Practical Nihilism
Abstract
:1.
2.
- GIRLS
- Sex is very dangerous—if I do it, I could die.
- I don’t want to die.
- I won’t have sex.
- BOYS
- Sex is very dangerous—if I do it, I might kill the woman I do it with.
- I don’t want to kill her.
- I won’t have sex.
3.
How do we justify a deduction? Plainly, by showing that it conforms to the general rules of deductive inference…[but on the other hand:]Principles of deductive inference are justified by their conformity with accepted deductive practice. Their validity depends upon accordance with the particular deductive inferences we actually make and sanction. If a rule yields unacceptable inferences, we drop it as invalid. Justification of general rules thus derives from judgments rejecting or accepting particular deductive inferences.17
4.
5.
6.
7.
8.
9.
10.
11.
Funding
Institutional Review Board Statement
Informed Consent Statement
Data Availability Statement
Acknowledgments
Conflicts of Interest
1 | The contrast here is with the hypothesis presented and defended as a matter of fact: roughly, the fact that there are no facts about what is valuable, what one should do, and so on. The position has recently come to be called ‘error theory,’ and is usually attributed to Mackie [1], but the thought is much older: David Hume held that, given what it takes for mental states to have contents, there could not be anything that counted as an argument that you ought to do something. Chapters 6–8 in [2] provides a reconstruction of Hume’s nihilism and his attempts, in his History of England, to provide a substitute, appropriate to political and moral contexts, for arguments proper about what to do. Refs. [3,4] are recent and typical entries in the error theory debates. |
2 | There is a long and insufficiently appreciated history of philosophers who have taken stands on extreme views as ways of putting on display much more nuanced positions. Just for instance, when Aristotle argued for the Principle of Noncontradiction, he took as his foil an opponent committed to affirming all contradictions; those who deny the Principle, and do so thoughtfully, insist that some, but not all, contradictions are true (Metaph. IV 3-6, K (XI), 5, 6 in [5]). Aristotle is not making the crude mistake of straw-manning his opponent, but rather exhibiting a problem his more moderate opponents have using the clearest, because most radical, case. Again for instance, Descartes develops an extreme form of skepticism, but not in order to convince you that there is no external world. Christine Korsgaard [6] provides a good example of the way dismissals of nihilism figure into arguments for other positions. Her paper constructs a classic two-front argument, one which positions instrumentalism between nihilism about practical reasons (the more minimal bracketing position) and more ambitious views about reasons (the more maximal bracketing position, which could be Kantian, or could be a richer notion of prudence). She invites you to agree that any argument for stepping up from nihilism to instrumentalism can be converted into an argument for taking one more step, from instrumentalism to a position that accepts categorical reasons; conversely, she argues that any reason an instrumentalist can deploy against a Kantian or self-interest theorist is matched by a reason a nihilist can deploy against an instrumentalist. The upshot—the standard conclusion of a two-front argument—is that the bracketed position is not sustainable: you can slide up, you can slide down, but you cannot stop in the middle, at instrumentalism. Korsgaard, however, takes this to be an argument for a more ambitious view; the reason is that she thinks that the more minimal position—nihilism—is already known to be, from the practical point of view, not an option. If, as I am about to argue, it is an option, Korsgaard’s argument is incomplete. |
3 | Ref. [7] exemplifies this way of thinking. There are, however, exceptions; e.g., ref. [8] argues against the view that instrumental rationality is a matter of taking the means to one’s ends, and also denies that reasons that turn on one thing’s being a means to another make up a distinct category of reasons, marked by a distinctive force. However, Raz is not by any means a nihilist; he thinks that we have a great many practical reasons, derived from facts about what is valuable. |
4 | Moreover, parts of the argument to come will turn on functional characterizations of our cognitive equipment; the intelligibility and the warrantedness of such characterizations surely both depend on our grasp of and competence with means-end reasoning. (I am grateful to Christoph Fehige for pressing me on the issue.) |
5 | Ref. [9] is a careful overview; outside of lying-in hospitals, during the nineteenth century, anyway in England, normal maternal mortality rates seemed to be in the ballpark of half to three-quarters of a percent per birth. (My 3–5% estimate multiplies that out by the larger parity, or family size, typical of earlier periods.) But sixteenth and seventeenth century rates seem to have been higher, on the order of one-and-a-quarter percent per birth (p. 159). As Loudon remarks, “Until the mid-1930s a majority of women in their childbearing years had personal knowledge of a member of her family, a friend, or a neighbor in a nearby street who had died in childbirth” (p. 164). See also pp. 396f (which reports on mortality rates in a religious community that refuses medical care), p. 198 for mortality rates for British lying-in hospitals prior to 1880, and p. 16 for a summary of mortality rates in England and Wales 1850–1980. |
6 | However, it does seem to me that the argument should make us skeptical about the effectiveness of safe-sex education campaigns; it was obvious, for the longest time, that unprotected sex could get someone killed, maybe you, and that did not stop precisely the human beings who ended up reproducing from having unprotected sex. |
7 | See [10] for a disconcerting sample, but not all the procedures were dangerous. Here is William Whewell [11] (vol. iii, p. 222), quoting Theophrastus on the procedures for gathering medicinal plants: “We are to draw a sword three times round the mandragora, and to cut it looking to the west: again, to dance round it, and to use obscene language, as they say those who sow cumin should utter blasphemies. Again, we are to draw a line round the black hellebore, standing to the east and praying; and to avoid an eagle either on the right or on the left; for say they, ‘if an eagle be near, the cutter will die in a year.’” |
8 | Here I am taking issue somewhat with [12], which is generally a valuable overview of the prehistory of modern medicine. Wootton agrees that “the real puzzle with regard to the history of medicine…is working out why medicine once passed for knowledge” (144), and “why doctors for centuries imagined that their therapies worked when they didn’t” (184). His explanations cover a range of no doubt contributing factors—“the way in which people identify with their own skills, particularly when they have gone to great trouble and expense to acquire them…the risk of pursuing new ideas” (251) “…the illusion of success, the placebo effect, the tendency to think of patients not diseases, the pressure to conform, the resistance to statistics” (149)—but miss what I am suggesting is likely to have been the element that allowed these factors to determine the outcome: that (like us) the physicians of the time simply did not care about means-end effectiveness, not enough to actually pay much attention to it, even when they were very concerned about the ends. |
9 | Even now, evidence-based medicine is still in its infancy, and, even now, trained physicians exhibit remarkable lapses. Just for instance, quite recently, injecting medical cement (polymethylmethacrylate or PMMA) into fractured bones was a widespread practice, but with no reliable research to back it up. When two carefully designed and unbiased studies showed it to be no better than placebo, trained spine surgeons were heard claiming at a professional conference—rather like participants in the sort of church service where one bears one’s testimony—that their personal experience showed the treatment had relieved the pain in patient after patient; in other words, their training in overriding cognitive illusions about effectiveness had not overridden their own cognitive illusions, and as ref. [13] (p. 38) observes, “despite the evidence, many specialists will not abandon the procedure.” (refs. [14,15]; ref. [16] is an editor’s retrospective, and ref. [17] is a larger followup study.) This procedure has since been in part replaced (in Europe, but not the US, where standards for demonstrating effectiveness are higher) by ‘coblation,’ a procedure that looks like a new-age fad rather than real medicine; its surprisingly high level of acceptance demonstrates once again how weak our instrumental reasoning abilities are. |
10 | Since the standard way of thinking in one wing of the practical-rationality literature has it that your means-end inferences are correct when the means chosen make sense given your beliefs about the expedients, there is a comparison that may help here. Suppose that I am very bad at adding and subtracting numbers between one and ten; for instance, I routinely add seven and five to get eleven (and perhaps, when you ask me, I tell you that seven plus five is eleven). Suppose that when it comes to larger numbers, I correctly execute the rules I was taught in grade school—“put down the 1 and carry the 1”—so that a sum like this one
The wing of the literature in question operates with a distinction between ‘motivating’ and ‘normative’ reasons inherited from [18]. So this is an occasion to question whether the distinction is well-motivated. Call the correct rules of arithmetic, the ones that should guide my calculations, my normative arithmetic reasons; we can imagine these systematized as a theory of normative arithmetic: perhaps what we were taught in grade school, or perhaps something fancier involving the Peano axioms. Call the mistaken views which I exhibit and that explain the digits I actually write down—in the example above, that —my motivating arithmetic reasons. It is obvious that there is no call for a theory of motivating arithmetic; that such a theory would not be part of mathematics; that such errors are not a special sort of arithmetic reason; and that anyone who went on to develop such a theory or an epistemological account of such reasons would be a crackpot. There is not a whole lot of difference between the crackpot enterprise and the somehow current notion that there are two sorts of reasons for action, the normative ones and the motivating ones, and that we need a theory of each. |
11 | I have found that a natural response is to start listing putatively effective activities. For instance, a correspondent tells me:
Leaving to one side the personal hygiene habits—these are due to public-health campaigns, and recall that modern medicine does investigate effectiveness relatively successfully—notice that the remainder of the entries have precisely the status of those premodern medical therapies: they are thought to be effective, and no one has really checked. It is irrelevant that someone thinks that he can list effective means without the requisite sort of verification: that I need to say more to convince people (that they go on believing that what they think is effective, is) is precisely the problem. |
12 | Now, in the medical domain, we have gotten good at counting successes and failures; perhaps we were helped out, at the beginning, by the ease with which the dead are counted. In most other domains, it is harder to count, and it is especially hard to estimate what proportion, weighted for importance, of our expedients are effective in these domains. We should not make the mistake of treating the difficulty as a rebuttal of the argument: where we can count, it turns out that we were ineffective (until we did start to count). And we were remarkably cocksure about our own effectiveness. It would be silly to suppose that the greater difficulty of counting warrants cocksureness elsewhere. |
13 | Returning briefly to a remark above, in order to find out what works, we need target states that we can specify clearly. Often we cannot specify the target states—for instance, we do not know how to measure education, mostly because we do not understand what it is. This obstacle is not our present topic, but it should not be underestimated. There is a smallish literature on the sort of thinking that takes us from underspecified ends to goals that are specified tightly enough to launch trains of means-end reasoning (see [19] for an overview), and there is another emerging literature on the pitfalls of metrics meant to serve as proxies for such targets [20,21]. However, these literatures do not examine the obstacles presented by loosely specified or hard-to-measure goals to determining how much there is in the way of instrumental reasoning. |
14 | But can’t I just lift a cup to my lips in order to drink? And is that not effective but unsupported means-end reasoning? When simple bodily actions are effective, you are not normally able to articulate the detailed calculative structure of the action; from your point of view, it just happens. That is because evolution (and we are not just talking recent primate evolution) has developed and debugged the machinery over many millions of years. Bear in mind that I am not claiming there is nothing we can do effectively; we ought to suppose otherwise, if only because cognitive scientists are in the business of finding tasks that some of their subjects can figure out how to perform. (‘Some,’ because a task that all subjects, or none of them, can execute does not generally give you a publishable result.) When natural selection has had long stretches of time to get the mechanics of locomotion, say, or some routine social problem down, we should not be all that surprised when the machinery works. What we are considering here, however, are more elaborate, less repetitive, often culturally inflected, relatively ephemeral, and therefore relatively novel problems that evolution has not had a chance to solve by trial and error. We should not think that being good at the former sort of task means that we will also be good at the latter. |
15 | Since I have been invoking natural selection, let me take time out to do some compare and contrast, in this case with [22], where Sharon Street attacks realism as a way of clearing space for (what she understands as) a reflective-equilibrium constructivism. In her view, there is no Darwinian explanation for sensitivity to the sort of nonnatural evaluative facts beloved of the Moorean tradition, but it is unreasonable to suggest that we are entirely unaware of what is good and what is not. While I agree with the observation about natural selection, from where I stand, realism and antirealism in metaethics are two sides of a debate over, to put it a bit bluntly, invisible glows. It is misguided to endorse either position—or even to think there are intelligible positions to endorse [23] (Chapters 5–6). What Street complacently pronounces to be the “implausible skeptical conclusion that our evaluative judgements are in all likelihood mostly off track” (122) seems to me not “far-fetched,” as she describes the claim a little later, but quite clearly the challenge facing anyone who takes ethics and moral theory seriously: they are wildly off-track, and the urgent question is what to do about it. Street does consider, under this heading, the possibility that “the tools of rational reflection [are]…contaminated”; she responds that “rational reflection about evaluative matters involves…assessing some evaluative judgements in terms of others…The widespread consensus that the method of reflective equilibrium, broadly understood, is our sole means of proceeding in ethics is an acknowledgement of this fact: ultimately, we can test our evaluative judgements only by testing their consistency with our other evaluative judgements, combined of course with judgments about the (non-evaluative) facts” (124). I do not belong to the alleged consensus; see [2] (pp. 7–10), for preliminary discussion of the shortcomings of reflective equilibrium; we will consider the method of reflective equilibrium in the coming section. Where Street wants to put to one side what she takes to be the unacceptable result that our evaluative reasoning is hopelessly corrupt, I am about to argue for it. Finally, Street’s focus is evaluation, primarily ethical or moral evaluation, rather than what the forms of legitimate practical inference are. |
16 | For an illustration, see the previous footnote. |
17 | Ref. [24] (pp. 63f), emphasis deleted. |
18 | I have had it suggested to me that the prevailing view is that reflective equilibrium is an explanation of the meaning of “valid inference rule.” While it is possible that Goodman is being misread in this way, first, I have never seen an argument for the claim so construed. Second, it would be a terrible theory of what “valid” means. And third, an appeal to such an understanding of the doctrine of reflective equilibrium would surely be an expression of the conviction, absolutely unbecoming in a philosopher, that it does not require any supporting argument. |
19 | |
20 | See especially [27], which nicely observes that in ‘calculative’ action, you take one step after the next, until you arrive at the ‘end’—i.e., the last step of the sequence. However, Vogler endorses the means-end interpretation of the structure: e.g., when asked why you are taking a step, you can adduce the ‘end,’ the termination point of the sequence, as a reason; and if you do, it counts as an objection if taking the step will not bring about the end. |
21 | Even when activity is instrumentally structured, in that earlier steps are chosen in view of the final end, the means-end or calculative structure of the activity can have various functions. Adopting such termination points can be a volitional prosthesis, for instance, a way of overcoming procrastination [29]. Ref. [30] argues that long-term plans are often not there to guide activity over the long term—they will most likely be abandoned mid-way, and a self-aware agent understands that—but to frame and support choices in the here-and-now. (The Bowman-Lelanuja Thesis is a corollary: when it is clear up front that your long-term plan will not be executed all the way to the end, realism about the effectiveness of the farther-out steps of the plan is beside the point [31] (p. 92f). This may be a partial justification for the evident lack of concern with whether what one does will achieve what one says it will.) In general, we should not assume, even when activity is composed of component actions directed towards an end, that the point of that instrumental structuring is attaining the end. |
22 | One might cynically imagine that the bureaucrats are generating institutional irrationality as a side effect of their personal and entirely effective instrumental reasoning: e.g., the bureaucrats’ goal is being visibly busy, and a faculty orientation serves that end. Having myself been in the sort of meetings that generate these activities, I can witness to such explanations being only rarely in place. |
23 | I am not going to pursue this line of argument now, but notice that there is every reason to believe that we are terrible at this as well, and here is some indirect evidence. Investment fund managers attempt to do better than the index for their market segment. They make their choices on the basis of causal arguments whose raw-effectiveness cores normally seem to make sense. I am told that being right about 60% of the time on a continuing basis is very, very good. So if the problem is not after all that they cannot be bothered to find effective means, they must generally be very bad at picking out the defeaters for those causal arguments. |
24 | |
25 | Ref. [34] is the properly published part of a samizdat text that raised such national security concerns (the original coauthor, Akio Morita, declined to authorize an English translation of his contribution). The observation that prompted public uproar was this:
|
26 | For exposition of the logic of this point see, e.g., [35] (esp. at p. 406). |
27 | In the version of protohuman agency I am dismissing, urgency levels fluctuate, and the task that gets addressed is the one that feels most urgent at the time. Now, it is not that you cannot find the hardware behaving this way sometimes, but when it does, performance is liable to be poor. To take an extreme example, drivers whose jeeps break down in the Sahara will end up drinking the vehicle fluids before they die; thirst becomes that urgent [36] (pp. 53, 149–152, 188). They do this even though the motor oil, battery fluid, radiator fluid and so on are not water, will not assuage their thirst, and will in various other ways poison them. This is the failure to invoke a relevant desirability characterization, which here would be something on the order of, “drinking is desirable as a means of hydration.” Instead, the priority assigned to drinking is increased as hydration levels fall, and eventually it becomes the top priority. Although this is an especially dramatic example, not all of them are; think of how students end up pulling all-nighters. In general, managing priorities this way is such a bad way of resolving the action sequencing problem that we cannot get by on it across the board: and so we don’t. This does not yet show that we do not use weights or strengths of desires to solve our scheduling problems in some more sophisticated way; but ref. [30] argues that the more sophisticated proposals succumb to a more complex relative of the problem at which I have been gesturing. |
28 | Ref. [37]; for a survey of older literature, see [38]. The phenomenon as I have just described it is familiar; this particular experiment was focused on the extent to which cognitive dissonance reduction happens in consciousness and depends on explicit memory; the results suggest, not particularly. The researchers are pushing back against the way of thinking on which we are observing reasoning conducted unawares, and suggesting that we should see cognitive dissonance reduction as merely a mechanism. And if we are as bad at instrumental reasoning as I have been suggesting, perhaps it had better be merely a mechanism: we could not manage the functionality if we had to figure out how to do it. |
29 | I am grateful to Madeleine Parkinson for pressing me on this point. |
30 | Full disclosure, I have been among those drawing that too-fast conclusion; see [42] (pp. 64–66, 175); so here I am disagreeing not only with Korsgaard but with my younger self. |
31 | When asking how bad we are at practical reasoning, it is natural to to wonder: compared with what? Here the obvious point of reference is the picture of the ideally rational agent since contested by the emerging bounded rationality literature. For readers interested in that contrast, a suitable representative, in the philosophical world, of the idealized view would be Donald Davidson [43] (Chapters 2–4), who argued that agents must be—as a condition of being interpretable—assumed to be very largely decision-theoretically coherent. For an entry point into the newer tradition, the psychological studies showing the idealized model to be untenable were launched by work collected in [44]—work that subsequently garnered a Nobel Prize for the surviving member of the collaboration. |
32 | You might think that we could make the checklists more easily searchable, by ordering them so that you find the most frequently encountered defeaters first. That will not do: as Taleb points out [45], defeaters that are so rare that we have not yet encountered them can also have impacts so devastating that we cannot afford to ignore them. It is in any case hard to believe that checklists are how defeasibility is managed. Oaksford and Chater point out that
|
33 | The problem is not merely an abstractly characterized but uninstanced possibility. I will give just one example (which however requires a slightly lengthy explanation). In order to improve the decisions made by institutional investors, the performance of fund managers is benchmarked. Investors want to be able to determine how much of the performance is attributable to a manager’s stock-picking skill, and how much to, e.g., sector allocation or risk assumption. So, almost inevitably, funds are confined to very tightly constrained classes of equities: say, small-cap growth stocks. (The fund’s performance can then be compared to the performance of other funds that are trying to do the very same thing.) The upshot is that a fund manager will be required to take positions that he understands to be against the interests of his investors: for instance, by selling a small-cap firm that is now doing so well it no longer counts as small-cap; or by buying stocks in a sector he expects to do badly, with the intention, not of making money for his clients, but of outpeforming a downward-trending index, or of not exceeding a limit on cash holdings. The cognitive exoskeleton does what it is supposed to, but produces perverse behavior over a large part of the market. |
34 | As Taleb discovered [48], exploring a closely related topic, we are so little used to thinking this way that he had to invent a word for the contrary of “fragility”. However, although the topics are related, they are not quite the same: he is interested, among other things, in learning from mistakes in ways that permit better decision-making down the road, while I am focused on the sorts of case where you are not going to learn from your mistakes in any way that will enable better decisions later. See, e.g., p. 192, where Taleb observes that to learn from your mistakes, you have “to be intelligent in recognizing favorable and unfavorable outcomes, and knowing what to discard”; but we may well not be that intelligent. |
35 | A nihilist might think that the problem is not just that we are bad at instrumental rationality, but that we are no good at figuring out what matters, even with these sorts of prompts. If the latter but not the former were correct, then effectiveness itself might turn out to be the problem: if you persistently choose the wrong goals, the better you are at pursuing them, the worse off you are. In an amusing series of asides, refs. [49] (p. 14) and [50] (pp. 44, 66f) recommend a “Bureau of Sabotage,” and suggest that “eternal sloppiness [i]s the price of liberty.” |
References
- Mackie, J.L. Ethics: Inventing Right and Wrong; Penguin: New York, NY, USA, 1977. [Google Scholar]
- Millgram, E. Ethics Done Right: Practical Reasoning as a Foundation for Moral Theory; Cambridge University Press: Cambridge, UK, 2005. [Google Scholar]
- Olson, J. In Defence of Moral Error Theory. In New Waves in Metaethics; Brady, M., Ed.; Palgrave Macmillan: New York, NY, USA, 2011; pp. 62–84. [Google Scholar]
- Streumer, B. Can We Believe the Error Theory? J. Philos. 2013, 110, 194–212. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Aristotle. Complete Works; Barnes, J., Ed.; Princeton University Press: Princeton, NJ, USA, 1984. [Google Scholar]
- Korsgaard, C.M. Skepticism about Practical Reason. In Varieties of Practical Reasoning; Millgram, E., Ed.; MIT Press: Cambridge, MA, USA, 2001; pp. 103–125. [Google Scholar]
- Dreier, J. Humean Doubts about Categorical Imperatives. In Varieties of Practical Reasoning; Millgram, E., Ed.; MIT Press: Cambridge, MA, USA, 2001; pp. 27–47. [Google Scholar]
- Raz, J. The Myth of Instrumental Rationality. J. Ethics Soc. Philos. 2005, 1, 2–28. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Loudon, I. Death in Childbirth: An International Study of Maternal Care and Maternal Mortality 1800–1950; Oxford University Press: Oxford, UK, 1992. [Google Scholar]
- Duden, B. The Woman Beneath the Skin; Dunlap, T., Translator; Harvard University Press: Cambridge, MA, USA, 1991. [Google Scholar]
- Whewell, W. History of the Inductive Sciences, 3rd ed.; John W. Parker and Son: London, UK, 1857. [Google Scholar]
- Wootton, D. Bad Medicine; Oxford University Press: Oxford, UK, 2007. [Google Scholar]
- Prasad, V.; Cifu, A.; Ioannidis, J. Reversals of Established Medical Practices: Evidence to Abandon Ship. J. Am. Med. Assoc. 2012, 307, 37–38. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed]
- Buchbinder, R.; Osborne, R.; Ebeling, P.R.; Wark, J.D.; Mitchell, P.; Wriedt, C.; Graves, S.; Staples, M.P.; Murphy, B. A Randomized Trial of Vertebroplasty for Painful Osteoporotic Vertebral Fractures. N. Engl. J. Med. 2009, 361, 557–568. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed] [Green Version]
- Buchbinder, R.; Kallmes, D. Vertebroplasty: When Randomized Placebo-Controlled Trial Results Clash with Common Belief. Spine J. 2010, 10, 241–243. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed]
- Carragee, E. The Vertebroplasty Affair: The Mysterious Case of the Disappearing Effect Size. Spine J. 2010, 10, 191–192. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed]
- Firanescu, C.E.; de Vries, J.; Lodder, P.; Venmans, A.; Schoemaker, M.C.; Smeet, A.J.; Donga, E.; Juttmann, J.R.; Klazen, C.A.H.; Elgersma, O.E.H.; et al. Vertebroplasty versus Sham Procedure for Painful Acute Osteoporotic Vertebral Compression Fractures (VERTOS IV): Randomised Sham Controlled Clinical Trial. BMJ 2018, 361. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed] [Green Version]
- Smith, M. The Humean Theory of Motivation. Mind 1987, 96, 36–61. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Millgram, E. Specificationism. In Reasoning: Studies of Human Inference and its Foundations; Adler, J., Rips, L., Eds.; Cambridge University Press: Cambridge, UK, 2008; pp. 731–747. [Google Scholar]
- Scott, J. Seeing Like a State; Yale University Press: New Haven, CT, USA, 1998. [Google Scholar]
- Porter, T. Trust in Numbers; Princeton University Press: Princeton, NJ, USA, 1995. [Google Scholar]
- Street, S. A Darwinian Dilemma for Realist Theories of Value. Philos. Stud. 2006, 127, 109–166. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Millgram, E. The Great Endarkenment; Oxford University Press: Oxford, UK, 2015. [Google Scholar]
- Goodman, N. Fact, Fiction, and Forecast, 4th ed.; Foreword by Hilary Putnam; Harvard University Press: Cambridge, MA, USA, 1983. [Google Scholar]
- Nietzsche, F. Basic Writings of Nietzsche; Modern Library/Random House: New York, NY, USA, 2000. [Google Scholar]
- Foucault, M. Madness and Civilization: A History of Insanity in the Age of Reason; Howard, R., Translator; Random House: New York, NY, USA, 1988. [Google Scholar]
- Vogler, C. Reasonably Vicious; Harvard University Press: Cambridge, MA, USA, 2002. [Google Scholar]
- McLuhan, M. The Gutenberg Galaxy; University of Toronto Press: Toronto, ON, Canada, 1966. [Google Scholar]
- Millgram, E. Virtue for Procrastinators. In The Thief of Time; Andreou, C., White, M., Eds.; Oxford University Press: New York, NY, USA, 2010; pp. 151–164. [Google Scholar]
- Bowman, M. Are Our Goals Really What We’re After? Ph.D. Thesis, University of Utah, Salt Lake City, UT, USA, 2012. [Google Scholar]
- Millgram, E. Pluralism about Action. In A Companion to the Philosophy of Action; O’Connor, T., Sandis, C., Eds.; Wiley-Blackwell: Oxford, UK, 2010; pp. 90–96. [Google Scholar]
- Cicerone, R.J.; Stedman, D.H.; Stolarski, R.S.; Dingle, A.N.; Cellarius, R.A. Assessment of Possible Environment Effects of Space Shuttle Operations; Technical Report; NASA Contractor Report CR-129003; University of Michigan: Ann Arbor, MI, USA, 1973. [Google Scholar]
- Ross, M.; Toohey, D.; Peinemann, M.; Ross, P. Limits on the Space Launch Market Related to Stratospheric Ozone Depletion. Astropolitics 2009, 7, 50–82. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
- Ishihara, S. The Japan That Can Say No; Baldwin, F., Translator; Simon and Schuster: New York, NY, USA, 1989. [Google Scholar]
- Tooby, J.; Cosmides, L. The Past Explains the Present: Emotional Adaptations and the Structure of Ancestral Environments. Ethol. Sociobiol. 1990, 11, 375–424. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Langewiesche, W. Sahara Unveiled; Pantheon: New York, NY, USA, 1996. [Google Scholar]
- Lieberman, M.; Ochsner, K.; Gilbert, D.; Schacter, D. Do Amnesics Exhibit Cognitive Dissonance Reduction? The Role of Explicit Memory and Attention in Attitude Change. Psychol. Sci. 2001, 12, 135–140. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed]
- Cooper, J. Cognitive Dissonance: Fifty Years of a Classic Theory; Sage Publications: London, UK, 2007. [Google Scholar]
- Griffiths, P. What Emotions Really Are; University of Chicago Press: Chicago, IL, USA, 1997. [Google Scholar]
- Dewey, J. Theory of Valuation. In John Dewey: The Later Works, 1925–1953; Boydston, J.A., Levine, B., Eds.; Southern Illinois University Press: Carbondale, IL, USA, 1981; Volume 13, pp. 191–251. [Google Scholar]
- Korsgaard, C.M. The Sources of Normativity; Cambridge University Press: Cambridge, UK, 1996. [Google Scholar]
- Millgram, E. Practical Induction; Harvard University Press: Cambridge, MA, USA, 1997. [Google Scholar]
- Davidson, D. Problems of Rationality; Clarendon Press: Oxford, UK, 2004. [Google Scholar]
- Kahneman, D.; Slovic, P.; Tversky, A. Judgment under Uncertainty: Heuristics and Biases; Cambridge University Press: Cambridge, UK, 1982. [Google Scholar]
- Taleb, N. The Black Swan, 2nd ed.; Random House: New York, NY, USA, 2010. [Google Scholar]
- Oaksford, M.; Chater, N. Rationality in an Uncertain World; Routledge: London, UK, 1998. [Google Scholar]
- Verhovek, S.H. Jet Age; Penguin: New York, NY, USA, 2011. [Google Scholar]
- Taleb, N. Antifragile: Things That Gain from Disorder; Random House: New York, NY, USA, 2012. [Google Scholar]
- Herbert, F. Whipping Star; Berkley Publishing: New York, NY, USA, 1971. [Google Scholar]
- Herbert, F. The Dosadi Experiment; Berkley Publishing: New York, NY, USA, 1977. [Google Scholar]
Disclaimer/Publisher’s Note: The statements, opinions and data contained in all publications are solely those of the individual author(s) and contributor(s) and not of MDPI and/or the editor(s). MDPI and/or the editor(s) disclaim responsibility for any injury to people or property resulting from any ideas, methods, instructions or products referred to in the content. |
© 2022 by the author. Licensee MDPI, Basel, Switzerland. This article is an open access article distributed under the terms and conditions of the Creative Commons Attribution (CC BY) license (https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/).
Share and Cite
Millgram, E. Practical Nihilism. Philosophies 2023, 8, 2. https://doi.org/10.3390/philosophies8010002
Millgram E. Practical Nihilism. Philosophies. 2023; 8(1):2. https://doi.org/10.3390/philosophies8010002
Chicago/Turabian StyleMillgram, Elijah. 2023. "Practical Nihilism" Philosophies 8, no. 1: 2. https://doi.org/10.3390/philosophies8010002
APA StyleMillgram, E. (2023). Practical Nihilism. Philosophies, 8(1), 2. https://doi.org/10.3390/philosophies8010002