays neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations. |
© 2021 by the author. Licensee MDPI, Basel, Switzerland. This article is an open access article distributed under the terms and conditions of the Creative Commons Attribution (CC BY) license (https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/).
Share and Cite
Bloomfield, P. Naturalistic Moral Realism and Evolutionary Biology. Philosophies 2022, 7, 2. https://doi.org/10.3390/philosophies7010002
Bloomfield P. Naturalistic Moral Realism and Evolutionary Biology. Philosophies. 2022; 7(1):2. https://doi.org/10.3390/philosophies7010002
Chicago/Turabian StyleBloomfield, Paul. 2022. "Naturalistic Moral Realism and Evolutionary Biology" Philosophies 7, no. 1: 2. https://doi.org/10.3390/philosophies7010002
APA StyleBloomfield, P. (2022). Naturalistic Moral Realism and Evolutionary Biology. Philosophies, 7(1), 2. https://doi.org/10.3390/philosophies7010002