Criteria for Ethical Allocation of Scarce Healthcare Resources: Rationing vs. Rationalizing in the Treatment for the Elderly
Abstract
:1. The Growing Need for Healthcare and the Chronic Resource Scarcity
2. Public Health Emergencies and the Rise of Difficult Choices: Macro Allocation Ethical Complexity
3. Prioritization Models and Criteria: Micro Allocation Ethical Challenges
3.1. First-Come, First-Served, and Higher-Severity, Higher-Priority
3.2. Rationing and Rationalizing22
4. The Age Criterion in the Allocation of Limited Resources during the Pandemic27
4.1. The Puzzling Age Factor
4.2. Rationing vs. Rationalization in the Elderly
Funding
Institutional Review Board Statement
Informed Consent Statement
Conflicts of Interest
1 | “Between 2000 and 2017, the global economy grew 1.6 times in real GDP per capita. As countries became richer, the demand for healthcare increased along with people’s expectations for their government to increase access to quality services. Concurrently, the cost of health services rose because of more expensive technologies. These factors drove up health spending globally. The increase has been particularly rapid in lower middle income and upper middle income countries”. |
2 | The World Health Organization (WHO) declared COVID-19 a pandemic on 11 March 2020: https://www.who.int/director-general/speeches/detail/who-director-general-s-opening-remarks-at-the-media-briefing-on-covid-19---11-March-2020 (accessed on 30 September 2022). |
3 | Let us consider, for example, the current health crisis which is viral and most likely zoonotic. Today, zoonoses account for about 60% of recognized pathogens (viruses, bacteria, protozoa, parasites, and fungi) and 75% of emerging (see [3]; their incidence rate in human health tends to increase due to human invasion of natural habitats, greater proximity between humans and animals, and increased human mobility with ease of travel, amongst other causes. Many zoonotic diseases do not yet have a cure, so the risks of infection and contagion become high. Furthermore, it is important to consider the viral mutations that whilst unavoidable, are also uncontrollable, only allowing forms of action a posteriori. Even though most viral mutations do not have a significant impact on public health, and the average speed of effective response to their health impacts is increasing—as was evident in the production of vaccines against COVID-19—health systems will only be able to react to new and harmful virus variants when they have already started to be transmitted within the wider community. |
4 | The current threats to public health do not result only from viruses, but also from bacteria and their increasing resistance to antibiotics, with the parallel loss of effectiveness of these, as is the case with some microorganisms (bacteria, fungi, viruses, and parasites) which are designated as ultra-resistant to most antimicrobials (See [4]). This is a reality that has been developing for a long time and that, during the pandemic, has been neglected, without, however, the risk having ceased to increase. The growing resistance to antibiotics heralds a reversal of the successes of recent centuries of progressive capacity to cure diseases, corresponding with a disturbing resurgence of untreatable pathologies. |
5 | While the world is still struggling with the COVID-19 pandemic, on 23 July 2022, WHO declared Monkeypox as a new global health emergency: https://www.who.int/news/item/23-07-2022-second-meeting-of-the-international-health-regulations-(2005)-(ihr)-emergency-committee-regarding-the-multi-country-outbreak-of-monkeypox. (accessed on 30 September 2022) |
6 | We refer, then, for example, to the growing number of patients with chronic diseases who, in a not-so-distant past, would not have survived, but who today can enjoy a long life with good control of a chronic pathology; significant increases in life healthcare worldwide (albeit mostly in the Western world), also increasing the number of years that each person needs healthcare which, as in the previous example, sends a growing influx of users to health services; and demographic growth all over the world (mostly in Asia and the Southern hemisphere), also increasing the number of people in need of healthcare. We also refer to cutting-edge technologies and state-of-the-art drugs that benefit patients who might otherwise be condemned to a life with some degree of limitation and certainly one which is shorter, but whose very high price significantly burdens national health services. It is, in fact, this constant scientific-technological innovation and the high cost of the products that are materializing which confirms the permanent deficit of healthcare resources: if there are new and better healthcare resources, they should be made available; however, their high price does not allow them to become accessible to all who need them, which results in chronic resource scarcity. |
7 | This will require, in terms of resource management, the elaboration of contingency plans—arrangements (identification, organization, coordination) in advance, to enable timely, effective, and appropriate responses to possible emergency situations—as well as the organization of strategic reserves—maintaining a pre-positioned backup of essential goods and emergency medical supplies to ensure a swift response to critical needs in cases of public health emergencies (See [5]). |
8 | “The term itself may refer either to the interests that members have in common or to the facilities that serve common interests. […] The common good is an important concept in political philosophy because it plays a central role in philosophical reflection about the public and private dimensions of social life.” |
9 | We understand its importance by remembering the recent pandemic experience. A large proportion of the existing healthcare resources were redirected to the fight against COVID-19, which has consequently dramatically affected other health sectors as diverse as oncology, surgery, prevention, and primary care, with very high costs in terms of human lives, and in the number of years of life and general well-being of citizens and populations. A good macro allocation is therefore an ethical imperative. |
10 | The deontological perspective began, in the western history of ethics, with Kant (See [7]), in 1785, and his enunciation of the moral law in whose fulfillment morality consists (regardless of the consequences). Morality consists of obedience to principles. |
11 | We refer to the Aristotelian formulation of the principle of “justice” in a very broad sense, as a guide to action (being a consequentialist or teleological principle). Aristotle defines “justice” specifically as a virtue (one of the four cardinal virtues) (See [8]). |
12 | Jeremy Bentham (1776), the founder of utilitarianism, in his Fragment on Government (see [9]) refers to the “fundamental axiom” as “the greatest happiness of the greatest number that is the measure of right and wrong.” A utilitarian approach to justice was developed by Stuart Mill (see [10]) and Henry Sidgwick (see [11] being also a consequentialist or teleological principle). |
13 | The specification of ethical principles into rules of action, that is, trying to qualify them, to give them more content when solving concrete problems, was first proposed by Henry S. Richardson (See [12], pp. 279–310). Richardson proposes the “specification” of principles to solve concrete ethical problems, instead of “applying” them directly to cases or to “balance” them when they are in conflict: (see [13], pp 285–307). We are freely using the model of specification to explain how the maximization of good corresponds to the principle of social utility. |
14 | The ideas of self-ownership and of minimal state are shared by libertarians in general, and well developed by Robert Nozick [14]. Distributive justice depends on a legitimate acquisition of goods, and also on the consideration of respect for the persons’ rights and for their possessions. |
15 | John Rawls [15] presents two major principles of justice: the (first, the one that takes priority over the second) principle of equal basic liberties; and the second principle (with two parts, the first taking priority over the second) of fair equality of opportunity together with the difference principle, under which special benefits can be attributed to the least advantaged members of society. |
16 | |
17 | The teleological perspective dates back to Ancient Greece, having been systematized by Aristotle, the founder of ethics, in his hierarchy of ends or goods and the establishment of means (virtues) to achieve them. Morality consists of the realization of successive goods, of the greater good. |
18 | The procedural perspective is contemporary, having begun to be developed within the scope of the discourse ethics by Karl-Otto Apel [20] and Jürgen Habermas [21], in their valorization of (rational) communication, of dialogue as a process of building (communicative) consensuses that legitimize action. This is what morality consists of. |
19 | Integrity, etymologically, refers to a whole, considered in its unaltered completeness, without fissures or gaps affecting or corrupting it, an incorrupt totality; which, in terms of action, translates into a behavior that cannot be influenced by sectarian and particular interest (see [22], pp 181–187). |
20 | Transparency, etymologically, refers to that which ‘lets the light through’, thus also letting the eye see or become visible; this, in terms of action, translates into making a given reality publicly accessible. |
21 | Extraordinarily, in exceptional situations such as those of war, natural disasters, and pandemics, triage can lead to discarding the most severe patients, those evaluated as beyond salvation. |
22 | The literature on the allocation of healthcare resources is very often focused on the issue of "rationing". The conceptualization of “rationalization” is rare, and the term “rationing” is sometimes used to classify a procedure that, in fact, corresponds to “rationalization”. Therefore, there is no really relevant bibliography on rationing vs rationalization. Nevertheless, its objective and clear distinction makes available two possible instruments, or strategies for the allocation of healthcare resources with obvious benefits for citizens and for national health systems, as we will show. |
23 | Both words derive etymologically from the Latin word ratio, onis, which could mean: the “calculation”, a numerical calculation; and also the capacity to calculate, that is, intelligence or judgment. Rationing focuses on the result of the judgment (its product), the ratio between two values, such as the goods to be assigned and the people in need of them: that which enables a relationship to be established between both. Rationalization focuses on the ability to make good judgments (the exercise of reason), applying reason to any decision, including the allocation of resources, in order to obtain the maximum benefit, making it more effective. Therefore, although rationing and rationalization have the same etymological source, they also have different meanings. |
24 | Eva Winkler [25] is one of the few scholars that present “rationalization”, “rationing”, and “prioritization” as “strategies to reduce the utilization of limited resources”. However, the definition of “rationalization” and “rationing”, and the comparison between both is not rigorous and clarifying enough. |
25 | The decision-making process satisfies the prevailing utilitarianism in health (following a teleological logic), based on respect for human dignity (following a deontological logic). |
26 | Even if, in some cases, the outcome is the same, whatever the logic used, the process will have been different. The teleological perspective (such as utilitarianism), would focus solely on the outcomes; the procedural perspective would also value the process adopted. When the outcome is the same, the difference lies in the procedure. This is particularly important when the outcome is negative, such as the exclusion of some people from healthcare. |
27 | The bibliography on the age criterion in the allocation of health care resources is very extensive and varied, and can adopt different perspectives, and invoke different reasons. As it is not our purpose, in the present context, to carry out a survey of the plurality of positions on the matter and respective grounds, we chose to systematize our position on the subject, based on the prevailing practices, in the healthcare setting, in this area. |
28 | “Age” has been a recurrent theme in the scrutiny of access to scarce healthcare resources and almost invariably a factor of exclusion (not admitting patients over a certain age), or of secondary access (admitting the elderly only in the absence of pressure on resources) (see [27], pp. 272–273). Yet, it was Daniel Callahan [28] who strongly proposed that life-extending medical care for the elderly (beyond the age of 70 or 80) should not be provided at state expense. This work—in the wake of Alasdair MacIntyre [29]—has been seminal and headed a position defended by many in a panoply of publications that have multiplied up to the present day. Nevertheless, this was not the predominant orientation during the pandemic, according to most of the guidelines that several national and international organizations have published since the beginning of the pandemic and that the WHO makes available under the title “Statements by National Ethics Committees” (https://www.who.int/teams/health-ethics-governance/diseases/covid-19/resources). (accessed on 30 September 2022) |
29 | We recognize that the use of biological age is not easy, especially in emergency situations, and neither does it have a parallel accuracy to that of chronological age. These facts, however, do not advocate the use of chronological age, but rather reinforce the ambiguity of using the age criterion. Either the biological age, the most clinically relevant, is used, or the age factor should not be used at all. |
30 | The attribution of a specific value to a person based on a characteristic constitutes a double violation of human dignity: (firstly) the intangible identity of the person cannot be reduced and objectified to no matter which characteristic, (secondly) because all people and each one has unconditional value—in the Kantian definition of the dignity of the person that is still predominant today. As Solomon, Wynia and Gostin argue [31], the same logic of exclusion due to physical characteristics (banned in democracies when referring to gender, ethnicity, etc.), such as age, could be coherently extended to the exclusion of many other individuals: for example, disabled persons or those with genetic or chronic diseases. |
31 | Joebges and Biller-Andorno [32], analyzing a few European triaging guidelines, also refer to the role of short-term vs. long-term survival as a key triaging criterion. Another expression also used within this context is the “natural life span” used to point out that some individuals have already achieved it and therefore their access to health care should be restricted (Callahan, 1987) [28]. |
32 | Vinay R, Baumann H, Biller-Andorno (see [33]) consider that, in triage protocols, at the international level, there is a highly consensual agreement to rely on medical prognosis, maximizing lives saved, and avoiding a quality-adjusted life-years policy. |
33 | The assessment of biological age (at the peak of COVID-19 or other public health emergencies) would have been difficult and even quite inaccurate. However, it would be preferable to the automatic exclusion of a person from intensive care solely because of their chronological age. The awareness of the distinction between biological age and chronological age and the greater importance of the first, taking into account the objective of saving lives, would have led to a personal (clinical evaluation) and not to an administrative (screening of personal identification) evaluation. |
References
- World Health Organization. Strengthening Public Sector Capacity, Budgets and Dynamic Capabilities towards Health for All. Council Brief n.º 4. 30 June 2022. Available online: https://cdn.who.int/media/docs/default-source/council-on-the-economics-of-health-for-all/who_councileh4a_councilbrief4.pdf?sfvrsn=275a7451_3&download=true (accessed on 30 September 2022).
- World Health Organization. Global Spending on Health: A World in Transition. 2019, p. 16. Available online: https://www.who.int/publications/i/item/WHO-HIS-HGF-HFWorkingPaper-19.4 (accessed on 30 September 2022).
- World Health Organization/EMRO. Zoonotic Disease: Emerging Public Health Threats in the REGION. 2021. Available online: http://www.emro.who.int/fr/about-who/rc61/zoonotic-diseases.html (accessed on 30 September 2022).
- World Health Organization. Antimicrobial Resistance. Key Facts. 2021. Available online: https://www.who.int/news-room/fact-sheets/detail/antimicrobial-resitance (accessed on 30 September 2022).
- World Health Organization. Strategic Preparedness, Readiness and Response Plan to End the Global COVID-19 Emergency in 2022. 2022. Available online: https://www.who.int/publications/i/item/WHO-WHE-SPP-2022.1 (accessed on 30 September 2022).
- Hussain, W.; The Common Good. The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Zalta, E.N., Ed., Spring Edition 2018. Available online: https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2018/entries/common-good/ (accessed on 30 September 2022).
- Kant, E. Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals, 2nd revised ed.; Cambridge University Press: Cambridge, UK, 2019. [Google Scholar]
- Aristotle. Ethics Nicomachean; Book V, 1131a; J. Vrin: Paris, France, 1900; pp. 21–24. [Google Scholar]
- Bentham, J. Fragment on Government; Cambridge University Press: Cambridge, UK, 2012. [Google Scholar]
- Mill, S. Utilitarianism, On Liberty, Representative Government; Lindsay, A.D., Ed.; Dent: London, UK, 1964. [Google Scholar]
- Sidgwick, H. The Methods of Ethics; Macmillan: London, UK, 1907. [Google Scholar]
- Richardson, H.S. Specifying Norms as a Way to Resolve Concrete Ethical Problems. Philos. Public Aff. 1990, 19, 279–310. [Google Scholar]
- Richardson, H.S. Specifying, balancing, and interpreting bioethical principles. J. Med. Philos. 2000, 25, 285–307. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Nozick, R. Anarchy, State, and Utopia; Basic Books: New York, NY, USA, 1974. [Google Scholar]
- Rawls, J. A Theory of Justice; Harvard University Press: Cambridge, MA, USA, 1971; Revised edition, 1999. [Google Scholar]
- Sandel, M. Liberalism and the Limits of Justice; Cambridge University Press: Cambridge, UK, 1982. [Google Scholar]
- MacIntyre, A. Whose Justice? Which Rationality? University of Notre Dame Press: Notre Dame, IN, USA, 1988. [Google Scholar]
- Taylor, C. Conditions of an Unforced Consensus on Human Rights. In The East Asian Challenge for Human Rights; Bauer, J.R., Bell, D., Eds.; Cambridge University Press: New York, NY, USA, 1999. [Google Scholar]
- Walzer, M. Spheres of Justice; Blackwell: Oxford, UK, 1983. [Google Scholar]
- Apel, K.-O. Towards a Transformation of Philosophy, Translated by Glyn Adey and David Frisby; Routledge and Kegan Paul: London, UK, 1983. [Google Scholar]
- Habermas, J. The Theory of Communicative Action. Vol. I: Reason and the Rationalization of Society; McCarthy, T., Ed.; Beacon: Boston, MA, USA, 1984; Volume 1. (In German) [Google Scholar]
- Patrão Neves, M. On scientific integrity: Conceptual clarification. Med. Health Care Philos. 2018, 21, 181–187. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed]
- Sciacchitano, S.; Bartolazzi, A. Transparency in Negotiation of European Union with Big Pharma on COVID-19 Vaccines. Front Public Health. 2021, 9, 647955. Available online: https://www.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/pmc/articles/PMC7930234/ (accessed on 30 September 2022). [CrossRef] [PubMed]
- Patrão Neves, M. Ethical implications of ‘Rationing’ vs ‘Rationalization’. Eubios J. Asian Int. Bioeth. 2020, 30, 134–135. [Google Scholar]
- Winkler, E. Rationalization, rationing, prioritization: Terminology and ethical approaches to the allocation of limited resources in hematology/oncology. Onkologie 2011, 34 (Suppl. 1), 2–5. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed] [Green Version]
- Patrão Neves, M. Ethical health resources allocation: Why the distinction between ‘rationing’ and ‘rationalization’ matters. Rev. Bio. y Der. 2020, 50, 63–79. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Beauchamp, T.; Childress, J. Principles of Biomedical Ethics, 6th ed.; Oxford University Press: New York, NY, USA; Oxford, UK, 2009. [Google Scholar]
- Callahan, D. Setting Limits: Medical Goals in an Aging Society; Simon and Schuster: New York, NY, USA, 1987. [Google Scholar]
- MacIntyre, A. The Right to Die Garrulously. In Death and Decision; Routledge: London, UK, 1978. [Google Scholar]
- Italian Society of Anesthesia Analgesia Reanimation and Intensive Care (SIAARTI, 2020), Recommendations of Clinical Ethics for Admission to Intensive Treatments and for Their Suspension, in exceptional Conditions of Imbalance between Needs and Available Resources. Available online: https://www.fundaciogrifols.org/documents/4662337/1023429220/Italia/a0d1573f-fa74-443d-b5e4-55ce78d08410 (accessed on 30 September 2022).
- Solomon, M.Z.; Wynia, M.K.; Gostin, L.O. Covid-19 Crisis Triage—Optimizing Health Outcomes and Disability Rights. N. Engl. J. Med. 2020. Available online: https://www.nejm.org/doi/full/10.1056/NEJMp2008300 (accessed on 30 September 2022). [CrossRef] [PubMed]
- Joebges, S.; Biller-Andorno, N. Ethics guidelines on COVID-19 triage—An emerging international consensus. Crit. Care 2020, 24, 20. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed]
- Vinay, R.; Baumann, H.; Biller-Andorno, N. Ethics of ICU triage during COVID-19. Br. Med. Bull. 2021, 138, 5–15. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed]
Ethical Requirements | Principles (Deontological Approach) | Ends (Teleological Approach) | Procedures (Procedural Approach) |
---|---|---|---|
Macro allocation | Social Justice and the different theories of Justice | Common Good and the evolution of its formulation | Integrity Transparency and their fine-tuning of principles and ends |
Different | Concepts | Consequences | Foundations | Guidelines |
---|---|---|---|---|
Rationing | Limitation of resources; focus on persons and their characteristics | Allocation of resources relies on a selection of criteria that fall on people; focus on a social evaluation of persons | Discriminates positively and negatively (criteria should be transparent, consensual, and fair); promotes equity, but may endanger human dignity | Applies to the distribution of non-vital scarce resources |
Rationalization | Optimization of resources; focus on resources and their performance | Allocation of resources adopts one single criterion, that of efficiency; focus on an efficiency assessment of resources | Does not discriminate (when complying with the duty of objectivity, accuracy, and transparency); promotes social justice and respects human dignity | Applies to the distribution of non-vital or vital scarce resources |
Age/Elderly | Ventilators (Vital) | Vaccines (Non-Vital) |
---|---|---|
Rationing | Rationing (requires prioritization/selection criteria) of ventilators adopted chronological age as a criterion. When there were no ventilators for everyone who needed them, health professionals started by excluding the older patients on behalf of the younger ones, progressively and according to ventilator availability Infringes Human Dignity and Social Justice | Rationing of the scarce vaccines available prioritized the chronologically oldest as they were the most vulnerable (regardless IL and QALY), and vaccination improved their resistance to infection Ethically sound (Human Dignity + Social Justice) |
Rationalization | Rationalization would have evaluated, among all patients in need of ventilation, those who were more likely to survive (saving lives), considering (not chronological age) their general state of health (including biological age) Ethically sound (Human Dignity + Social Justice) Rationalization would have adopted biological age as a criterion (saving lives); in addition, it could also have considered life years (IL) or quality-adjusted life years (QALY) saved Exchanges Human Dignity for Social Justice | Rationalization of the scarce vaccines available prioritized the biologically most vulnerable (regardless IL and QALY), and vaccination improved their resistance to infection Ethically sound (Human Dignity + Social Justice) |
Publisher’s Note: MDPI stays neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations. |
© 2022 by the author. Licensee MDPI, Basel, Switzerland. This article is an open access article distributed under the terms and conditions of the Creative Commons Attribution (CC BY) license (https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/).
Share and Cite
Patrão Neves, M.d.C. Criteria for Ethical Allocation of Scarce Healthcare Resources: Rationing vs. Rationalizing in the Treatment for the Elderly. Philosophies 2022, 7, 123. https://doi.org/10.3390/philosophies7060123
Patrão Neves MdC. Criteria for Ethical Allocation of Scarce Healthcare Resources: Rationing vs. Rationalizing in the Treatment for the Elderly. Philosophies. 2022; 7(6):123. https://doi.org/10.3390/philosophies7060123
Chicago/Turabian StylePatrão Neves, Maria do Céu. 2022. "Criteria for Ethical Allocation of Scarce Healthcare Resources: Rationing vs. Rationalizing in the Treatment for the Elderly" Philosophies 7, no. 6: 123. https://doi.org/10.3390/philosophies7060123
APA StylePatrão Neves, M. d. C. (2022). Criteria for Ethical Allocation of Scarce Healthcare Resources: Rationing vs. Rationalizing in the Treatment for the Elderly. Philosophies, 7(6), 123. https://doi.org/10.3390/philosophies7060123