1. Introduction
Land acquisition for generating public goods such as infrastructure projects has remained an important policy concern in India. After a major land reform bill was passed in 2013, potential land buyers raised concerns about the draconian consent and compensation measures mandated in the bill. Land is a fixed resource and redistributing it among different groups through the market might result in second-best allocations. This implies that one group, the buyer or the seller, might be worse-off after the transaction occurs. However, the post-transaction redistribution of land may also result in higher overall social welfare [
1]. Therefore, the role of the government in land markets must be reexamined. Due to complaints from members of the business community, the succeeding Indian government promulgated an amendment bill in 2015, which collapsed in the upper-house of the Indian parliament. This article examines the necessity of a key amendment proposed in the bill—the removal of the “consent clause” in five areas: industrial corridors, public-private partnership projects, rural infrastructure, affordable housing, and defense. In other words, the government wanted to retain the ability to impose eminent domain in the aforementioned areas. We ask whether the removal of the consent clause would have led to efficient land allocation outcomes.
During the early part of the 19th century, the British-India government passed legislations to acquire land for public use in the eastern and southern parts of the country against the demands of the land owners. Soon after this, the scope of these legislations was broadened to the rural and forest areas and they were collectively called The Land Acquisition Act of 1894. This was the first comprehensive land acquisition law in India. According to the law, land would be acquired for the creation of public goods, where the state would be the agent of acquisition from individual owners. The government would determine the price of the land parcel under consideration. As expected, the interpretation of a “public good” was broad and it compromised the rights of the land owners.
The Right to Fair Compensation and Transparency in Land Acquisition, Rehabilitation and Resettlement Act (LARR) was passed by the Indian Parliament in September 2013 [
2]. The Act replaces the Land Acquisition Act of 1894 and is considered one of the signature achievements of the United Progressive Alliance, which was the ruling coalition party at the time. The Act creates a transparent process through which buyers can acquire land for industrialization and other commercial activities. However, the bill also requires owners to be adequately compensated and resettled. “Adequate compensation” implies that if a buyer acquires land at market value for any public purpose, then the land owner must be resettled with the option of a monthly allowance of up to
$500 for 20 years.
1 The owner can also choose to receive a payment of
$11,000 upfront instead of the monthly allowance.
2 If undeveloped land is resold, then the government shares 20% of the appreciated land value with the original owner. The Land Acquisition Bill of 1894 mandates that the market value of land must be determined by the three-year moving average of the land’s price. The new Act maintains a variation of this provision and adds two other provisions to determine the market value of land: (1) “the value will be set as or the higher of the minimum value specified in the Indian Stamp Act, 1899 for the registration of sale deeds in the area, where the land is situated”; (2) “the value will be set as or the higher of the consented amount in case the land is acquired for private companies or public-private partnership projects”.
The succeeding government, led by Prime Minister Narendra Modi, was dissatisfied with some clauses in the original Act and promulgated three amendment bills, one in 2014 and two in 2015, to address the concerns of potential land buyers. Nine amendments were introduced in the 2015 bill. One of these amendments was the exclusion of the “Consent” clause, which became contentious. In this paper, we examine the impact of the “Consent” clause in the original bill and ask if its removal is beneficial for social welfare. The removal of the “Consent” clause would allow the government to acquire land for industrial corridors, public private partnership (PPP) projects, rural infrastructure, affordable housing, and defense without the approval of the land owners.
3 The original Act requires the consent of at least 80% land owners for private projects (PP) and 70% for PPP projects [
3].
Several members of academia and various political parties in India have condemned the proposed removal of the consent clause. Since forced acquisition is a component of the amendment bill, the market-value approach is inefficient for the land owners. Every owner has their own land valuation, which is subjective. In microeconomic terms, this implies that the utility derived from owning the land is more than just a function of its price.
4 It could be a function of locational amenities or emotional attachment. If the owner is forced to sell, they may receive disutility from the transaction. If the seller and the buyer negotiate a price, then the buyer could face an exaggerated valuation from the seller. Ghatak and Ghosh propose two solutions for the problem: (1) the transfer price is determined by an auction; and (2) the sellers get an option of compensation in cash or compensation in land [
4]. Both proposals make the process fairer for the owners. However, their analysis does not consider the welfare of non-farm members of the society and that the auction price might be too high and not result in an acquisition.
Numerous studies examine the impact of land acquisition on social welfare [
5,
6,
7,
8,
9]. The majority of the discussion in these studies draws attention to the potential losses for the land owners and not to the benefits that might arise from private or government entities acquiring land for industrial use. “Benefit” is defined as the difference between the potential output or psuedo-output a piece of land would generate if acquired, and the cost to the land owners. For example, suppose the government acquires land for industrial use, if the expected value of the output exceeds the value currently being generated from the unsold land, then the acquisition is warranted. Under the “Consent” clause, this might not occur as the owner has the right to refuse any transaction price. Land acquisition for an infrastructure project is another example. The acquired stretch of land might be used for building a bridge. While the bridge inherently does not produce any output, it facilitates output or pseudo-output production through the commuters who would use the bridge.
Other studies examine the impact of land reform on farmers’ welfare and agricultural productivity [
10,
11]. Besley and Burgess deduce that various land reforms in India led to a decrease in poverty [
12]. However, they do not investigate whether land used for non-agricultural purposes would have yielded a higher social output. The few studies which examine land conversion from agricultural to non-agricultural use argue that conversion leads to food security and environmental problems favoring the involvement of the government in land use decisions, as the author contends that market-based land allocations might lead to agricultural decline [
13,
14].
In this paper, we aim to prove that the removal of the “Consent” clause is optimal. We use Pareto efficiency and the Kaldor-Hicks criterion to conduct our analysis. Clearly, forcing owners to surrender their land can skew the wealth distribution of an economy. Therefore, we derive a compensation strategy, which would improve the original act (if implemented), such that it is universally acceptable.
2. Literature Review of Pareto Efficiency and Kaldor-Hicks Criterion
In this section, we describe the concept of Pareto Efficiency and its uses in applied microeconomics such as the Kaldor-Hicks criterion. Pareto efficiency or optimality is a state in which no individual can be made better off without making someone else worse-off [
15,
16]. It is usually used in the context of welfare economics, where two or more individuals are endowed with various goods. It addresses the individuals’ desire to maximize utility and trade goods with each other at the market price to arrive at an optimal allocation of goods. When the market price is assumed to be exogenous and all individuals are price takers, then the state of optimality is known as a Partial equilibrium [
17]. If the market price is endogenous or determined in conjunction with the production process, then the state of optimality is known as a general equilibrium. In our model, we assume that land acquisition will lead to endogenous land prices [
18]. Pareto efficiency is attained when no individual can be made better off without compromising someone else’s utility.
In real life, attaining Pareto efficiency is difficult. Therefore, most policymakers strive for the second-best outcomes or Pareto-preferred outcomes. This approach is also termed as the Kaldor-Hicks criterion. Under this criterion, as long as societal gains exceed losses from a certain policy’s implementation and if the winners can hypothetically compensate the losers—even if such a compensation does not occur), then that policy is justified [
19,
20]. This criterion is the foundation of the modern cost-benefit analysis and has been heavily debated amongst academics and lawmakers. Posner defines the Kaldor-Hicks criterion as wealth maximization and not utility maximization and argues that it is the best tool that policymakers possess to judge the merits of policies or public projects, which involve transactions between willing and unwilling parties [
21]. He shows that out of all the decision rules that a government can employ, others being Pareto efficiency and utility maximization, the Kaldor-Criterion is the most pragmatic approach for economic development. Finally, he notes that unlike Pareto efficiency, where the public project may most likely never get undertaken, and utility maximization, where benefits and costs are strictly dependent on the functional form of the researcher, the Kaldor-Hicks criterion forces the government to confront the cost-benefit of a particular policy or project. Therefore, as an example for our case, even if the land policy is not implemented since the costs were shown to be higher than the benefits, through the Kaldor-Hicks approach, the government would be better prepared for similar situations in the future, because the value of costs and benefits was computed for the decision.
The total land endowment of a country is fixed and unlike money, it cannot be increased or decreased to attain Pareto efficient outcomes. Therefore, the initial allocation of each individual is already Pareto efficient. Since the redistribution of land is a zero-sum game, where some individuals will win and others will lose, policymakers could invoke the Kaldor-Hicks criterion to justify redistribution. Achieving such allocations is, however, difficult due to political barriers faced by the government. In the case where the government acquires land, the owners could potentially be unsatisfied with the compensation amount. As a consequence, this could lead to an enormous waste of tax-payer resources.
Blume, Rubinfeld, and Shaprio (BRS) argue that tax-payer sponsored compensation for land takings by the government is inefficient, since landowners under the perception that their land will be taken overdevelop their properties such that the value of the land is no longer at the social optimum [
22]. Overdevelopment here implies a state where the landowner deliberately reduces the public-use value of the land. BRS further propose that a lump sum payment should only be made if the landowners have made optimal investments in the land. This approach only works if the courts can rely on community standards to determine if the land has experienced overinvestment. Innes further adds that land takings should be avoided unless the public use value is substantially above the private use value to the landowner [
23]. However, his analysis does not elaborate on the precise meaning of “substantial”. Knetsch and Borcherding, and Cooter propose that the government may create an option with the land owners, which allows them to take the land at any time at a pre-arranged price [
24,
25]. Since price is pre-negotiated, land owners will not be undercompensated. However, a major drawback of this approach is that reaching a price agreement may prove to be difficult if the owner receives utility from the land, which is more than a function of the price. Miceli builds on BRS’s analysis to derive a socially optimum compensation strategy, as long as the taken land’s public-use value exceeds the private value to the current owner [
26].
While we have discussed the effectiveness of the Kaldor-Hicks criterion and various compensation strategies, the actual compensation amount given to landowners has often been a source of controversy. For example, Keliang et al. observed that out of 476 expropriation cases in China, a majority of the farmers were undercompensated [
27]. According to the World Bank’s Land and Governance Assessment Framework (LGAF), affected populations in Afghanistan, Brazil, Ethiopia, Nigeria, South Africa, South Sudan, and Tanzania were inadequately compensated for taken land [
28]. Van Eerd and Banerjee found similar cases in Cambodia, Indonesia, Sri Lanka, and the Philippines [
29]. Cernea notes that a lack of adequate compensation for displaced populations might immediately lead to impoverishment, thereby potentially creating a scenario where the social benefits are in fact lower than the social costs [
30]. For example, in India prior to the LARR, 50–55 million people were displaced due to dam construction. According to Cernea, since 2004, 75% of the displaced populace in India has been inadequately compensated.
Our literature review portrays the delicate balance between the need for the development of societal and compensation strategies that must be enacted if the land owners are in fact willing to transact. The following sections show why the Kaldor-Hicks criterion must be invoked prior to the compensation stage.
3. Methodology and Theoretical Model
In this section, we construct a mathematical model to demonstrate the prevailing weaknesses of the “Consent” clause in the LARR Act of 2013. Suppose there are two individuals, a buyer and a land owner. Let index 1 indicate the buyer and 2 indicate the land owner. They both have a concave utility function
(buyer) and
(land-owner). Under the construction of a concave utility function, an increasing amount of a good consumed, in our case land, leads to a higher level of satisfaction, such that
. However, too much consumption is characterized by diminishing returns, which is mathematically represented by
.
5Let
be the total acreage that the land owner possesses, where
is the acreage that the buyer desires and
is the remaining acreage, which the land owner will retain. Each individual’s utility is a function of their post-transaction land ownership. It is implied that acquiring acreage
leaves the buyer with a certain amount of utility
and the land owner with utility
. Other parameters, which might alter the shape of the utility function, are considered later. Let
be the per-acre price of
. We assume that, if given a choice, the land owner would prefer to keep all their land such that
>
.
6 The spatial restraint is:
, indicating that the buyer is only transacting with the current land owner and cannot satisfy their utility requirements by acquiring land from other owners. We also assume that the buyer must obtain their optimal land requirement to maximize their utility function. There are no second-best allocations, which will be agreeable to the buyer. For example, suppose that a private entity requires at least
to complete its project, an allocation less that
would cause an indefinite stoppage. This outcome is unacceptable to the buyer and hence he or she must obtain
.
We define
as the post-transaction ownership vector agreeable to the land owner and
as the vector agreeable to the buyer.
also provides a higher value of output such that:
The function
here represents the monetary value of the allocation, such that social welfare at
(when the buyer acquires her desired allocation) is higher than social welfare at
(when the owner keeps her desired allocation). In real life, we can equate this assumption to the public use value or the opportunity cost of the land. For example, suppose there is a farmer producing
amount of gross domestic product (GDP) on a piece of land. If the land buyer from our current problem uses the same piece of land, then the GDP would be higher. Therefore,
indicates that the allocation
can provide a more efficient social outcome. The two vectors represent two conflicting states:
as state 1 and
as state 2, where land is divided either as
or as
. In state 1, the buyer is only able to acquire
and the land owner keeps
. This transaction is suboptimal for the buyer. In state 2, the buyer obtains their desired land
and the land owner is left with
, a transaction suboptimal for the land owner.
Figure 1 depicts the two states:
Given the assumptions of the post-transaction vectors, it follows that:
implying that the buyer obtains a higher utility if state 1 is realized, where the land allocation is
and vice-versa for the land owner. It is easy to presume that:
, which indicates that
is Pareto preferred to
based on the Kaldor-Hicks compensation criteria. However, we demonstrate that this might not necessarily be the case.
4. Propositions
Proposition 1. Given p as the per-acre price of L, allocation can never be realized with the “Consent” clause.
The objective of the buyer is to acquire
and they are willing to pay
per-acre. We can observe that Equation (2) will never be satisfied if
is the landowner’s final allocation. This is due to the fact that the land owner achieves a higher utility by keeping allocation
. The owner’s utility function is only associated with the land that they own and not by its value. The rationale behind the “Consent” clause in LARR Act of 2013 can be explained by removing this assumption. Recall that under the common assumption of Kaldor-Hicks criterion, if the winners, in this case the buyer, as s/he is obtaining her desired allocation
, can compensate the losers (land-owners), then
is Pareto preferred to
. We postulate this because the land owners’ wealth in state 1 and state 2 remains the same. More formally,
From Equation (3), it is clear that the transaction transfers wealth and does not create it.
7 Under the rationale of the consent clause mandated in the LARR Act of 2013, it must be that:
where
and
are the values of the remaining pieces of land under both the states. Equation (5) demonstrates that the utility of wealth in both states is the same, so the owner would be willing to accept the terms of the transaction. However, Equation (5) does not necessarily imply that:
In Equation (6), the utility of wealth is not similar to the utility of land. This contradiction might arise in a real-life situation. To show this, we return to our private entity example, where the entity makes an offer of per-acre to the land owner. The land owner might be unwilling to sell due to logistical constraints. Say the owner is a farmer and has a successful operation. While s/he gets the market value for her/his land, s/he might not be able to procure a different piece of land to continue her/his farming operation. Due to this difficulty, s/he might not sell her/his land, despite knowing that her/his net wealth would remain the same. There might be counter examples, where an owner’s utility of wealth is equal to their utility of land and therefore a compensation of per-acre is acceptable to them. But such a solution would not work from the government’s viewpoint as it would create an uncertainty in the transaction. The wording of the “Consent” clause leaves acceptance up to the owner, which might result in the inefficient social allocation .
Proposition 2. There is no price under the “Consent” clause such that: We now consider the case where the buyer offers a price , which satisfies or overcomes the utility of the land restraint in Equation (5). This proposition considers the case of offering a higher compensation price to make Pareto preferred to . It is conceivable that several owners who were reluctant to sell earlier are now swayed towards acceptance. Yet due to the presence of the “Consent” clause, there will remain a few or several owners who will not accept the trade, since Therefore, price remains an inefficient price from the government’s viewpoint, as some owners will always reject any transaction.
Proposition 3. The removal of the “Consent” clause is a necessary yet insufficient condition for social welfare maximization.
Following the conclusion of proposition 1 and 2, we observe the difficulties that the “Consent” clause poses for attaining the preferred allocation . Both propositions convey that there is no compensation price, which satisfies every land owner in the society. If the power is left in the hands of the land owners, then a transaction guaranteeing a more efficient allocation of a land parcel can be vetoed.
We now assume that the “Consent” clause is removed as was desired by the amendment Bill of 2015 and allocation is achieved with the buyer paying per-acre to acquire . Since social welfare is higher. However, forcing the land owners to concede is only a necessary and not sufficient condition for social welfare maximization. This follows from the fact that the land owners no longer possess their first-choice allocation. Hence, social welfare is higher at than at , but is not Pareto or Kaldor-Hicks efficient and social welfare is not maximized. Recall that this is employing the Kaldor-Hicks criterion, since social welfare is higher at
Proposition 4. Is there an amount , with which the government compensates the land owners such that social welfare is maximized at the Pareto preferred allocation , thus satisfying Kaldor-Hicks efficiency?
The buyer has no incentive to pay above the market price
to procure the land, since the lack of a consent clause ensures that the land is sold through eminent domain. It is the only price that maximizes the buyer’s profit function.
8 However, the choice of
may negatively impact the income distribution and consequently prevent social welfare maximization. Therefore, it is the government’s responsibility to determine a compensation amount
, which maximizes the collective utilities of all the individuals in the society.
9 Let
be a linear social welfare function, such that:
subject to,
W is a utilitarian function, with the sum of weighted individual utility functions, and
represents the welfare weights that are assumed to be the inverse of the marginal utility of incomes (MUI).
10 By construction, this implies that
.
is the post-transaction allocation vector of all the individuals;
is the compensation amount that the government must decide to give to the affected individuals; and
is the total budget available to the government for the compensations.
Equation (8) requires the government to maximize the social wealth function of the society, by choosing
q. Solving (8) leads to an optimal compensation amount, which is a function of
,
, and
B. More formally,
Recall that is a parameter here, since the individual land allocations have already been decided. is the parameter of interest in this problem and its presence in Equation (10) implies that the compensation amount must depend on the income distribution of the owners whose land is acquired. An individual’s marginal utility of income varies with their position on the wealth distribution. We expect a high-income individual (suppose an industrialist) to have a lower marginal utility of income, since a gain of an additional unit of income leads to minimal utility gains. Whereas, a low-income farmer values that additional unit much more than an industrialist. Therefore, if the government forcefully acquires land from an individual who lies on the bottom-half of the income distribution, he or she deserves more compensation than someone who resides in the upper-half. The compensation distribution should mirror the income distribution so that Equation (8) is maximized. In the current wording of the LARR Act of 2013, the market value of land is multiplied by a factor of up to 2 if the land is acquired in rural areas. Special provisions have also been made for lower-caste individuals. However, the Act does not explicitly incorporate compensation based on the income distribution.
In the above analysis, is assumed to be exogenous, signifying that the government is not concerned about where the funds for compensation come from. In reality, we know that the compensation will be funded by tax-payers of India and therefore B is endogenous. If B is assumed to be endogenous, then the optimal compensation will differ, so we call it . This is due to the altered budget constraint. The income distribution will be influenced by taxation, which subsequently has an impact on the marginal utilities of income. While qualitatively there is no difference between and , the quantitative values of both will be different. The precise structural specification of both and is beyond the scope of this article.
While this proposition offers a sound compensation strategy, we require quantitative measures of to convince policymakers. Finding empirical values of is difficult without the policy being enacted. Therefore, we would have to rely on a simulation exercise, where we estimate MUI weights from the income distribution. For this exercise, we require precise income and land value data, at least at the district level, in order to determine representative MUI weight measures, which is beyond the scope of the current study.
5. Simulation Exercise for Proposition 4
In this section, we present a two-person simulation approach for obtaining the MUI weights:
mentioned in proposition 4. Suppose the functional form of
is linear-additive in Equation (8), such that
. Let
and the total compensation budget be
$500. Equation (8) can then be written as:
such that (from Equation (9))
Now assume that the maximum possible value for
is bounded at some finite utility level
and the maximum possible budget is
$500. Further suppose that prior data indicates that person 1 has a marginally higher household income than person 2, implying that the compensation vector will satisfy:
. For this simulation, we assume that:
where
are the household incomes of persons 1 and 2, respectively. Equation (14) shows that person 1’s income is assumed to be
of person 2’s income. Therefore, the objective function is specified in Equation (11) and the constraints are in (12)–(14). Recall that according to the Kaldor-Hicks criterion:
must hold for efficiency. Next, we run the above model in the statistical software R (see code in the
Appendix). The results from the simulation are presented in the
Table 1 below.
We can clearly see that the objective function in Equation (11) is maximized when
and
.
11 The optimal values of the compensation vector are
$235.29 and
$264.70, which satisfy are assumed constraint:
and allocate the entire budget for compensation. These values are in line with the theoretical specification of our model illustrated in proposition 4. Note that social welfare is maximized when the MUI weight is most skewed in favor of the low-income household.
6. Conclusions
India is a developing economy and due to stable population growth, large scale industrialization is required to keep the GDP growth rate positive. The LARR Act of 2013 is a huge step in the correct direction and the amendment bill, as shown through the propositions, might have enhanced the effectiveness of the Act. It would have ensured faster development of the manufacturing sector and Special Economic Zones (SEZs), which might lead to a higher job and GDP growth rate. While concerns relating to the small scale agricultural producers and poor land owners in general are valid, the potential benefits of the removal of the consent clause cannot be discounted. The government of India, after its failure to pass the proposed amendment bill, introduced the Model Leasing Act (2016), which intends to skirt the problem of forced land acquisition. This Act would allow the government to lease land for development at the market rental rate for a fixed duration. The land owners will retain full ownership under this Act. While this solution may seem favorable, the long-term costs to the tax-payers have not been examined.
The Kaldor-Hicks criterion is a potent decision tool available to any national government. Unlike Pareto efficiency, where optimal outcomes for each member of the society are a pre-requisite for any policy to be implemented, the Kaldor-Hicks criterion allows the government to make a decision by comparing the policy’s benefits to its costs. This approach permits faster developmental possibilities and forces the government to consider the current and long-term benefits and costs of a policy. However, we do not deny the shortcomings of the criterion. Since the criterion relies heavily on wealth and utility maximization, the distributional effects of a policy are ignored in favor of total benefits. It is possible that the benefits and costs are interpreted differently under wealth maximization and utility maximization. For example: if a private land buyer succeeds in obtaining her desired allocation and only produces value for herself, which exceeds the total costs to the government and/or landowners, then the Kaldor-Hicks efficiency would have been achieved, since wealth was maximized. However, under utility maximization, a single land buyer gaining land for private use would never exceed the collective utilities of several landowners, irrespective of the value generated and thus not Kaldor-Hicks efficient. This is why we chose utility maximization to develop our propositions, since total utility from potential land acquisition should exceed the sum of landowners’ lost utility and the compensation disbursed by the government.
In this article, we derive conditions based on the Kaldor-Hicks criterion to show that removing the “Consent” clause is necessary for social welfare maximization. The presence of the “Consent” clause can lead to failed transactions and productivity losses for the economy. Some owners will always agree to the transaction and the compensation terms in the original Act of 2013, which as we observed, could potentially induce inefficient compensation from the government, yet some owners will always decline any transaction irrespective of the compensation on offer. Given this scenario, the removal of the “Consent” clause coupled with a compensation based on the marginal utility of income is an effective policy solution. Compensation based on income distribution might be politically difficult to implement, since the biggest conflicts may arise between mid-income and poor farmers or landowners. Mid-income farmers may feel that they are being treated unfairly, despite it being optimal from the government’s viewpoint. In view of such disagreements, the government’s decision to offer higher compensation to rural land owners is unsurprising. However, we maintain that compensation based on marginal utility of income is the correct approach as it maximizes social welfare, as seen from the simulation exercise, and helps maintain a balanced budget.