Next Article in Journal
The Existence of Nontrivial Solution for a Class of Kirchhoff-Type Equation of General Convolution Nonlinearity without Any Growth Conditions
Next Article in Special Issue
SAIPO-TAIPO and Genetic Algorithms for Investment Portfolios
Previous Article in Journal
Critical Indices and Self-Similar Power Transform
Previous Article in Special Issue
Transdisciplinary Scientific Strategies for Soft Computing Development: Towards an Era of Data and Business Analytics
 
 
Font Type:
Arial Georgia Verdana
Font Size:
Aa Aa Aa
Line Spacing:
Column Width:
Background:
Article

Rough Approximation Operators on a Complete Orthomodular Lattice

School of Electronics and Information Engineering, Taizhou University, Taizhou 318000, China
Axioms 2021, 10(3), 164; https://doi.org/10.3390/axioms10030164
Submission received: 3 June 2021 / Revised: 19 July 2021 / Accepted: 26 July 2021 / Published: 27 July 2021
(This article belongs to the Special Issue Softcomputing: Theories and Applications II)

Abstract

:
This paper studies rough approximation via join and meet on a complete orthomodular lattice. Different from Boolean algebra, the distributive law of join over meet does not hold in orthomodular lattices. Some properties of rough approximation rely on the distributive law. Furthermore, we study the relationship among the distributive law, rough approximation and orthomodular lattice-valued relation.

1. Introduction

In 1982, Pawlak [1] proposed rough set theory as an excellent tool for incomplete information processing. Since then, a series of works describe rough sets relying on the mathematical structure of the set, such as logics [2,3,4], algebraic and topological structures [5,6]. Rough sets over different mathematical structures have different properties. In particular, rough sets over Boolean algebra [7,8], lattice effect algebra [9], residuated lattices [10,11,12,13,14,15,16] and other lattices [17,18,19] have been studied.
In 1936, Birkhoff and von Neumann [20] considered the orthomodular lattice as quantum logic for studying the algebraic structure of quantum mechanics. There are many extensions of Pawlak’s rough set, such as fuzzy rough sets [21,22], covering based rough sets [23,24,25], probabilistic rough sets [26,27], soft rough sets [28,29,30,31], Diophantine fuzzy rough sets [32,33,34,35], multi-granulation rough sets [36,37,38], hesitant fuzzy rough set [39] and so on. However, as far as I know, there is only a little literature addressing the rough sets and quantum logics together. In 2017, Hassan [40] considered a rough set classification method via quantum logic. In our previous work [41], we proposed rough set via join and meet on a complete orthomodular lattice (COL). Since orthomodular lattices are different from Boolean algebras, in particular, the distributive law not hold in orthomodular lattices, then we find many basic properties of rough sets rely on the distributive law. Obviously, the underlying laws of logic play an important part in the concept of rough approximations. However, sometimes the underlying laws of logic were taken for granted in rough approximations based on logics. In order to enhance the importance of the underlying laws of logic in rough set theory, a useful method is set up based on the equivalence between the underlying laws of logic and the basic properties of rough approximations. Note that Pawlak’s rough sets also rely on the equivalence relation. In this paper, we studied the relations among the distributive law, rough approximations and lattice-valued relation. Moreover, some topological structures of orthomodular lattice-valued rough approximations are investigated.
The paper is organized as follows: In Section 2, we recall definitions of orthomodular lattices and orthomodular lattice-valued rough approximations. In Section 3, we study the relationship among the distributive law, rough approximations and lattice-valued relations. In Section 4 is the conclusion.

2. Preliminaries

2.1. Orthomodular Lattices

First, we recall definitions of orthomodular lattices, for details see [42,43,44,45,46,47,48].
A COL L = L , , , , , 0 , 1 is a complete bounded lattice and unary operator ⊥ has the following properties: for all η , ξ L
(1)
η η = 1 , η η = 0 ;
(2)
η = η ;
(3)
η ξ ξ η ;
(4)
η ξ η ( η ξ ) = ξ .
The property (4) is the orthomodular law, denoted by (OL). It is weaker than the distributive law, denoted by DL, which is not valid in orthomodular lattice.
An orthomodular lattice-valued set (l-valued set for short) is a mapping E : U L , where U is a finite universe. For any a L , a ^ is the constant l-valued set, i.e., a ^ ( x ) = a , x U . Similarly, an orthomodular lattice-valued relation (l-valued relation for short) on U is a mapping E : U × U L . We say R is serial, if y U R ( x , y ) = 1 for all x U . We say R is transitive, if R ( α , γ ) β U R ( α , β ) R ( β , γ ) for all α , β , γ U .

2.2. Rough Approximations on a COL

Then, we recall the rough approximations on a COL [41].
Definition 1
([41]). Let L be a COL and R be an L-valued relation on a finite universe U. With each L-valued set E on U, the lower approximation operator (LAO) and the upper approximation operator (UAO) of E are defined, respectively, as follows:
L R ( E ) ( μ ) = ν U R ( μ , ν ) E ( ν ) , μ U
and
T R ( E ) ( μ ) = ν U R ( μ , ν ) E ( ν ) , μ U .
The pair L R ( E ) , T R ( E ) is a L valued rough set of E relative to COL L.
Example 1.
Let C be the set of complex numbers. In the complex Hilbert space 2 C 2 , | 00 , | 01 , | 10 and | 11 represent its orthonormal base. ρ i j = s p a n { | i j } is denoted the subspace spanned by | i j , i , j = 0 , 1 . For any closed subspace G and H of 2 C 2 , G H if the subspace G is included in H, ∧ is intersection of subspaces, ∨ is union of subspaces, G is the orthogonal space of G, 0 is the zero subspace and 1 is 2 C 2 . Then L 2 = L 2 , , , , , 0 , 1 is a COL, where L 2 is the set of all closed subspaces of 2 C 2 , more details see [43,47].
We define an COL-valued rough approximation whose truth value is a closed subspace of 2 C 2 . Let U = { p , q } , R ( p , p ) = R ( q , q ) = 1 and R ( p , q ) = R ( q , p ) = v 01 . Moreover, define E : U L 2 as E ( p ) = v 00 , E ( q ) = v 11 . Then
  • T R ( E ) ( p ) = ( R ( p , p ) E ( p ) ) ( R ( p , q ) E ( q ) ) = ( 1 v 00 ) ( v 01 v 11 ) = v 00
  • T R ( E ) ( q ) = ( R ( q , p ) E ( p ) ) ( R ( q , q ) E ( q ) ) = ( v 01 v 00 ) ( 1 v 11 ) = v 11
  • L R ( E ) ( p ) = ( R ( p , p ) E ( p ) ) ( R ( p , q ) E ( q ) ) = ( 1 v 00 ) ( v 01 v 11 ) = 0
  • L R ( E ) ( q ) = ( R ( q , p ) E ( p ) ) ( R ( q , q ) E ( q ) ) = ( v 01 v 00 ) ( 1 v 11 ) = 0
Example 2.
Consider the smallest OL which is not a Boolean algebra, called M O 2 [49], as shown in Figure 1. Let the universe U = { u 1 , u 2 , u 3 } . Define a L-valued set
E = a u 1 + a u 2 + b u 3
and a L-valued relation R on M O 2 in Table 1. Thus, we have
L R ( E ) ( μ 1 ) = R ( μ 1 , μ 1 ) E ( μ 1 ) R ( μ 1 , μ 2 ) E ( μ 2 ) R ( μ 1 , μ 3 ) E ( μ 3 ) = 1 a 0 a ) 0 b = a 1 1 = a L R ( E ) ( μ 2 ) = R ( μ 2 , μ 1 ) E ( μ 1 ) R ( μ 2 , μ 2 ) E ( μ 2 ) R ( μ 2 , μ 3 ) E ( μ 3 ) = 0 a a a ) 0 b = 1 a 1 = a L R ( E ) ( μ 3 ) = R ( μ 3 , μ 1 ) E ( μ 1 ) R ( μ 3 , μ 2 ) E ( μ 2 ) R ( μ 3 , μ 3 ) E ( μ 3 ) = 0 a 0 a ) b b = 1 1 1 = 1 T R ( E ) ( μ 1 ) = R ( μ 1 , μ 1 ) E ( μ 1 ) R ( μ 1 , μ 2 ) E ( μ 2 ) R ( μ 1 , μ 3 ) E ( μ 3 ) = 1 a 0 a ) 0 b = a 0 0 = a T R ( E ) ( μ 2 ) = R ( μ 2 , μ 1 ) E ( μ 1 ) R ( μ 2 , μ 2 ) E ( μ 2 ) R ( μ 2 , μ 3 ) E ( μ 3 ) = 0 a a a ) 0 b = 0 0 0 = 0 T R ( E ) ( μ 3 ) = R ( μ 3 , μ 1 ) E ( μ 1 ) R ( μ 3 , μ 2 ) E ( μ 2 ) R ( μ 3 , μ 3 ) E ( μ 3 ) = 0 a 0 a ) b b = 0 0 b = b .

3. Relation among the Distributive Law, Rough Approximations and Lattice-Valued Relations

First, we give some relation between distributive law and rough approximations.
Proposition 1.
The following three statements are equivalent:
(1) 
L satisfies DL.
(2) 
T R ( E F ) ( T R ( E ) T R ( F ) ) .
(3) 
L R ( E F ) ( L R ( E ) L R ( F ) ) .
Proof. 
( 1 ) ( 2 ) : By using the distributive law of meet over join, we have
T R ( E F ) ( x ) = y U ( R ( x , y ) ( E F ) ( y ) ) = y U ( R ( x , y ) ( E ( y ) F ( y ) ) ) = y U ( ( R ( x , y ) E ( y ) ) ( R ( x , y ) F ( y ) ) ) = ( T R ( E ) T R ( F ) ) ( x ) .
( 2 ) ( 1 ) : Our purpose is to show a ( b c ) = ( a b ) ( a c ) , a , b , c L . Put R ( x , y 1 ) = a , and R ( x , y ) = 0 for other y U ; E ( y 1 ) = b , F ( y 1 ) = c , and E ( y ) = F ( y ) = 0 for other y U . Then, we have
T R ( E F ) ( x ) = y U ( R ( x , y ) ( E F ) ( y ) ) = R ( x , y 1 ) ( E F ) ( y 1 ) = a ( b c ) .
and
( T R ( E ) T R ( F ) ) ( x ) = T R ( E ) ( x ) T R ( F ) ( x ) = y U ( R ( x , y ) E ( y ) ) y U ( R ( x , y ) F ( y ) ) = R ( x , y 1 ) E ( y 1 ) R ( x , y 1 ) F ( y 1 ) = ( a b ) ( a c )
Therefore, we obtain a ( b c ) = ( a b ) ( a c ) from (2).
( 1 ) ( 3 ) : By using the distributive law of join over meet,
L R ( F F ) ( x ) = y U R ( x , y ) ( E F ) ( y ) = y U ( R ( x , y ) ( E ( y ) F ( y ) ) ) = y U ( R ( x , y ) E ( y ) R ( x , y ) F ( y ) ) = ( L R ( E ) L R ( F ) ) ( x ) .
( 3 ) ( 1 ) : Similarly, our purpose is to show a ( b c ) = ( a b ) ( a c ) , a , b , c L . Let R ( x , y 1 ) = a , and R ( x , y ) = 1 for other y U ; E ( y 1 ) = b , F ( y 1 ) = c , and E ( y ) = F ( y ) = 1 for other y U . Then,
L R ( E F ) ( x ) = y U ( R ( x , y ) ( E F ) ( y ) ) = R ( x , y 1 ) ( E ( y 1 ) F ( y 1 ) ) = a ( b c ) .
and
( L R ( E ) L R ( F ) ) ( x ) = L R ( E ) ( x ) L R ( F ) ( x ) = y U ( R ( x , y ) E ( y ) ) y U ( R ( x , y ) F ( y ) ) = R ( x , y 1 ) E ( y 1 ) R ( x , y 1 ) F ( y 1 ) = ( a b ) ( a c )
Therefore, we obtain a ( b c ) = ( a b ) ( a c ) from (3). □
The following results are also based on the distributive law of join over meet.
Proposition 2.
If L satisfies DL, then the following three statements are equivalent
(1) 
R is serial, i.e., y U R ( x , y ) = 1 for all x U .
(2) 
T R ( a ^ ) a ^ , for any a L .
(3) 
L R ( a ^ ) a ^ , for any a L .
Proof. 
( 1 ) ( 2 ) : By using the distributive law of join over meet, we have
T R ( a ^ ) ( x ) = y U R ( x , y ) a ^ ( y ) = y U R ( x , y ) a = a y U R ( x , y ) = a 1 = a .
( 2 ) ( 1 ) : Take a = 1 ; then it follows from the proof of necessity and T R ( 1 ^ ) ( x ) = 1 for every x X that y U R ( x , y ) = 1 holds for every x U . Hence R is serial.
Similarly, we can prove ( 1 ) ( 3 ) . □
Now, we study the relationship among the distributive law, rough approximation and COL-valued relation.
Proposition 3.
If two of the following statements hold, then the third statement holds:
(1) 
L satisfies DL.
(2) 
R is transitive, i.e., R ( α , γ ) β U R ( α , β ) R ( β , γ ) holds for all α , β , γ U .
(3) 
T R ( T R ( E ) ) T R ( E ) .
Proof. 
( 1 ) + ( 2 ) ( 3 ) : By using the distributive law of join over meet, we have
T R ( T R ( E ) ) ( x ) = y U ( R ( x , y ) T R ( E ) ( y ) ) = y U ( R ( x , y ) ( z U ( R ( y , z ) E ( z ) ) ) ) = z U ( y U ( R ( x , y ) R ( y , z ) ) E ( z ) ) z U ( R ( x , z ) E ( z ) ) = T R ( E ) ( x ) .
( 1 ) + ( 3 ) ( 2 ) : Assume that R is not transitive. It follows than that for some x 0 , z 0 U , y U ( R ( x 0 , y ) R ( y , z 0 ) ) R ( x 0 , z 0 ) is not hold.
Let E ( z 0 ) = 1 and E ( y ) = 0 for other y U . Then, we have
T R ( T R ( E ) ) ( x 0 ) = y U ( R ( x 0 , y ) R ( y , z 0 ) )
and
T R ( E ) ( x 0 ) = R ( x 0 , z 0 ) .
Therefore, it follows from (3) that y U ( R ( x 0 , y ) R ( y , z 0 ) ) R ( x 0 , z 0 ) .
( 2 ) + ( 3 ) ( 1 ) : Given a , b , c L , let U = x , y , z , R L U × U which R ( x , y ) = R ( x , z ) = a , R ( y , z ) = R ( z , z ) = b , R ( z , y ) = R ( y , y ) = c and others are o, and E L U which E ( y ) = c , E ( z ) = b , E ( x ) = 0 . It easy to see R is transitive. Then, we have
T R ( E ) ( x ) = ( R ( x , y ) E ( y ) ) ( R ( x , z ) E ( z ) ) = ( a c ) ( a b ) ,
T R ( E ) ( y ) = ( R ( y , y ) E ( y ) ) ( R ( y , z ) E ( z ) ) = b c ,
T R ( E ) ( z ) = ( R ( z , z ) E ( z ) ) ( R ( z , y ) E ( y ) ) = b c ,
and
T R ( T R ( E ) ) ( x ) = ( R ( x , y ) T R ( E ) ( y ) ) ( R ( x , z ) T R ( E ) ( z ) ) = ( a ( b c ) ) ( a ( b c ) ) = a ( b c ) .
Therefore, by T R ( T R ( E ) ) ( x ) T R ( E ) ( x ) we obtain ( a ( b c ) ) ( ( a c ) ( a b ) ) .
Since ( a ( b c ) ) ( ( a b ) ( a c ) ) always holds. Thus a ( b c ) = ( a b ) ( a c ) .
 □
Proposition 4.
If two of the following statements hold, then the third statement holds:
(1) 
L satisfies DL.
(2) 
R is transitive.
(3) 
L R ( E ) L R ( L R ( E ) ) .
Proof. 
Similar to Proposition 3. □
Propositions 3 and 4 give some basic properties of rough approximations that do not only rely on the binary relation but also on the distributive law.
Definition 2
([50]). Let U be a non-empty set, a function i n : L U L U is an l valued interior operator if and only if (iff) for all E , F L U it satisfies:
(1) i n ( a ^ ) = a ^ ;
(2) i n ( E ) E ;
(3) i n ( E F ) = i n ( E ) i n ( F ) ;
(4) i n ( i n ( E ) ) = i n ( E ) ;
Definition 3
([50]). Let U be a non-empty set, a function c l : L U L U is an l valued closure operator iff for all E , F L U it satisfies:
(1) c l ( a ^ ) = a ^ ;
(2) E c l ( E ) ;
(3) c l ( E F ) = c l ( E ) c l ( F ) ;
(4) c l ( c l ( E ) ) = c l ( E ) ;
Proposition 5.
If two of the following statements hold, then the third statement holds:
(1) L satisfies DL.
(2) R is serial and transitive.
(3) L R is an l valued interior operator.
Proof. 
Immediate from Proposition 1 of [41] and Propositions 1, 2 and 4. □
Note that DL is also a condition of that lower rough approximation is an interior operator.
Proposition 6.
If two of the following statements hold, then the third statement holds:
(1) L satisfies DL.
(2) R is serial and transitive.
(3) T R is an l valued closure operator.
Proof. 
Immediate from Proposition 1 of [41] and Propositions 1, 2 and 3. □
Similar to Propositions 3 and 4, Propositions 5 and 6 also show that some topology properties of rough approximations that do not only rely on the binary relation but also on the distributive law.
Example 3.
Consider a L-valued relation R on M O 2 in Table 2.
Then L R and T R , respectively, are l valued interior operator and l valued closure operator for any l-valued set E : U M O 2 .
Moreover, if we use the following definitions of l valued interior operator and l valued closure operator which are weaker than Definitions 2 and 3, respectively.
Definition 4.
Let U be a non-empty set, a function i n : L U L U is an l valued interior operator iff for all E , F L U it satisfies:
(1) i n ( 0 ^ ) = 0 ^ ;
(2) i n ( E ) E ;
(3) i n ( E F ) = i n ( E ) i n ( F ) ;
(4) i n ( i n ( E ) ) = i n ( E ) ;
Definition 5.
Let U be a non-empty set, a function c l : L U L U is an l valued closure operator iff for all E , F L U it satisfies:
(1) c l ( 1 ^ ) = 1 ^ ;
(2) E c l ( E ) ;
(3) c l ( E F ) = c l ( E ) c l ( F ) ;
(4) c l ( c l ( E ) ) = c l ( E ) ;
Then, we have the following results.
Proposition 7.
If two of the following statements hold, then the third statement holds:
(1) L satisfies DL.
(2) R is transitive.
(3) L R is an l valued interior operator.
Proof. 
Immediate from Proposition 1 of [41] and Propositions 1 and 4. □
Proposition 8.
If two of the following statements hold, then the third statement holds:
(1) L satisfies DL.
(2) R is transitive.
(3) T R is an l valued closure operator.
Proof. 
Immediate from Proposition 1 of [41] and Propositions 1 and 3. □
Example 4.
Consider a L-valued relation R on M O 2 in Table 3.
Then L R is an l valued interior operator of Defintion 4 but is not an l valued interior operator of Defintion 2, and T R is an l valued closure operator of Defintion 5 but is not an l valued closure operator of Defintion 3.

4. Conclusions

In this paper, we studied COL-valued rough approximation. Some properties of rough approximations rely on DL of ∨ over ∧ and binary relation. Obviously, the distributive law plays an important part in the operation of rough approximations. Many basic properties of rough approximations do not only rely on the binary relation but also on the distributive law (see Propositions 2–4). Moreover, some topology properties of rough approximations do not only rely on the binary relation but also on the distributive law (see Propositions 5–8).
Orthomodular lattices can be viewed as a sharp quantum structure. There is another concrete or standard quantum logic, called unsharp quantum logics which do not satisfy the non-contradiction principle [49]. Proceeding from this angle, we can study the rough approximations based on unsharp quantum logics as future work.

Funding

This research was funded by the National Science Foundation of China under Grant No. 62006168 and Zhejiang Provincial Natural Science Foundation of China under Grant No. LQ21A010001.

Data Availability Statement

Not applicable.

Conflicts of Interest

The authors declare no conflict of interest.

Abbreviations

The following abbreviations are used in this manuscript:
COLcomplete orthomodular lattice
OLorthomodular law
DLdistributive law
LAOlower approximation operator
UAOupper approximation operator
iffif and only if

References

  1. Pawlak, Z. Rough sets. Int. J. Comput. Inf. Sci. 1982, 11, 341–356. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  2. Rauszer, C. An equivalence between theory of functional dependence and a fragment of intuitionistic logic. Bull. Pol. Acad. Sci. Math. 1985, 33, 571–579. [Google Scholar]
  3. Vakarelov, D. A modal logic for similarity relations in Pawlak knowledge representation systems. Fundam. Inform. 1991, 15, 61–79. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  4. Vakarelov, D. Modal logics for knowledge representation systems. Theor. Comput. Sci. 1991, 90, 433–456. [Google Scholar]
  5. Yao, Y.Y. Constructive and algebraic methods of the theory of rough sets. Inf. Sci. 1998, 109, 21–47. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  6. Pei, Z.; Pei, D.; Zheng, L. Topology vs. generalized rough sets. Int. J. Approx. Reason. 2011, 52, 231–239. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
  7. Pawlak, Z.; Skowron, A. Rough sets and boolean reasoning. Inf. Sci. 2007, 177, 41–73. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
  8. Qi, G.; Liu, W. Rough operations on Boolean algebras. Inf. Sci. 2005, 173, 49–63. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
  9. Hua, X. Fuzzy rough set based on lattice effect algebra. J. Intell. Fuzzy Syst. 2019, 36, 29–36. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  10. Radzikowska, A.M.; Kerre, E.E. Fuzzy rough sets based on residuated lattices. Trans. Rough Sets Lect. Notes Comput. Sci. 2004, 3135, 278–296. [Google Scholar]
  11. Bao, Y.; Yang, H.; She, Y. Using one axiom to characterize L-fuzzy rough approximation operators based on residuated lattices. Fuzzy Sets Syst. 2018, 336, 87–115. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  12. Yin, Y.Q.; Huang, X.K. Fuzzy Roughness in hyperrings based on a complete residuated lattice. Int. J. Fuzzy Syst. 2010, 13, 185–194. [Google Scholar]
  13. Yin, Y.Q.; Zhan, J.M.; Corsini, P. Fuzzy roughness of n-ary hypergroups based on a complete residuated lattice. Neural Comput. Appl. 2011, 20, 41–57. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  14. Wang, C.Y.; Hu, B.Q. Fuzzy rough sets based on generalized residuated lattices. Inf. Sci. 2013, 248, 31–49. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  15. She, Y.H.; Wang, G.J. An axiomatic approach of fuzzy rough sets based on residuated lattices. Comput. Math. Appl. 2009, 58, 189–201. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
  16. Jiang, H.; Zhan, J.; Chen, D. Covering-based variable precision L-fuzzy rough sets based on residuated lattices and corresponding applications. Int. J. Mach. Learn. Cybern. 2021, 12, 2407–2429. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  17. Chen, D.; Zhang, W.; Yeung, D.; Tsang, E.C.C. Rough approximations on a complete completely distributive lattice with applications to generalized rough sets. Inf. Sci. 2006, 176, 1829–1848. [Google Scholar]
  18. Liu, G.L. Generalized rough sets over fuzzy lattices. Inf. Sci. 2008, 178, 1651–1662. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  19. Ma, L.W. Two fuzzy covering rough set models and their generalizations over fuzzy lattices. Fuzzy Sets Syst. 2016, 294, 1–17. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  20. Birkhoff, G.; von Neumann, J. The logic of quantum mechanics. Ann. Math. 1936, 37, 823–843. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  21. Li, T.; Leung, Y.; Zhang, W. Generalized fuzzy rough approximation operators based on fuzzy coverings. Int. J. Approx. Reason 2008, 48, 836–856. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
  22. Dubois, D.; Prade, H. Rough fuzzy sets and fuzzy rough sets. Int. J. Gen. Syst. 1990, 17, 191–209. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  23. Yang, B.; Hu, B.Q. Matrix representations and interdependency on L-fuzzy covering-based approximation operators. Int. J. Approx. Reason. 2018, 96, 57–77. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  24. Li, L.Q.; Jin, Q.; Hu, K.; Zhao, F.F. The axiomatic characterizations on L-fuzzy covering-based approximation operators. Int. J. Gen. Syst. 2017, 46, 332–353. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  25. Yao, Y.; Yao, B. Covering based rough set approximations. Inf. Sci. 2012, 200, 91–107. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  26. Yao, Y. The superiority of three-way decisions in probabilistic rough set models. Inf. Sci. 2011, 180, 1080–1096. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  27. Yao, Y. Three-way decisions with probabilistic rough sets. Inf. Sci. 2010, 180, 341–352. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
  28. Ali, M.I. A note on soft sets, rough soft sets and fuzzy soft sets. Appl. Soft Comput. 2011, 11, 3329–3332. [Google Scholar]
  29. Feng, F.; Li, C.; Davvaz, B.; Ali, M.I. Soft sets combined with fuzzy sets and rough sets: A tentative approach. Soft Comput. 2010, 14, 899–911. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  30. Kanwal, R.S.; Shabir, M. Rough approximation of a fuzzy set in semigroups based on soft relations. Comput. Appl. Math. 2019, 38, 1–23. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  31. Riaz, M.; Karaaslan, F.; Nawaz, I.; Sohail, M. Soft multi-rough set topology with applications to multi-criteria decision-making problems. Soft Comput. 2021, 25, 799–815. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  32. Riaz, M.; Hashmi, M.R.; Kalsoom, H.; Pamucar, D.; Chu, Y.M. Linear Diophantine fuzzy soft rough sets for the selection of sustainable material handling equipment. Symmetry 2020, 12, 1215. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  33. Ayub, S.; Shabir, M.; Riaz, M.; Aslam, M.; Chinram, R. Linear Diophantine Fuzzy Relations and Their Algebraic Properties with Decision Making. Symmetry 2021, 13, 945. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  34. Riaz, M.; Hashmi, M.R.; Pamucar, D.; Chu, Y.M. Spherical linear Diophantine fuzzy sets with modeling uncertainties in MCDM. Comput. Modeling Eng. Sci. 2021, 126, 1125–1164. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  35. Riaz, M.; Hashmi, M.R. Linear Diophantine fuzzy set and its applications towards multi-attribute decision-making problems. J. Intell. Fuzzy Syst. 2019, 37, 5417–5439. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  36. Sun, B.; Ma, W.; Xiao, X. Three-way group decision making based on multigranulation fuzzy decision-theoretic rough set over two universes. Int. J. Approx. Reason. 2017, 81, 87–102. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  37. Qian, Y.; Zhang, H.; Sang, Y.; Liang, J. Multigranulation decision theoretic rough sets. Int. J. Approx. Reason. 2014, 55, 225–237. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  38. Kong, Q.; Xu, W. The comparative study of covering rough sets and multi-granulation rough sets. Soft Comput. 2019, 23, 3237–3251. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  39. Ma, W.; Lei, W.; Sun, B. Three-way group decisions based on multigranulation hesitant fuzzy decision-theoretic rough set over two universes. J. Intell. Fuzzy Syst. 2020, 38, 2165–2179. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  40. Hassan, Y.F. Rough set classification based on quantum logic. J. Exp. Theor. Artif. Intell. 2017, 29, 1325–1336. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  41. Dai, S. Topological characterizations of rough set theory based on quantum logic. New Math. Nat. Comput. 2021. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  42. Pták, P.; Pulmannová, S. Orthomodular Structures as Quantum Logics; Kluwer: Dordrecht, The Netherlands, 1991. [Google Scholar]
  43. Mittelstaedt, P. Quantum Logic; D. Reidel: Dordrecht, The Netherlands, 1978. [Google Scholar]
  44. Ying, M.S. Automata theory based on quantum logic (I). Int. J. Theor. Phys. 2000, 39, 985–995. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  45. Ying, M.S. Automata theory based on quantum logic (II). Int. J. Theor. Phys. 2000, 39, 2545–2557. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  46. Ying, M.S. A theory of computation based on quantum logic(I). Theor. Comput. Sci. 2005, 344, 134–207. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
  47. Qiu, D.W. Notes on automata theory based on quantum logic. Sci. China Ser. F Inf. Sci. 2007, 50, 154–169. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  48. Dai, S. A note on implication operators of quantum logic. Quantum Mach. Intell. 2020, 2, 15. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  49. Chiara, M.L.D.; Giuntini, R.; Greechie, R. Reasoning in Quantum Theory: Sharp and Unsharp Quantum Logics; Springer: Berlin/Heidelberg, Germany, 2004. [Google Scholar]
  50. Davey, B.A.; Priestley, H.A. Introduction to Lattices and Order; Cambridge University Press: Cambridge, UK, 2002. [Google Scholar]
Figure 1. Orthomodular lattice M O 2 [49].
Figure 1. Orthomodular lattice M O 2 [49].
Axioms 10 00164 g001
Table 1. The L-valued relation R in Example 2.
Table 1. The L-valued relation R in Example 2.
R u 1 u 2 u 3
u 1 100
u 2 0a0
u 3 00b
Table 2. The L-valued relation R in Example 3.
Table 2. The L-valued relation R in Example 3.
R u 1 u 2 u 3
u 1 100
u 2 010
u 3 001
Table 3. The L-valued relation R in Example 4.
Table 3. The L-valued relation R in Example 4.
R u 1 u 2 u 3
u 1 a00
u 2 0a0
u 3 00a
Publisher’s Note: MDPI stays neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Share and Cite

MDPI and ACS Style

Dai, S. Rough Approximation Operators on a Complete Orthomodular Lattice. Axioms 2021, 10, 164. https://doi.org/10.3390/axioms10030164

AMA Style

Dai S. Rough Approximation Operators on a Complete Orthomodular Lattice. Axioms. 2021; 10(3):164. https://doi.org/10.3390/axioms10030164

Chicago/Turabian Style

Dai, Songsong. 2021. "Rough Approximation Operators on a Complete Orthomodular Lattice" Axioms 10, no. 3: 164. https://doi.org/10.3390/axioms10030164

APA Style

Dai, S. (2021). Rough Approximation Operators on a Complete Orthomodular Lattice. Axioms, 10(3), 164. https://doi.org/10.3390/axioms10030164

Note that from the first issue of 2016, this journal uses article numbers instead of page numbers. See further details here.

Article Metrics

Back to TopTop