Harry Potter and the Philosopher’s Table
Abstract
:1. Fictional Creationism and Intentional Creation
- (1)
- Harry Potter is a fictional character.
- (2)
- Harry Potter is a distinct fictional character from Hermione Granger.
- (3)
- Harry Potter was created by acts involving literary practice.
- (4)
- There are many fictional characters less famous than Harry Potter.
When and How: When and how does a fictional object come into existence?
Intentional Creation: A new distinct fictional object o is intentionally created by an author S, if and only if (or whenever) S has an appropriate intention to create the new fictional object o that is distinct from other fictional objects, and as a causal consequence of that intention, S pretends to believe a singular proposition about o.6
2. Artifacts That Come into Existence without Successful Creative Intentions
Nominalist Rowling: J. K. Rowling is an amateur philosopher. She is a nominalist and thus faithfully believes that abstract entities of any kind do not exist. When she writes the Harry Potter series, she believes writing her stories will not produce any fictional objects and does not intend to create any fictional objects. But many people start reading Rowling’s book and then talk about Harry Potter and Hermione Granger.
Nihilist van Inwagen: Peter van Inwagen is a mereological nihilist and thus faithfully believes that there are no tables but merely simples arranged tablewise (van Inwagen [25]). When he carves wood in his garage, he does not intend to make a table; he is simply trying to arrange simples tablewise. However, when his neighbors see van Inwagen’s wood carving, they come to believe that a table comes into existence.
Swamp Book: Particles of swamp gas coalesce and form an object that is intrinsically identical to a copy of the book Harry Potter and the Philosopher’s Stone in our actual world. Many people start reading this book and then talk about Harry Potter and Hermione Granger.Swamp Table: Particles of swamp gas coalesce and form an object that is intrinsically identical to the table in my kitchen. People who witness this incredible process come to believe that a table comes into existence.
Inadvertently Created Potter: When J.K. Rowling wrote the Harry Potter series, she was under the mistaken impression that the protagonist, Harry Potter, was a real person. Introducing the name “Harry Potter”, Rowling intended to refer to a famous English entertainer she thought existed quite independently of her novel. Readers, who read her book and are aware that Harry Potter is not a real person, start to talk about Harry Potter as a fictional character.10Inadvertently Created Table: Joy intends to make a piano bench. But due to her clumsy carpentry skills, the result comes out an ordinary table-shaped object. Her friends say that Joy has inadvertently created a table, and Joy agrees with them.
3. Communal Belief and Function
Communal Belief and Function: (When there is no one who intentionally creates an object o as an artifact kind K), if one’s actual belief that o belongs to a K is (or is disposed to be) rigidly accepted by a relevant community, and o has a K-function (or o already functions as a K), then o exists as a K.13
4. How to Bring Fictional Objects into Existence without Creative Intentions
- (5)
- Vulcan is a mythical planet.
- (6)
- Vulcan is a distinct mythical planet from Phaeton.
- (7)
- Nappy is an imaginary emperor.
- (8)
- Nappy is a distinct imaginary emperor from Mappy.
Creation of Mythical Objects: A mythical object o is inadvertently created by a subject S, if (or when) S mistakenly believes that there is such an object as o and tries to entertain a singular proposition about o.Creation of Imaginary Objects: An imaginary object o is created by a subject S, if (or when) S propositionally imagines a singular proposition about o.
5. Concluding Remarks
Funding
Institutional Review Board Statement
Informed Consent Statement
Data Availability Statement
Acknowledgments
Conflicts of Interest
1 | |
2 | In this paper, in line with many creationists, I will assume referentialism about names. |
3 | The usual strategy of creationists to solve the problem of fictional negative existentials is that in most cases where speakers utter “Harry Potter does not exist”, the proposition that Harry Potter does not exist as a real person is conveyed either semantically or pragmatically. See, e.g., Van Inwagen [1] (p. 308 n.11); Thomasson [4] (pp. 112–113); Predelli [10] (pp. 272–277); von Solodkoff [11]; Salmon [3] (pp. 302–303). See also Braun [5] for the gappy proposition approach to fictional negative existentials. |
4 | Everett [12,13] famously criticizes fictional realism for being committed to ontic indeterminacy. In response, Schnieder & von Solodkoff [14] suggest a default metaphysical assumption to avoid ontic indeterminacy; Thomasson [15], Cameron [16], and Woodward [17] argue that Everett’s case leads only to harmless semantic indeterminacy; Lee [9] argues that the intention-based approach to fictional objects does not lead to ontic indeterminacy. For criticism of Schnieder & von Solodkoff, see Everett [13] (ch. 8.2) and Caplan & Muller [18]; for criticism of Thomasson, see Everett [13] (ch. 8.3); for criticism of Cameron and Woodward, see Cohen [19], Friedell [20], and Yum [21]. |
5 | I think that an adequate answer to When and How will also shed some light on the identity conditions of fictional objects. But, I will not discuss this issue here due to the scope of this paper. |
6 | |
7 | Strictly speaking, the fictional character named “Harry Potter” in the Swamp Book scenario is numerically different from Harry Potter in the actual world, if fictional objects are individuated by their origin. (The same goes for the Nominalist Rowling scenario as well). For simplicity, I will ignore the ambiguity between our use of the name “Harry Potter” and the use of “Harry Potter” by the inhabitants of the Swamp Book world. |
8 | Thomasson [4] (p. 142) and Friedell [23] (p. 294) would claim that in Swamp Book, no literary work or fictional character comes into existence. For example, Friedell says, “Imagine Rowling, solely for the fun of it, arbitrarily punches keys on a computer. Like the proverbial Shakespeare-typing monkeys, she coincidentally types a string of symbols that corresponds to what (in our world) are the words of the Harry Potter novels. Intuitively, Rowling produces no novels or characters. She produces tokens of symbols that an observer (unaware of her arbitrary process) might naturally mistake for a copy of a novel that contains characters”. It may be true that in the above case, no character is created right after Rowling punches keys on a computer. But, as I have argued, it seems ad hoc to claim that even after ordinary speakers’ uses of “Harry Potter” become widespread, and thus they use external metafictional sentences such as (1)–(4) in almost exactly the same way as we do, every ordinary speaker, including literary critics, is mistaken in thinking that there is a fictional character Harry Potter only because there is no author. Of course, Thomasson and Friedell might be able to develop a non-ad hoc error theoretic explanation for this intuition. But, other things being equal, the theory that straightforwardly explains our intuitions should be preferred. I will explain in detail how Harry Potter comes into existence in the Swamp Book scenario in Section 4. |
9 | Philosophers who believe that concrete artifacts are necessarily intention-dependent, such as Thomasson [26] (p. 53) and Baker [27] (p. 99), would claim that there is no table in the Swamp Table scenario. Juvshik [28] (pp. 9324–9325) has recently suggested an error-theoretic explanation for why we have the ordinary intuition that there exists a table in Swamp Table. According to Juvshik, it is in fact a case of tacit or potential appropriation: we are conflating the potential use of such an object with its being an artifact. I sympathize with Juvshik’s idea behind this, but do not fully agree with his explanation. (I will explain why in detail in Section 3). At this point, however, it is important to notice that I am not invoking those scenarios to defend the mind-independence view of concrete artifacts. Nor am I claiming that there would be no plausible error theoretic explanation for proponents of the intention-dependence view of concrete artifacts. The only thing I am claiming here is simply that there are at least ordinary intuitions that we should explain, and again, all other things being equal, the theory that straightforwardly explains our intuitions should be preferred. |
10 | This scenario originally comes from Zvolenszky [29] (p. 319), who argues that a fictional character can be inadvertently created without an author’s creative intention. In her original scenario, Tolstoy was under the mistaken impression that the protagonist, Prince Bolkonsky was a real person. I have modified her example into one about Rowling and Harry Potter. |
11 | Friedell [23] (p. 294) claims that Harry Potter in this case is not a fictional character but a mythical object. Here, Friedell seems to think that the category of a mythical object and that of a fictional object are mutually exclusive, but I do not see why. As I have argued elsewhere (Lee [9], p. 395), if an object is categorized as a mythical object because it was inadvertently created, while an object is categorized as a fictional object because its nature is to be depicted such-and-such in fiction, there seems to be no inconsistency to say that Harry Potter is both a mythical and a fictional object in this case. I will discuss this issue in detail in Section 4. |
12 | I do not deny that there are many other cases where an object is used as an artifact kind K, even though it is not a K (cf. Evnine [30] (p. 415), [31] (p. 86, pp. 132–133); Cray [32] (p. 290); Friedell [23] (p. 293); Goodman [33] (p. 4)). But my point here is simply that we have the ordinary intuition that a new table is inadvertently created, at least in the Inadvertently Created Table scenario. |
13 | I assume in this paper that most artifact kinds have their own functions in order to simplify the discussion. A table, for example, has a table-function: it can be used to put things down, to eat, to write, to work, and so on. Of course, this assumption does not imply that table is essentially a functional kind. |
14 | Here, I assume that Joy’s friends consist of a relevant community in this context. |
15 | For our purposes, I dramatize the historical example. The true story is that Alfred Fielding and Marc Chavannes, the actual inventors of Bubble Wrap, in fact realized that their product could be used as a packaging material after their attempts to sell it as a wall covering were unsuccessful. (I thank Yoorim In for bringing this example to my attention.) |
16 | There would be a complicated case in which, even if a communal belief that o belongs to a K is not overridden by a maker’s intention, the maker remains stubborn and continues to believe and claim that o belongs to a K’. In such a case, it is difficult to answer whether the maker’s belief is overridden by the community. However, even if the belief is not overridden, there is no problem with CBF accepting that o belongs to both a K and a K’ in this case. (I thank Hwan Sunwoo for the helpful discussion on this issue.) |
17 | To avoid a controversial case, let us further assume that the creator of o intentionally created a computer-shaped prop, but later mistakenly comes to believe that o is a real computer, so that everyone, including the creator, rigidly believes that o is a computer. |
18 | Note that even if a rigid communal belief is not overridden by a maker’s intention and belief, this does not mean that this communal belief is always retained in the presence of any counter-evidence. If they encounter evidence that o is not a computer but a computer-shaped prop, such as the examination of its internal structure, they will recant their belief. |
19 | |
20 | Juvshik [36] (pp. 559–560) also provides a similar criticism against the functionalist view. |
21 | Goodman [33] (pp. 7–8) seems to bite the bullet and accept this consequence to some extent. |
22 | I assume that in a normal situation, when we see an ordinary piano bench, we do not usually believe that it is a table. In what cases, then, do we usually believe that o belongs to an artifact kind K? Perhaps when properties that a K usually has are salient to us: we might believe that o is a table because the table-function that o has is very salient to us, because o has a similar shape to tables we have seen so far, etc. |
23 | There is a related interesting question as to whether a new table still comes into existence in Swamp Table case even if there is nobody around to believe that a table comes into existence. Our intuition does not seem clear in this case, and although CBF does not commit to any particular answer, I would like to briefly mention two possible views in which I have no preference: First, if we want to say that a new table comes existence even if nobody believes it to be a table, then we should admit that there would be many more tables than we expect, though perhaps not too many. We could additionally include only objects in the domain of a table that have salient table-properties, which would make us immediately believe them to be tables when we encounter them. Second, if we want to say that no table comes into existence, then we should explain away our remaining counterintuition: perhaps we are conflating the potential belief we will have when we encounter that table-shaped object with its being a table. (I thank an anonymous reviewer and Wooram Lee for suggesting that I consider this issue). |
24 | There are in fact some complications here. If Tso is a concrete composite object, but not essentially a table, then when a table comes into existence by a rigid communal belief, we would need a new name, say “Tab”, for a table. Then, Tso and Tab would not be one and the same object because they have different modal properties. By contrast, if table is a phase sortal as phasalists maintain, then we would have only one and the same object, Tso, which is passing through a temporary phase table. For simplicity, however, I will disregard these complications. |
25 | For the sake of argument, I assume that table is an artifact kind, so all tables are artifacts. But if it is trivially true that artifacts must be the products of successful creative intentions (which I disagree with), then my view would be that some tables are not artifacts, while table is still not a purely functional kind (and CBF must be modified as well). For the present purpose, however, I will not discuss this issue further and simply assume that table is an artifact kind. |
26 | |
27 | Juvshik [36] (pp. 561–567) has recently suggested that communal acceptance is arguably sufficient for appropriation. However, his view differs significantly from mine in two aspects: First, according to Juvshik, some act or attempt is still necessary for appropriation, whereas in my view it is not. Second, Juvshik’s concept of communal acceptance for appropriation requires knowing that the artifact is of a particular kind and intending that it be a member of a different artifact kind, whereas my concept of rigid communal belief does not require this kind of knowledge and intention. |
28 | |
29 | |
30 | It is commonly assumed that a mythical object is an abstract object inadvertently created by a person’s mistaken theorizing (See, e.g., Salmon [3,40]; Braun [5,41]; Kripke [7]; Zvolenszky [29]; Lundgren [42]). However, I believe that the idea of a mythical object can be uniformly applied to a mistaken belief in general, and so in this paper I will define a mythical object in terms of a mistaken belief for the sake of argument. (cf. Voltolini [43]: He distinguishes two kinds of mythical objects: legendary objects like Zeus and post-empirical posits like Vulcan). |
31 | In this paper, I will use the term “imagination” only in the sense of propositional imagination, not in the sense of mental imagery. |
32 | Cf. Caplan [44]: He plausibly argues that parallel arguments can be made for mythical creationism and imaginary creationism, similar to the argument for fictional creationism, thereby forcing fictional creationists to accept both. In this paper, I assume, for the sake of argument, that this reasoning is plausible; however, it is not without controversy, as Kroon [45] criticizes fictional creationism by arguing that the possibility of generalizing the argument for fictional objects to imaginary objects threatens the plausibility of fictional creationism. (See also Goodman [46,47] for criticism of mythical creationism and Zvolenszky [29]; Lundgren [42]; Voltolini [43] for responses and discussion.) |
33 | It seems reasonable to me to say that in the Nominalist Rowling and Inadvertently Created Potter scenarios, Harry Potter is also an imaginary object, because when we read the book, we as readers propositionally imagine singular propositions about the wizard named “Harry Potter.” However, there seems to be no problem in categorizing one object as both a mythical object and an imaginary object at the same time; they are not mutually exclusive categories. |
34 | Cf. Juvshik [36] (p. 555): He points out that according to the Platonic view of musical works, literature, and film, abstract objects can be treated in the same manner as the appropriation cases: an agent appropriates a pre-existing object, such as a piece of driftwood or an abstract type of sound sequence, as a new artifact, such as a wine rack or a piece of music, respectively. |
35 | There are indeed similar complications here, as mentioned in n.24. If new fictional objects are genuinely created by a communal belief, then it follows that the mythical object named “Harry Potter” and the fictional object named “Harry Potter” would not be one and the same object if they have different modal properties and different existence and persistence conditions. By contrast, if fictional object is a phase sortal which an abstract object can pass through, then there would be only one abstract object named “Harry Potter”. But I will discuss this in detail at another time. (I thank Yoorim In for pointing this out.) |
36 | Note that since CBF only provides a sufficient condition for the existence of artifacts, I do not exclude other possible ways, besides communal belief, in which fictional objects come into existence without successful creative intentions. In any case, the point is that IC combined with CBF explains all the relevant data we have so far. So, although I guess that fictional creationists now have a complete answer to Brock’s When and How question, I would like to be careful about asserting it (I thank an anonymous reviewer for suggesting that I consider this issue). |
References
- Van Inwagen, P. Creature of Fiction. Am. Philos. Q. 1977, 14, 299–308. [Google Scholar]
- Searle, J. The Logical Status of Fictional Discourse. In Expression and Meaning; Cambridge: New York, NY, USA, 1979; pp. 58–75. [Google Scholar]
- Salmon, N. Nonexistence. Noûs 1998, 32, 277–319. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Thomasson, A. Fiction and Metaphysics; Cambridge University: Cambridge, UK, 1999. [Google Scholar]
- Braun, D. Empty Names, Fictional Names, Mythical Names. Noûs 2005, 39, 596–631. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Voltolini, A. How Ficta Follow Fiction: A Syncretistic Account of Fictional Entities; Springer: Dordrecht, The Netherlands, 2006. [Google Scholar]
- Kripke, S. Reference and Existence; Oxford University Press: Oxford, UK, 2013. [Google Scholar]
- Friedell, D. Abstract Creationism and Authorial Intention. J. Aesthet. Art Crit. 2016, 74, 129–137. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Lee, J. Authorial Intention, Readers Creation, and Reference Shift. Philos. Q. 2022, 72, 381–401. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Predelli, S. ‘Holmes’ and Holmes—A Millian Analysis of Names and Fiction. Dialectica 2002, 56, 261–279. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Von Solodkoff, T. Fictional Realism and Negative Existentials. In Empty Representations: Reference and Non-Existence; Manuel Garcia-Carpintero, M., Marti, G., Eds.; Oxford University Press: Oxford, UK, 2014; pp. 333–352. [Google Scholar]
- Everett, A. Against Fictional Realism. J. Philos. 2005, 102, 624–649. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Everett, A. The Nonexistent; Oxford University Press: Oxford, UK, 2013. [Google Scholar]
- Schnieder, B.; von Solodkoff, T. In Defence of Fictional Realism. Philos. Q. 2009, 59, 138–149. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Thomasson, A. Fiction, Existence and Indeterminacy. In Fictions and Models: New Essays; Woods, J., Ed.; Philosophia: Munich, Germany, 2011; pp. 109–148. [Google Scholar]
- Cameron, R. How to be a Nominalist and a Fictional Realist. In Art and Abstract Objects; Uidhir, C.M., Ed.; Oxford University Press: Oxford, UK, 2013; pp. 179–196. [Google Scholar]
- Woodward, R. Identity in Fiction. Philos. Phenomenol. Res. 2017, 94, 646–671. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Caplan, B.; Muller, C. Against a Defense of Fictional Realism. Philos. Q. 2014, 64, 211–224. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Cohen, W. Fictional Realism and Metaphysically Indeterminate Identity. Analysis 2017, 77, 511–519. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Friedell, D. Fiction and Indeterminate Identity. Analysis 2020, 80, 221–229. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Yum, I. Against the Precisificational Approach to Fictional Inconsistencies. Ergo 2023, 9, 1766–1783. [Google Scholar]
- Brock, S. The Creationist Fiction: The Case against Creationism about Fictional Characters. Philos. Rev. 2010, 119, 337–364. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Friedell, D. Abstract and Concrete Products: A Response to Cray. J. Aesthet. Art Crit. 2017, 75, 292–296. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Friedell, D. A Problem for All of Creation. J. Aesthet. Art Crit. 2018, 76, 98–101. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Van Inwagen, P. Material Beings; Cornell University Press: Ithaca, NY, USA, 1990. [Google Scholar]
- Thomasson, A. Artifacts and Human Concepts. In Creations of the Mind: Essays on Artifacts and Their Representations; Lauren, S., Margolis, E., Eds.; Oxford University Press: Oxford, UK, 2007; pp. 52–73. [Google Scholar]
- Baker, L.R. The Ontology of Artifacts. Philos. Explor. 2004, 7, 99–112. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Juvshik, T. Artifacts and Mind-Dependence. Synthese 2021, 199, 9313–9336. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Zvolenszky, Z. Fictional Characters, Mythical Objects, and the Phenomenon of Inadvertent Creation. Res. Philos. 2016, 91, 311–333. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Evnine, S. Ready-mades: Ontology and Aesthetics. Br. J. Aesthet. 2013, 53, 407–423. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
- Evnine, S. Making Objects and Events: A Hylomorphic Theory of Artifacts, Actions, and Organisms; Oxford University Press: Oxford, UK, 2016. [Google Scholar]
- Cray, W. Abstract Generationism: A Response to Friedell. J. Aesthet. Art Crit. 2017, 75, 289–292. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Goodman, J. On Inadvertently Made Tables: A Brockean Theory of Concrete Artifacts. Acta Anal. 2021, 36, 1–9. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Mag Uidhir, C. Art and Art-Attempts; Oxford University Press: Oxford, UK, 2013. [Google Scholar]
- Brock, S. A Recalcitrant Problem for Abstract Creationism. J. Aesthet. Art Crit. 2018, 76, 93–98. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Juvshik, T. Artifactualization without Physical Modification. Res. Philos. 2021, 98, 545–572. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Baker, L.R. The Metaphysics of Everyday Life; Cambridge University Press: Cambridge, UK, 2007. [Google Scholar]
- Koslicki, K. Form, Matter, Substance; Oxford University Press: Oxford, UK, 2018. [Google Scholar]
- Hick, D.H. Using Things as Art. Grazer Philos. Stud. 2019, 96, 56–80. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Salmon, N. Mythical Object. In Meaning and Truth: Investigations in Philosophical Semantics; Campbell, J.K., O’Rourke, M., Shier, D., Eds.; Oxford University Press: Oxford, UK, 2002; pp. 91–107. [Google Scholar]
- Braun, D. Hob, Nob, and Mythical Witches. In Reference and Referring; Kabasenche, W.P., O’Rourke, M., Slater, M.H., Eds.; MIT Press: Cambridge, MA, USA, 2012; pp. 149–187. [Google Scholar]
- Lundgren, B. Mistake Is to Myth What Pretense Is to Fiction: A Reply to Goodman. Philosophia 2017, 45, 1275–1282. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed] [Green Version]
- Voltolini, A. Against Mythical Backward-looking Creationism. Inquiry 2023, 6, 1016–1035. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Caplan, B. Creature of Fiction, Myth, and Imagination. Am. Philos. Q. 2004, 41, 331–337. [Google Scholar]
- Kroon, F. The Fiction of Creation. In Truth in Fiction; Lihoreau, F., Ed.; Ontos Verlag: Heusenstamm, Germany, 2011; pp. 203–221. [Google Scholar]
- Goodman, J. Creatures of Fiction, Objects of Myth. Analysis 2014, 74, 35–40. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Goodman, J. On Inadvertently Created Abstracta, Fictional Storytelling, and Scientific Hypothesizing. Res. Philos. 2017, 94, 177–188. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
Disclaimer/Publisher’s Note: The statements, opinions and data contained in all publications are solely those of the individual author(s) and contributor(s) and not of MDPI and/or the editor(s). MDPI and/or the editor(s) disclaim responsibility for any injury to people or property resulting from any ideas, methods, instructions or products referred to in the content. |
© 2023 by the author. Licensee MDPI, Basel, Switzerland. This article is an open access article distributed under the terms and conditions of the Creative Commons Attribution (CC BY) license (https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/).
Share and Cite
Lee, J. Harry Potter and the Philosopher’s Table. Philosophies 2023, 8, 67. https://doi.org/10.3390/philosophies8040067
Lee J. Harry Potter and the Philosopher’s Table. Philosophies. 2023; 8(4):67. https://doi.org/10.3390/philosophies8040067
Chicago/Turabian StyleLee, Jeonggyu. 2023. "Harry Potter and the Philosopher’s Table" Philosophies 8, no. 4: 67. https://doi.org/10.3390/philosophies8040067
APA StyleLee, J. (2023). Harry Potter and the Philosopher’s Table. Philosophies, 8(4), 67. https://doi.org/10.3390/philosophies8040067