Arthur Prior and Augustine’s Alleged Presentism
Abstract
:1. Introduction
2. From Augustine to Prior
2.1. Prior’s Presentism
- “The present simply is the real considered in relation to a particular.”
- “The present simply is the real considered with a particular kind of contrasting unreality in mind, namely the pa[st].”
2.2. The 11th Book of Confessiones
2.3. Prior’s Utilization of Augustine
The construction I am sketching embodies the truth behind Augustine’s suggestion of the ‘secret place’ where past and future times ‘are’, and his insistence that wherever they are, they are not there as past or future but as present. The past is not the present but it is the past present, and the future is not the present but it is the future present.
3. From Prior to Augustine
3.1. Augustinian Temporality in Wider Context
3.2. On Divine Eternity
3.3. On Creation
It is far from doubt that the world was not created in time but with time. For what happens in time happens before one time and after another, afterward it is past and beforehand it is future. But there could be no past because there was no creation whose motion and change were acted upon. On the contrary, the world was made with time if, in its creation, motion and change were made.54
3.4. On the Human Condition
3.5. Augustine’s Proto-Presentism
Funding
Data Availability Statement
Acknowledgments
Conflicts of Interest
1. | Literally “to be before”, though it also contains the meaning “to preside over”. |
2. | “Augustine’s thinking [about eternity] was the core that determined the broad outlines of all that later medieval philosophical theology made of the concept of God” [1] (p. 73). |
3. | |
4. | This was an important insight of N. L. Wilson contributing to being logically rigorous about the way we commonly speak of enduring and changing individuals, though he does so without using tenses: “Wilson, in short, has indeed brought us out of Egypt; but as yet has us still wandering about the Sinai Peninsula” [13] (p. 78). |
5. | The example of uttering this after being drilled by a dentist was already used in 1938 by C.D. Broad in his second volume of An Examination of McTaggart’s Philosophy [14] (p. 118). |
6. | Thus, PnFnp is interchangeable with “p now” i.e., the plain p, where n stands for time-units [13] (p. 66). Prior preferred the Polish notation of Łukasiewicz to the that of Russell and Whitehead’s Principia Mathematica (cf. [2], pp. v, 3–9). Prior would later reconsider whether “now” is always redundant [15] (pp. 171–193); [7] (pp. 42–43 n 2). |
7. | At the end of his article “Egocentric Logic”, Prior formalizes his position [15] (pp. 237–240). |
8. | Prior discusses the “wait-and-seeishness” character of certain statements regarding the future (cf. [13], pp. 101–108). |
9. | Thomas Clemmons has provided a stellar overview of Augustine’s earlier discussions on the subject [18] (pp. 3–16). |
10. | “mutari atque variari”. |
11. | “totum esse praesens”. |
12. | “nullum vero tempus totum esse praesens”. |
13. | “What is said overall in Conf. XI on the analysis of time does not solve the problem of the connection between eternity and time; overall, as in the first line, Augustine emphasizes the distance” [21] (p. 289). |
14. | |
15. | “Quid est ergo tempus?”. |
16. | “Si nemo ex me quaerat, scio; si quaerenti explicare vellim, nescio” [19] (XI, 14.17). |
17. | Cf. [23], 17. |
18. | “Longum fuit illud praesens tempus”. |
19. | “Nam si extenditur, diuiditur in praeteritum et futurum: praesens autem nullum habet spatium”. |
20. | “quod non est”. |
21. | “Quaero, pater, non affirmo”. |
22. | At times, he addresses the human soul (e.g., [19] (XI, 15.19)). |
23. | “ex aliquo procedit occulto”. |
24. | Lenka Karfíková characterizes Confessiones as a “work of memory” capturing personal identity through narration [24] (p. 175). Plato speaks about all learning being a process of recollection [25] (81d–82a), and Augustine was familiar with the paradox of only being able to seek what we partially already know [19] (X, 18.27–19.28). |
25. | “tempora sunt tria, praesens de praeteritis, praesens de praesentibus, praesens de futuris”. |
26. | Cicero distinguishes between memoria, intelligentia, and providentia [21] (p. 350). |
27. | |
28. | “Ex illo ergo, quod nondum est, per illud, quod spatio caret, in illud, quod iam non est”. |
29. | “implicatissimum aenigma”. |
30. | “Inde mihi visum est nihil esse aliud tempus quam distentionem: sed cuius rei, nescio, et mirum, si non ipsius animi”. |
31. | “Time, then, according to Augustine, is the time of the observed thing (there would be no time without passing things), but only in the form of an impression that a passing thing leaves in the soul. The impression is distension of the soul itself—that is, distension of its attention into a memory and an expectation” [24] (p. 187). |
32. | In Essays Religious, Prior discusses Augustine’s view of predestination [26] (pp. 175–176, 224). |
33. | Prior credits Findlay with being “In a sense the founding father of modern tense-logic” [3] (p. 1) and for teaching him “almost all that I know of either Logic or Ethics” [29] (p. xi). Some debate has revolved around the question of why Prior would credit Findlay as the founder when Prior’s reason for doing so seemingly rests on a small footnote of Findlay’s article. David Jakobsen demonstrates that there is more to this story than a single reference [30]. The footnote of Findlay, who also thoroughly utilizes Augustine in formulating his position [28] (pp. 222–229), is the following: “The calculus of tenses should have been included in the modern development of modal logics. It includes such obvious propositions as that x present ≡ (x present) present; x future ≡ (x future) present ≡ (x present) future; also such comparatively recondite propositions as that (x). (x past) future; i.e., all events, past, present and future, will be past” [28] (p. 233 n 17). |
34. | Findlay’s article also discusses Confessiones. |
35. | This, of course, is just a metaphor that should not be taken literally. |
36. | |
37. | “secretissime et praesentissime … immutabilis, mutans omnia”. |
38. | “tota ubique”. |
39. | |
40. | Augustine’s view of divine immutability is therefore less “strict” and metaphysically developed than thomistic simplicity. For Augustine, unchangeability, not simplicity, seems to be the most fundamental description. |
41. | “Truly, God does not come to know things in time he did not know beforehand” [34] (IV, 9.17)—“Neque enim Deus temporaliter cognoscit quod ante non noverat”. |
42. | “cuncta praeterita et futura tempora superari”. |
43. | “ubique totum, sine tempore sempiternum”. |
44. | “sine ullo tempore”. |
45. | “occultam aeternitatem semper praesentis”. |
46. | According to Augustine, the Platonists are the philosophers nearest to the Christian way of thinking [36] (VIII, 5), and he even say that they would have become Christians if they had lived in his time ([37], 4.7), though becoming increasingly critical of Platonism later in life (cf. [38], pp. 106–107). Plotinus was known to have the most thorough understanding of Plato [36] (IX, 10). Though clearly being an original thinker, Plotinus viewed himself as someone who merely explained and commented on Plato’s thoughts [39] (xlvii). The divine graded triad consist of The One (the First, the Good) in complete unity followed by the Intellectual Principle (ὁ νοῦς, the primal thinker) constituted in stable act upon which the Soul (the All-Soul, the principle of life) follows [22] (II, 9.1; III, 3.3). The human soul must devote itself to the intellectual principle [22] (I, 2.4) liberating itself from this low sphere [22] (II, 3.9) through contemplation [22] (I, 2.6). For Plotinus, things on the low end of the ontological scale are characterized by diversity, multiplicity, and confusion whereas ideal forms and the divine consist in unity, harmony, and coherence [22] (I, 6.2). Thus, the evil is described as being contrary to existence [22] (I, 6.6) and as lacking goodness either to some degree or absolutely [22] (I, 8.5). In this earthly sphere, matter is constantly changing [22] (II, 4.3) and by its alienation from the intellectual realm it can be characterized as non-existent and non-being [22] (II, 4.16, III, 6.7). Humanity is midway between the gods and beasts and can chose to ascend to the former or descend to the latter [22] (III, 2.8). The end of contemplation is θεωρία [22] (III, 8.1) developing Aristotle’s concept of it being the highest activity of humans leading to complete happiness [40] (X, 1177a1–1178b1). Advancing from nature to the Soul to the Intellectual Principle through contemplation a person becomes more intimate with the object contemplated [22] (III, 8.8) reaching greater unity and becoming closer with The One, of which nothing can be affirmed since The One transcends all descriptions—even existence, life, and essence [22] (III, 8.10). It was within the Soul’s nature to create the cosmos. To question this implies a beginning in the eternal and is like asking why a creator creates (Enn. II. 9.8). Time and eternity are two entirely separate things, since time belongs to the realm of process. As Plato said, time is the moving image of eternity, and, therefore, Plotinus gives a definition of eternity before he reflects on the nature of time [22] (III, 7.1–2). Eternity is an unbroken whole without parts, a unity without intervals, and changeless, motionless life in an eternal now [22], (III, 7.2–3). Time belongs to the lower, though not lowest, levels having descended from eternity [22] (III, 7.7). Plotinus is especially preoccupied with discussing and critizising Aristotle’s treatment in Physics [41] (IV); [22] (III, 7.7–10). In establishing the cosmos, the Soul laid eternity aside and made the world a servant to time, thus time is the Soul’s life in movement [22] (III, 7.11). Time is a thing within itself present everywhere within the cosmos but could evaporate if the Soul returned to its primal unity [22] (III, 7,12–13). Though similarities are obvious it is debated whether Augustine had read Ennead III, 7. The origin of temporality is explained from an ontological source in the Plotinian Soul, which Augustine has no need for [33] (79–80), and, in Augustine’s view, history is vastly more significant [18] (5). |
47. | “Deus meus ubique praesens est, ubique totus”. |
48. | “What is ‘I am who am’ if not ‘I am eternal’? “What is ‘I am who am’ if not ‘I am not able to change?’” [42] (VII)—“quid est, [ego sum qui sum], nisi, aeternus sum? quid est, [ego sum qui sum], nisi, qui mutari non possum?” |
49. | |
50. | “ante principium temporis non erat tempus”. Augustine frequently uses principium for Christ, wisdom, mediator, etc. (cf. [45], 75). |
51. | “caelum intellectuale”. |
52. | “involucris primordialibus in tempore evolvitur”. |
53. | “quod tempus sine aliqua mobili mutabilitate non est”. |
54. | “procul dubio non est mundus factus in tempore, sed cum tempore. Quod enim fit in tempore, et post aliquod fit, et ante aliquod tempus; post id quod praeteritum est, ante id quod futurum est; nullum autem posset esse praeteritum, quia nulla erat creatura, cuius mutabilibus motibus ageretur. Cum tempore autem factus est mundus, si in eius conditione factus est mutabilis motus”. |
55. | “trium temporum”. |
56. | The same applies for the created world: “For he [God] is such that in comparison with him things that are, are not” [47] (134.4)—“Ita enim ille est, ut in eius comparatione ea quae facta sunt, non sint”. |
57. | Leftow considers whether the meaning of this could be “… that one object has more intense, full, or genuine existence than another, or that one assertion of existence is better founded than another” [1] (81). |
58. | |
59. | Both “creatio ex nihilo” and “creatio continua” are traditional dogmas of Christian faith. |
60. | Augustine uses “space” for time elsewhere: “three years and six months is a short space [of time]” [36] (XX, 13)—“trium annorum et sex mensium brevissimum spatium est”. |
61. | “ut nec ulla explicari locutione possit nec ulla ratione vitari”. |
62. | “If you understand it, it is not God”/“Si enim comprehendis, non est Deus” [48] (CXVII, III). |
References
- Leftow, B. Time and Eternity; Cornell University Press: Ithaca, NY, USA; London, UK, 1991. [Google Scholar]
- Prior, A.N. Formal Logic, 2nd ed.; Clarendon Press: Oxford, UK, 1962. [Google Scholar]
- Prior, A. Past, Present and Future; Clarendon Press: Oxford, UK, 1967. [Google Scholar]
- Prior, A.N. Some Free Thinking About Time. In Time, Creation and World-Order; Wegener, M., Ed.; Aarhus University Press: Aarhus, Denmark, 1999; pp. 265–269. [Google Scholar]
- Curtis, B.L.; Robson, J. A Critical Introduction to the Metaphysics of Time; Bloomsbury Academic: London, UK; New York, NY, USA, 2016. [Google Scholar]
- Ingram, D.; Tallant, J. Presentism. In The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy; Winter 2022 Edition; Zalta, E.N., Nodelman, N., Eds.; Stanford University: Stanford, CA, USA, 2022. [Google Scholar]
- Bourne, C. A Future for Presentism; Clarendon Press: Oxford, UK, 2006. [Google Scholar]
- Oaklander, L.N. Two Versions of the New B-Theory of Language. In Time, Tense, and Reference; Jokić, A., Smith., Q., Eds.; The MIT Press: Cambridge, UK, 2003; pp. 271–303. [Google Scholar]
- Smith, Q. Language and Time; Oxford University Press: Oxford, UK, 1993. [Google Scholar]
- Smith, Q. Reference to the Past and Future. In Time, Tense, and Reference; Jokić, A., Smith, Q., Eds.; The MIT Press: Cambridge, UK, 2003; pp. 357–390. [Google Scholar]
- Prior, A.N. Time and Modality: Being the John Locke Lectures for 1955–1956 Delivered in the University of Oxford; Clarendon Press: Oxford, UK, 1957. [Google Scholar]
- Prior, A.N. Changes in Events and Changes in Things. In Metaphysics: The Big Questions, 2nd ed.; van Inwagen, P., Zimmerman, D.W., Eds.; Blackwell Publishing: Oxford, UK, 2008; pp. 131–141. [Google Scholar]
- Prior, A.N. Papers in Logic and Ethics; Geach, P.T., Kenny, A.J.P., Eds.; Gerald Duckworth & Company Limited: London, UK, 1976. [Google Scholar]
- Broad, C.D. Ostensible Temporality. In The Philosophy of Time: A Collection of Essays; Gale, R.M., Ed.; Macmillan & Co Ltd.: London, UK; Melbourne, Australia, 1968; pp. 117–142. [Google Scholar]
- Prior, A.N. Papers on Time and Tense; New edition; Hasle, P., Øhrstrøm, P., Braüner, T., Copeland, J., Eds.; Oxford University Press: Oxford, UK, 2003. [Google Scholar]
- Prior, A.N. The Notion of the Present. In Metaphysics: The Big Questions, 2nd ed.; van Inwagen, P., Zimmerman, D.W., Eds.; Blackwell Publishing: Oxford, UK, 2008; pp. 129–131. [Google Scholar]
- Jakobsen, D.A.N. Prior’s Notion of the Present. In Multidisciplinary Aspects of Time and Time Perception; Vatakis, A., Esposito, A., Giagkou, M., Cummins, F., Papadelis, G., Eds.; Springer: Berlin/Heidelberg, Germany, 2011; pp. 36–45. [Google Scholar]
- Clemmons, T. Time, Eternity, and History in Augustine’s Early Works. In Augustine and Time; Doody, J., Hannan, S., Paffenroth, K., Eds.; Lexington Books: London, UK, 2021; pp. 3–20. [Google Scholar]
- Augustini, S.A. Confessiones. In Opera Omnia; Patrologiae Latinae Elenchus 32; Migne, J.P., Ed.; Parisiis: Paris, France, 1861. [Google Scholar]
- Augustini, S.A. Soliloquiorum. In Opera Omnia; Patrologiae Latinae Elenchus 32; Migne, J.P., Ed.; Parisiis: Paris, France, 1861. [Google Scholar]
- Flash, K. Was ist Zeit?: Augustinus von Hippo. Das XI. Buch der Confessiones. Historisch-philosophische Studie. Text—Übersetzung—Kommentar; Klostermann Seminar: Frankfurt, Germany, 1993. [Google Scholar]
- Plotinus. The Enneads. MacKenna, S., Translator; abridged with an introduction and notes by John Dillon; Penguin Books: London, UK, 1991. [Google Scholar]
- Augustini, S.A. De diversis Quaestionibus octoginta tribus. In Opera Omnia; Patrologiae Latinae Elenchus 40; Migne, J.P., Ed.; Parisiis: Paris, France, 1861. [Google Scholar]
- Karfíková, L. Memory, Eternity, and Time. In The Cambridge Companion to Augustine’s Confessions; Tarmo, T., Ed.; Cambridge University Press: Cambridge, UK, 2020; pp. 175–190. [Google Scholar]
- Plato. Meno. In Classics of Philosophy, 3rd ed.; Pojman, L.P., Vaughn, L., Eds.; Oxford University Press: Oxford, UK, 2011; pp. 101–111. [Google Scholar]
- Prior, A.N. Essays Religious. In Three Little Essays: Arthur Prior in 1931; Jakobsen, D., Øhrstrøm, P., Prior, M., Rini, A., Eds.; Logic and Philosophy of Time; Aalborg University Press: Aalborg, Denmark, 2020; Volume 3, pp. 167–227. [Google Scholar]
- Prior, A.N. Essay Scientific. In Three Little Essays: Arthur Prior in 1931; Jakobsen, D., Øhrstrøm, P., Prior, M., Rini, A., Eds.; Logic and Philosophy of Time; Aalborg University Press: Aalborg, Denmark, 2020; Volume 3, pp. 229–282. [Google Scholar]
- Findlay, J.N. Time: A treatment of some puzzles. Aust. J. Psychol. Philos. 1941, 19, 216–235. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Prior, A.N. Logic and the Basis of Ethics; Clarendon Press: Oxford, UK, 1949. [Google Scholar]
- Jakobsen, D. In What Sense is J.N. Findlay the Founding Father of Tense-Logic? Hist. Philos. Log. 2021, 42, 180–188. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Gale, R.M. The Philosophy of Time: A Collection of Essays; MacMillan: London, UK; Melbourne, Australia, 1968. [Google Scholar]
- Power, S.E. Philosophy of Time: A Contemporary Introduction; Routledge: New York, NY, USA; London, UK, 2021. [Google Scholar]
- Zachhuber, J. Time and Soul: From Aristotle to St. Augustine; Chronoi Band 6; Zeit, Zeitempfinden, Zeitordnungen—Time, Time Awareness, Time Management; Herausgegeben von Eva Cancik-Kirschbaum, Christoph Markschies und Hermann Parzinger; De Gruyter: Berlin, Germany; Boston, MA, USA, 2022. [Google Scholar]
- Augustini, S.A. De Genesi ad Litteram. In Opera Omnia; Patrologiae Latinae Elenchus 34; Migne, J.P., Ed.; Parisiis: Paris, France, 1861. [Google Scholar]
- Augustini, S.A. De Trinitate. In Opera Omnia; Patrologiae Latinae Elenchus 42; Migne, J.P., Ed.; Parisiis: Paris, France, 1861. [Google Scholar]
- Augustini, S.A. De Civitate Dei. In Opera Omnia; Patrologiae Latinae Elenchus 41; Migne, J.P., Ed.; Parisiis: Paris, France, 1861. [Google Scholar]
- Augustini, S.A. De Vera Religione. In Opera Omnia; Patrologiae Latinae Elenchus 34; Migne, J.P., Ed.; Parisiis: Paris, France, 1861. [Google Scholar]
- Haystrup, H. Augustin Studier 14: Vestens Filosof og Kirkelærer; C.A. Reitzels Forlag A/S: Copenhagen, Denmark, 2001. [Google Scholar]
- Henry, P. The Place of Plotinus in the History of Thought. In The Enneads; MacKenna, S., Translator; abridged with an introduction and notes by John Dillon; Penguin Books: London, UK, 1991; pp. xlii–lxxxiii. [Google Scholar]
- Aristotle. Nicomachean Ethics. In Classics of Philosophy, 3rd ed.; Pojman, L.P., Vaughn, L., Eds.; Ross, W.D., Translator; Oxford University Press: Oxford, UK, 2011; pp. 266–308. [Google Scholar]
- Aristotle. Physics. In The Philosophy of Time: A Collection of Essays; Book IV; Gale, R.M., Ed.; Hardie, R.P.; Gaye, R.K., Translators; Macmillan & Co Ltd.: London, UK; Melbourne, Australia, 1968; pp. 9–23. [Google Scholar]
- Augustini, S.A. Sermones. In Opera Omnia; Patrologiae Latinae Elenchus 38; Migne, J.P., Ed.; Parisiis: Paris, France, 1861. [Google Scholar]
- Augustini, S.A. De Genesi ad Litteram imperfectus. In Opera Omnia; Patrologiae Latinae Elenchus 34; Migne, J.P., Ed.; Parisiis: Paris, France, 1861. [Google Scholar]
- Augustini, S.A. Retractationum. In Opera Omnia; Patrologiae Latinae Elenchus 32; Migne, J.P., Ed.; Parisiis: Paris, France, 1861. [Google Scholar]
- Ayoub, C.N.A. Time, Mirror of the Soul. In Augustine and Time; Doody, J., Hannan, S., Paffenroth, K., Eds.; Lexington Books: London, UK, 2021; pp. 73–87. [Google Scholar]
- Augustini, S.A. De Genesi contra Manichaeos. In Opera Omnia; Patrologiae Latinae Elenchus 34; Migne, J.P., Ed.; Parisiis: Paris, France, 1861. [Google Scholar]
- Augustini, S.A. Enerrationes in Psalmos. In Opera Omnia; Patrologiae Latinae Elenchus 36; Migne, J.P., Ed.; Parisiis: Paris, France, 1861. [Google Scholar]
- Augustini, S.A. Epistolae. In Opera Omnia; Patrologiae Latinae Elenchus 33; Migne, J.P., Ed.; Parisiis: Paris, France, 1861. [Google Scholar]
Disclaimer/Publisher’s Note: The statements, opinions and data contained in all publications are solely those of the individual author(s) and contributor(s) and not of MDPI and/or the editor(s). MDPI and/or the editor(s) disclaim responsibility for any injury to people or property resulting from any ideas, methods, instructions or products referred to in the content. |
© 2024 by the author. Licensee MDPI, Basel, Switzerland. This article is an open access article distributed under the terms and conditions of the Creative Commons Attribution (CC BY) license (https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/).
Share and Cite
Steiner, T.N. Arthur Prior and Augustine’s Alleged Presentism. Philosophies 2024, 9, 162. https://doi.org/10.3390/philosophies9060162
Steiner TN. Arthur Prior and Augustine’s Alleged Presentism. Philosophies. 2024; 9(6):162. https://doi.org/10.3390/philosophies9060162
Chicago/Turabian StyleSteiner, Thomas N. 2024. "Arthur Prior and Augustine’s Alleged Presentism" Philosophies 9, no. 6: 162. https://doi.org/10.3390/philosophies9060162
APA StyleSteiner, T. N. (2024). Arthur Prior and Augustine’s Alleged Presentism. Philosophies, 9(6), 162. https://doi.org/10.3390/philosophies9060162