Let us now go back to Baehr’s unifying account of open-mindedness as intellectual virtue. He argues that the conceptual core of open-mindedness lies in the fact that a person departs, moves beyond, or transcends a certain default or privileged cognitive standpoint (p. 149). Hence, also in his account, the challenge remains how one is able to transcend one’s default cognitive standpoint, exactly in cases where it matters most, namely when biases etc. are systematically hidden from one’s own mind. Along the same lines as we have shown above with Riggs’s account, an account like Baehr’s also needs to fill in open-minded attention for this crucial step. Open-minded attention is what enables the emancipation from a default cognitive standpoint in the case of systematically hidden contents, and thus makes open-mindedness open-minded. But there is more.
Two of Baehr’s main aims in unifying the different kinds of open-mindedness into a unified account of intellectual virtue are to show that (1) one does not need to assume a doxastic conflict or disagreement to be at the heart of open-mindedness—that is, there are also instances where the virtue of open-mindedness is needed when there is no opposing view to be considered—and (2) that not all forms of open-mindedness include rational assessment—that is, sometimes being open-minded is not about weighing evidence for and against a claim.
5.1. Doxastic Conflict
Baehr’s account seems confused about what it means to have a doxastic conflict. Baehr finds it implausible that open-mindedness is required only in situations where there is a doxastic conflict with one’s current beliefs. He writes:
(…) it is tempting to think of open-mindedness as essentially relevant to situations involving intellectual conflict, opposition, challenge, or argument, and in particular, to situations involving a conflict between a person’s beliefs, on the one hand, and an opposing position, argument, or body of evidence, on the other.
and
While initially plausible, the conflict model is inadequate as a general account of open-mindedness. This is because an exercise of open-mindedness (1) need not involve the setting aside or suspending of any beliefs; and (2) it need not presuppose any kind of conflict or disagreement between an open-minded person’s beliefs and the object of her open-mindedness. Both (1) and (2) are a function of the fact that open-mindedness can be manifested in situations in which the person in question is neutral with respect to the items being assessed.
This seems to betray a somewhat naïve view on what our epistemic default positions are when we are confronted with new evidence, a new view, or a new opinion. Baehr seems to think that there is such a thing as a neutral standpoint in regard to new information. And consequently, he thinks there must also be a kind of open-mindedness that applies to situations where the new information does not stand in conflict with any of our default cognitive standpoints (because they can be neutral in respect to the new information).
If we consider the model of attention as foregrounding and backgrounding, we obtain a different picture of our default cognitive standpoint. With this model, we are
never in a position of a neutral blank slate, as it were, in regard to any of the new information we receive. We always already have certain habits of foregrounding and backgrounding with which we take in the new information in the first place. For example, it is possible that I have never been in a garden before. Even in such a case, when I step into a garden the first time, I am not in a neutral cognitive standpoint in regard to the new impressions there. Some things will be more salient to me than others, even if I have never seen them before. I might have a habit of foregrounding red things as opposed to green things,
6 and so the berries will be foregrounded (thus, noticed) and the green leaves backgrounded. Hence, there is no neutral standpoint. And the attention model makes this clearer. What and how we foreground and background is, of course, all the more relevant if we consider how we perceive the
social world, where implicit social biases are usually at work. How I perceive the social world is inherently structured by my habits of foregrounding and backgrounding, which we know include implicit biases for all of us. Here, it is all the more important to realize that there is no neutral standpoint to start out with.
Let me clarify two points here: first, what kind of conflict is necessarily involved when we have to exercise the virtue of open-mindedness (
Section 5.1.1), and second, what it would mean to have a neutral standpoint (
Section 5.1.2).
5.1.1. What Kind of Conflict?
One could respond to the argument so far that ‘doxastic’ means ‘judgment-based’, and so a doxastic conflict is a conflict in judgment, and not just any kind of conflict. And the activity of foregrounding and backgrounding does not, by itself, imply the making of a judgment. So, in that sense, there is still no doxastic conflict if a situation requires of us to suspend our usual ways of foregrounding and to do it in a new way.
If considered in the narrow sense of ‘judgment-based’, open-mindedness does not always presuppose a doxastic conflict. The point made above should, thus, be understood in a weaker sense: that there is some form of conflict presupposed in exercising the virtue of open-mindedness. One could call this necessary conflict an ‘expectation conflict’. One expects (in virtue of one’s habits of foregrounding) ideas, visual stimuli, etc. to be structured into foreground and background in a certain way, but a new situation requires of one to revise that expectation, so that other objects are foregrounded than those expected. That is when the virtue of open-mindedness needs to be exercised. If there were no such conflict in expectation, there would be no need to suspend one’s usual ways of foregrounding, hence no need for the virtue to be exercised. We can understand the term ‘expectation conflict’ as the more general term, under which ‘doxastic conflict’ falls as one species. Hence, the revision this article makes to Baehr’s account—if doxastic conflict is to be understood in this narrower sense—is that it is not accurate to say that there is sometimes no conflict at all between one’s current way of seeing things and the new way one is trying to adopt, when exercising the virtue of open-mindedness. Some conflict is always required for the virtue of open-mindedness to be called for. This conflict might not always include a conflict in judgments, but at least a conflict in one’s expectations and how one then has to revise one’s habits of foregrounding and backgrounding. Baehr seems to have assumed a wrong dichotomy: either open-mindedness presupposes a kind of conflict between a person’s prior beliefs and the object of her open-mindedness, or open-mindedness can also be operative when a person is neutral with respect to the items being assessed. Our considerations show that there is a third possibility: one can also experience an expectation conflict (different foregrounding required than one’s habitual way), which means that one is not neutral in respect to the assessed objects, but one does likewise not have conflicting beliefs (not a doxastic conflict). These considerations do not speak against Baehr’s unifying account; they only make it more precise.
From the way we have now revised Baehr’s account with the attention framework, a worry might arise. The worry might be that this framework conceives of any change as a form of conflict. But, one might say, learning something new might require of me to change my foregrounding and backgrounding, but that does not necessarily mean that my new view is in conflict with my prior one—it is just different. In response to this worry, let me suggest distinguishing between three cases: (1) a case where the new view is in doxastic conflict with the old one; (2) a case where the new view is ‘only’ in an expectation conflict with the old one; and (3) a case where the new view is simply added to the old ones (having learned something completely new), in the sense that none of my prior views had to be adjusted or revised to add the new view.
In distinguishing these three cases, I argue that in cases 1 and 2, we need to exercise the virtue of open-mindedness in order to acquire the new view. In the third case, however, the virtue of open-mindedness is not required. That is, if I learn something new that does not in any way challenge my current views, not even my implicit expectations and what I give more and less focus to, then one does not need open-mindedness to add this view to one’s current views. To be able to learn something new in that way might still require some intellectual virtues, for example, the intellectual virtue of curiosity. But curiosity is not the same as open-mindedness. I suggest that this is precisely a good criterion to distinguish the virtues of curiosity and open-mindedness: while the latter is required in cases where at least one’s current expectations need to be revised to acquire the new view, curiosity is already required even if the new view is a conflict-free addition to one’s current views. Thus, it is true that in this framework, any change is conceived of as a conflict with one’s prior expectations. But this does not seem to be problematic by itself. Once we have the more minimal concept of an expectation conflict, we can see that even quite minimal expectations can be in conflict when we consider something new. On the contrary to being problematic, this framework helps us distinguish the virtue of open-mindedness from a very similar but distinct one: from the virtue of curiosity.
5.1.2. What is a Neutral Standpoint?
One might wonder what a neutral standpoint would be according to the attention framework, after we have rejected its possibility in our revision of Baehr’s account. The worry might be that if even one’s best efforts, exercising all intellectual virtues, cannot achieve a neutral standpoint, then it is an (either psychologically or conceptually) impossible standpoint, and hence not relevant for epistemic considerations in the first place. That is, it does not show us anything interesting to say that such a standpoint is epistemically not achievable, if the concept is made to be unachievable in principle. So, the challenge to the attention framework is: can we still conceive of a, in principle, neutral standpoint, or does that concept have no space in an attention framework?
A response to this must make the concept of ‘biases’ more precise. So far, it has been argued that a neutral standpoint is not achievable because we will never get rid of all of our biases. This was a loose way of making the point. A more precise way of putting it is the following. What we cannot get rid of, as long as we hold any beliefs and expectations at all, are presuppositions. Presuppositions can be thought of as those beliefs on which other beliefs necessarily build. For example, if I say “I like apples”, I presuppose that apples exist, that I have preferences, that apples are the kind of things that one can like, and so on (cf. Beaver, Geurts, Denlinger [
20] for more on presuppositions). So, no matter how thoroughly we examine our beliefs, there will always be some beliefs that are presupposed by holding old and by adopting new beliefs. There is no way out, as it were. The point can also be put in this way: we cannot think outside of conceptual frameworks, and conceptual frameworks are a network of presupposed beliefs within which we form our other beliefs.
7 If we called a standpoint ‘neutral’ only if it was ‘outside’ of such a framework, it would indeed be a conceptual impossibility to achieve that standpoint, and, thus, not epistemically relevant to consider such a standpoint.
Now, it is one thing to claim that we cannot get rid of presuppositions, and it is another to claim that we cannot get rid of biases. Biases are not just any presuppositions that we make. Biases (usually thought of as implicit biases) are a special kind of presuppositions: presuppositions that we had better not have.
8 They are called biased because they distort our thinking in some way. They make us think of an aspect as connected with one concept rather than another, they make us draw conclusions in one direction rather than another, they narrow our conceptual choices in a way that is unnecessary and distorting, and so on. What would it thus mean to say that a standpoint is neutral if it is not biased in this distorting sense? That is, a standpoint that does presuppose beliefs, but only non-biased ones? We would hope that such a standpoint is at least conceptually (even if perhaps not psychologically) possible. If we give up the possibility of a non-distorted standpoint, we lose track of what it would mean to make progress in one’s thinking. That is, if we want a notion of an intellectual virtue, we better think that one can get rid of distortions in thinking, at least in principle. Hence, we at least must think that, in principle, a non-biased standpoint is possible.
As a matter of epistemic humility, however, it is better to assume, at any given point in time, that we probably have not achieved such a fully non-biased standpoint (yet). While conceptually possible, it would most often be rash to assume that one has achieved a fully non-biased standpoint. Exactly in order to be able to be open-minded, one needs to assume that, most likely, one still has some implicit biases in the way one has structured one’s thoughts.
This kind of limitation in achieving a neutral standpoint is non-problematic for our issues at hand here, however. We can think of the virtue of open-mindedness as a necessary virtue (among others) to get rid of distortions in our thinking, that is, to also get rid of our biases. In the best of cases, with this virtue, we ameliorate all our biased presuppositions into non-biased presuppositions. However, it would be rash to assume, at any given point in time, that we have actually achieved such a neutral, that is, fully non-biased standpoint.
It is in this sense that Baehr’s position seems to assume a naïve view on our epistemic default position. He seems to assume that there can be cases where we are neutral in this latter sense—that we have no biases or expectations. The point made here is that we at the very least have certain expectations, and those lead to an expectation conflict in how to foreground when confronted with something new, even if there is no judgment-based conflict. On top of that, we always make (implicit) presuppositions because we cannot think outside of a conceptual framework—although this aspect is not problematic for Baehr’s view. In regard to biases, however, it is important that even if we think that it is
in principle possible to get rid of all our biases, it would at any given point in time be rash to assume that one has achieved such an epistemic standpoint. To sum up, given that there can also be expectation conflict and that we should never assume that we have in fact gotten rid of all our biases, we cannot epistemically act as if from a neutral standpoint.
9 This is just another way of showing that the virtue of open-mindedness is always exercised in the context of an encountered conflict, pace Baehr, be this a doxastic or some other expectation conflict. It is only when some new impression or information conflicts with my current ways of understanding (or structuring) things that I have an occasion to be open-minded (or to fail to be so).
It is clear that ‘conflict’ is not to be understood in a problematic sense here; this would be too strong and narrow. It does not need to be as strong as, for instance, a
conceptual incoherence with my current views, nor does it need to entail some negatively valenced feelings toward the new information. All it takes for it to count as a conflict is some sort of incongruence with my current default expectations. That is, all it takes is a situation that requires of me to foreground things differently than I would habitually do. If I habitually foreground the berries, and someone asks me whether the leaves are pointy or round, this requires of me to suspend my habit of foregrounding the berries, so that I can notice the shape of the leaves. If I follow suit to do this in order to answer the question, I exercise a form of open-mindedness.
10 The question about the shape of the leaves triggered an expectation conflict, in that it required of me to go against my habit of foregrounding the berries. Another example would be if I had the habit of always foregrounding male loud voices in a group discussion, and the topic currently discussed is women’s issues. This situation requires of me to suspend my habit of foregrounding male loud voices, so that I can notice what the women in the group say. If I follow suit to do this, I exercise a form of open-mindedness, in which I have to overcome my own habits of foregrounding. The question of what the women in the group say triggered an expectation conflict, in that it required of me to go against my habit of foregrounding male loud voices. But there is nothing particularly bad in experiencing such an expectation conflict.
In each of these cases, there is thus a conflict at the heart of exercising open-mindedness. The conflict lies between my habitual ways of foregrounding and the required way of foregrounding. Our default position is always already a particular way of foregrounding mental contents. That is why open-mindedness is such an important intellectual virtue. We would do better to give up on the myth of a neutral default standpoint and acknowledge how ubiquitous conflict is. This way, we can see how important the virtue of open-mindedness is, and understanding it as a virtue of attention helps us see that.
5.2. Rational Assessment
The last central aspect of Baehr’s account to be considered is his point that not all forms of open-mindedness include rational assessment—that is, he says, sometimes being open-minded is not about weighing evidence for and against a claim. I argue here that understanding open-mindedness as a virtue of attention explains better why open-mindedness does not necessarily entail rational assessment. Hence, the contribution of considering attention in this last aspect is not to disagree with Baehr (as in the case before, about the role of conflict), but to agree with him and to give an underlying reason why this is so.
Baehr [
1] considers the case of a high-school physics class to illustrate in what sense one can exhibit the virtue of open-mindedness without going through a rational assessment:
(…) imagine a physics teacher who has just led a group of bright high school students through a unit on Einstein’s Special Theory of Relativity. Most of the students have managed to follow the teacher’s lessons and thus have achieved a basic understanding of the theory. In the final part of the course, the teacher intends to push his students a significant step further by introducing them to Einstein’s General Theory. This is bound to pose a major challenge for most of the students in the course. It will require an even more dramatic departure (compared with the Special Theory) from their usual ways of thinking about space, time, physical laws, velocity, frames of reference, and the like.
Baehr thinks that, in this situation, the students need to exercise a form of open-mindedness in order to be able to wrap their minds around the scientific claims of Einstein’s General Theory, and that in this case, there is no rational assessment involved. Hence, there are cases of open-mindedness that do not include rational assessment. “For the students are not attempting to assess or evaluate Einstein’s General Theory. At this stage, they are simply trying to follow or understand it.” ([
1], p. 146).
I agree with Baehr that this is a case of open-mindedness and that it does not include rational assessment. What I want to argue is that the initial idea that open-mindedness would necessarily include rational assessment was misguided and comes from not seeing it as a virtue of attention. The idea that open-mindedness would necessarily include rational assessment seems to mean, in Baehr’s case, that it has something to do with “assessing or evaluating” a position (e.g., Einstein’s General Theory). This seems, to wit, to be a leftover from some reliabilist (as opposed to responsibilist) ways of understanding intellectual virtues (considering that reliabilist virtue epistemology was there first, and virtue responsibilists like Baehr try to move away from it).
Recall, reliabilists’ main criterion is whether a certain mental practice reliably leads to truth. Hence, much of reliabilists’ thought is on how evidence is being treated—how evidence is being assessed and evaluated. Responsibilists also care about how evidence is being treated, but in a different way. They ask what habits lead to certain (virtuous) practices, and which do not. In a responsibilist framework of asking which (mental) habits lead to (intellectual) virtues, rational assessment can sometimes play a role, but not always, and never the most fundamental one. Hence, Baehr’s default position of considering rational assessment a necessary ingredient of open-mindedness seems to betray some reliabilist tendencies (from which he then moves away).
Considering open-mindedness as a virtue of attention, by contrast, has the promise of making it obvious that we do not have to consider rational assessment as a necessary ingredient of open-mindedness. In that sense, to understand open-mindedness as a virtue of attention is more thoroughly grounded in a responsibilist framework.
The core of understanding open-mindedness as a virtue of attention is that we ask, instead, how we foreground and background mental contents. Importantly, we ask how we are able to suspend our usual ways of foregrounding. This can but does not have to include rational assessment. Applied to the physics high-school class, we see that what the teacher asks the students to do requires a dramatic departure from their usual ways of thinking about space, time, physical laws, velocity, and frames of reference. That is, it requires of them to suspend their usual habits of what they foreground when they think about space, time, physical laws, etc., in order to make mental space for other ways of conceiving of these concepts. It seems natural in the attention framework of open-mindedness that rational assessment never appears as a step, and it seems natural that this is a (paradigmatic) way of being open-minded. This shows the strength of understanding open-mindedness as a virtue of attention.
Let us consider a related but slightly different observation by Baehr about the virtue of open-mindedness, with which I would like to close this section showing the strength of the attention model for the virtue of open-mindedness.
Baehr [
1] observes that when being open-minded, this sometimes means engaging in what he calls a “positive psychological activity” ([
1], p. 150), that is, for example, actively considering a competing position to one’s own. But at other times, he notices, being open-minded has “a negative character: it consists in refraining from taking up an alternative cognitive standpoint” ([
1], p. 151) He then concludes that “this illustrates the important point that while open-mindedness is often a matter of positively opening one’s mind, it is sometimes a matter of not closing it” ([
1], p. 151).
Again, I agree with Baehr that open-mindedness consists in both of these mental practices, namely what he calls “positively opening” and “not closing”. And again, I argue that understanding it as a virtue of attention shows the underlying reason why this is so. An attention framework of open-mindedness makes this a non-surprising aspect of this virtue. In Baehr’s own definition, by contrast, it might look like a surprising result that open-mindedness sometimes consists in a “positive” activity of considering a new standpoint, and sometimes in a “negative” one of refraining from taking on a certain standpoint. In an attention framework, these two mental practices are really one and the same.
The clue is to realize that “refraining from taking up a certain standpoint” is just as much a “positive” psychological activity as “considering a new standpoint”.
11 That is, in a non-attention framework, it might look like either we actively consider a new standpoint and so we engage in a positive mental activity, or we “refrain” from this, remaining in our prior standpoint, which is considered a “negative” activity, in the sense that one does not go through any steps to get to a new standpoint.
It is this last assumption that distorts the picture. Remaining in a certain standpoint while being confronted with new impressions is not a merely negative mental activity, because it is not a mere refraining from going through certain mental steps. On the contrary, it is an active endeavor, and a (sometimes) arduous achievement. It is an active interference in how to foreground things, resisting a ‘natural’ (default) way of foregrounding. Imagine someone approaches you and says, “notice how women always try to get a guy’s money in a divorce process”. This person is asking you to foreground a certain (assumed) motive when you hear stories of people going through a divorce. When he says that to you, your mind, at least for a moment, might imagine things the way this person claims it to be. If you then, open-mindedly, decide to not keep this now-inserted-in-you way of foregrounding the next time you hear a divorce story, you are actively keeping this way of foregrounding at bay. You have to do something in order to not succumb to this misogynistic bias. So, you refrain from taking on this standpoint by actively suspending this way of foregrounding. This is in no way different from, and instead the same kind of activity as, when you suspend your usual ways of foregrounding in order to make mental space for a new standpoint. So, it does not matter whether you do the suspending to take on a new standpoint, or whether on the contrary you do it to avoid a new standpoint. In both cases, you suspend your immediate way of foregrounding things in order to get rid of biases, overconfidence, and wishful thinking. The “positive” and “negative” mental practices, in Baehr’s words, are thus really one and the same in an attentional framework of open-mindedness. Hence, understanding open-mindedness as a virtue of attention gets rid of the requirement of an extra explanation as to why there seem to be two different mental activities that both count as open-mindedness. In short, attention gives us a unified, realistic, and coherent account of open-mindedness.