Next Article in Journal
Graded Many-Valued Modal Logic and Its Graded Rough Truth
Next Article in Special Issue
Comparison of Overlap and Grouping Functions
Previous Article in Journal
Do Bitcoin and Traditional Financial Assets Act as an Inflation Hedge during Stable and Turbulent Markets? Evidence from High Cryptocurrency Adoption Countries
Previous Article in Special Issue
On r-Ideals and m-k-Ideals in BN-Algebras
 
 
Font Type:
Arial Georgia Verdana
Font Size:
Aa Aa Aa
Line Spacing:
Column Width:
Background:
Article

On Implicative Derivations of MTL-Algebras

1
College of Teacher Education, Xinyang Normal University, Xinyang 464000, China
2
School of Financial Mathematics and Statistics, Guangdong University of Finance, Guandzhou 510521, China
3
School of Mathematics and Statistics, Anyang Normal University, Anyang 455000, China
4
School of Science, Xi’an Shiyou University, Xi’an 710065, China
*
Author to whom correspondence should be addressed.
Axioms 2022, 11(7), 340; https://doi.org/10.3390/axioms11070340
Submission received: 8 June 2022 / Revised: 4 July 2022 / Accepted: 11 July 2022 / Published: 15 July 2022
(This article belongs to the Special Issue Non-classical Logics and Related Algebra Systems)

Abstract

:
This paper introduces the implicative derivations and gives some of their characterizations on MTL-algebras. Furthermore, we provide some representation of MTL-algebras by implicative derivations and obtain some representation of Boolean algebra via the algebra of all implicative derivations. Finally, we explore the relationship between implicative derivation and other operators on MTL-algebras and show that there exists a bijection between the sets of multiplier and implicative derivations on IMTL-algebras. The results of this paper can provide the common properties of implicative derivations in the t-norm-based fuzzy logical algebras.

1. Introduction

In order to capture the logic of t-norm-based fuzzy logics and their residual [1], Esteva et al. introduced the t-norm-based fuzzy logic MTL [2], and the resulting class of algebras called MTL-algebras. They have interesting algebraic properties and cover all the mathematical structures that appear in a t-norm-based fuzzy logic framework, such as, MV-algebras, BL-algebras, Gödel algebras, IMTL-algebras and R 0 -algebras. Therefore, MTL-algebras are important algebraic structures in which the community of fuzzy logicians have become interested [1,2,3,4,5].
The notion of derivations is instrumental in studying properties and structure in fuzzy logical algebraic structures. In 1957, Posner [6] studied kinds of derivations in a prime ring and some of their basic algebraic properties. Afterward, Jun, Borzooei and Zhan et al. [7,8,9] produced some characterizations of p-semisimple BCI-algebras via derivations with respect to BCI-algebras with derivation. In 2008, Xin, Çeven et al. [10,11,12] characterized modular lattices and distributive lattices by isotone derivations with respect to lattices with derivations. Furthermore, Alshehri, Ghorbain, Yazarli, et al. [13,14,15] derived the derivations on MV-algebras and gave some conditions under which an additive derivation is isotone, in fact, for a linearly ordered MV-algebra. In 2013, Lee et al. [16,17] introduced and studied derivations and f-derivations on lattice implication algebras and discussed the relations between derivations and filters. In 2016, He et al. [18] investigated the kinds of derivations in residuated lattices, and characterized Heyting algebras with respect to the above derivations. In 2017, Hua [19] studied derivations in R 0 -algebras, which are equivalent to NM-algebras, and discussed the relation between filters and the fixed point set of these derivations. The paper is motivated by the following considerations:
(1)
It is well-known that derivations have been studied on MV-algebras, BL-algebras IMTL-algebras and residuated lattices and so on. Although they are essentially different logical algebras they are all particular types of MTL-algebras. Thus, it is meaningful for us to establish the derivation theory of MTL-algebras for studying the common properties of derivations in t-norm-based fuzzy logical algebras.
(2)
The previous research regarding derivations on logical algebras is multiplicative derivation, which is a map that satisfies
d ( x y ) = ( d ( x ) y ) ( x d ( y ) ) .
There are few studies, however, regarding derivations defined by → and any other operations on residuated structures so far. Therefore, it is interesting to study these derivations on logical algebras.
(3)
It has always been known that Galois connections play a central role in studying logical algebras, and the relation between derivations and Galois connections is an important research topic to study. However, there are few research works regarding the relation between derivations and Galois connections on logical algebras so far. Thus, it is necessary for us to study the relation between derivations and Galois connections on logical algebras. Given these considerations, we propose a new type of derivation on MTL-algebras. Indeed,
(1)
The notion of implicative derivations, which are defined by the operations ↪ and ⋓, is introduced on MTL-algebras, and some characterizations of them are given. (see Definition 3, Theorem 1).
(2)
Every implicative derivation is principle on IMTL-algebras (see Theorem 2, Remark 2).
(3)
Every Boolean algebra represents the sets of all implicative derivations on Boolean algebras (see Theorem 6).
(4)
There is an isotone Galois connection between the sets of multipliers and implicative derivations on IMTL-algebras (see Theorem 7).
(5)
There is a bijection between the sets of multiplier and implicative derivations on IMTL-algebras (see Theorem 8).
In Section 2, we review some basic nations and definitions of MTL-algebras. In Section 3, we introduce implicative derivations on MTL-algebras and provide some of their characterizations. In Section 4, we give some representations of MTL-algebras by implicative derivations. In Section 5, we discuss the relationships between implicative derivations with other operators on MTL-algebras.

2. Preliminaries

First, some basic notions of MTL-algebras and their related algebraic results are presented.
Definition 1
([5]).An algebra ( M , , , , , 0 , 1 ) is said to be a residuated lattice if
(1)
( M , , , 0 , 1 ) is a bounded lattice,
(2)
( M , , 1 ) is a commutative monoid,
(3)
u v w iff u v w , for any u , v , w L .
By M we mean that the universe of a residuated lattice ( M , , , , , 0 , 1 ) . On M , we define
u v iff u v = 1 .
Then ≤ is a binary partial order on M and for u M , 0 u 1 .
A residuated lattice M is an MTL-algebra if it satisfies the prelinearlity equation:
( PRE ) ( u v ) ( v u ) = 1 .
An MTL-algebra M is a Gödel algebra if it satisfies
( IDE ) u u = u .
We denote the set { u | u u = u } of M by I ( M ) .
An MTL-algebra M is an IMTL-algebra if it satisfies the double negation property:
( DNP ) ¬ ¬ u = u .
In every IMTL-algebra, we define further operations as follows:
u v = ¬ ( ¬ u ¬ v ) ,
and also check
u v = ¬ ( ¬ u ¬ v ) , u v = ¬ u v .
An IMTL-algebra M is called an R 0 -algebra if it satisfies:
( WNM ) ( u v 0 ) ( u v u v ) = 1 .
Proposition 1
([2]).The following hold in any MTL-algebra M , for all u , v , w M ,
( 1 ) if u v , then v w u w , w u w v and u w v w ,
( 2 ) u ( u v ) = u v ,
( 3 ) ( u v ) w ( u w ) ( v w ) ,
( 4 ) u v u ,
( 5 ) u ( v w ) ( u v ) ( u w ) ,
( 6 ) u ( u w ) = ( u v ) ( u w ) ,
( 7 ) u v ( u w ) ( v w ) ,
( 8 ) u v = ( u v ) v ,
( 9 ) u ( v w ) = ( u v ) ( u w ) ,
( 10 ) u ( v w ) = ( u v ) ( u w ) ,
( 11 ) u v = ( ( u v ) v ) ( v u ) u ) ,
( 12 ) u ( v w ) = ( u v ) ( u w ) ,
( 13 ) ( M , , ) is a distributive lattice,
( 14 ) if u I ( M ) and v , w M , then
(i) u v = u v ,
(ii) u ( v w ) = ( u v ) ( u w ) .
Definition 2
([20]).Given sets E , F and two order-preserving maps f : E F and g : F E , the pair ( f , g ) establishes a Galois connection between E and F if f g i d F and g f i d E .

3. Implicative Derivations of MTL-Algebras

Then, we introduce derivations in MTL-algebras and give some of their characterizations.
Definition 3.
Let M be an MTL-algebra. A mapping g : L L is called an implicative derivation on L if
g ( u v ) = ( g ( u ) v ) ( u g ( v ) ) ,
for any u , v M .
Denoting G ( M ) to be the set of implicative derivations of M .
Some examples of implicative derivations on MTL-algebras are presented.
Example 1.
Let M be an MTL-algebra. Define a mapping 1 g : M M by
1 g ( u ) = 1
for all u M . Then 1 g G ( M ) . Moreover, defining g 1 : M M by
g 1 ( u ) = u
for all u M . Then g 1 G ( M ) .
Example 2.
Let M = { 0 , u , v , w , 1 } be a chain. Defining operations ⊡ and ↪ are
0uvw1   0uvw1
000000   011111
u0u0uu   uv1111
v00vvv   vuu111
w0uvww   w0uv11
10uvw1   10uvw1
Then ( M , , , , , 0 , 1 ) is an MTL-algebra. Now, we define g : M M as follows:
g ( x ) = 0 , x = 0 , u , x = u , v , x = v , 1 , x = w , 1 .
Then g G ( M ) .
Example 3.
Let M n be a standard n-valued R 0 -algebra for some n 2 .
g ( x ) = 1 n 1 , u = 0 n 2 n 1 x , u 0 ,
Then g G ( M ) .
Example 4.
Let M = [ 0 , 1 ] and we define , on M are
u v = min { u , v } , u v = 1 , u v , v , o t h e r w i s e .
Then ( M , min , max , , , 0 , 1 ) is an MTL-algebra. Now, we define g : M M as follows:
g ( u ) = u , u 0.5 , 1 , u 0.5 ,
then g G ( M ) .
Example 5.
Let M be an MTL-algebra and a M . Then g a ( u ) = a u for any u M is an implication derivation on M .
Proposition 2.
Let g G ( M ) . Then, for any u , v M ,
( 1 ) g ( 1 ) = 1 ,
( 2 ) u g ( u ) ,
( 3 ) g ( u ) g ( v ) g ( u v ) ,
( 4 ) g ( u ) v u g ( v ) ,
( 5 ) g ( u v ) = u g ( v ) ,
( 6 ) g ( u v ) g ( u ) g ( v ) .
Proof. 
(1)–(3) are easily verified, we only show (4)–(6).
(4) It follows from (2) and Proposition 1(1).
(5) From (4), we have
g ( u v ) = ( g ( u ) v ) ( u g ( v ) ) = u g ( v ) ,
for any u , v M .
(6) It can be observed directly from (2) and Proposition 1(1). □
Theorem 1.
Let g : M M be a map on an MTL-algebra M . Then the following are equivalent:
( 1 ) g D ( M ) ,
( 2 ) g ( u v ) = u g ( v ) for any u , v M .
Proof. 
( 1 ) ( 2 ) Obviously from Proposition 2(5).
( 2 ) ( 1 ) From (2), we have
g ( 1 ) = g ( 0 u ) = 0 g ( u ) = 1 ,
and hence
1 = g ( u u ) = u g ( u ) ,
which implies u g ( u ) . Then by Proposition 1(1),
g ( u v ) = u g ( v ) = ( g ( u ) v ) ( u g ( v ) ) ,
for any u , v M . □
Remark 1.
The map g p : M M , as defined by
g p ( u ) = p u
for any u M , g p G ( M ) , which is said to be the principle implicative derivation. Indeed,
g p ( u v ) = p ( u v ) = u ( p v ) = u g p ( v ) ,
for any u , v M .
By Remark 1, whether any implicative derivation g can be represented as the form of g p .
Indeed, this assertion is not true for MTL-algebra.
Example 6.
Let M = { 0 , u , v , 1 } be a chain. Defining operations ⊡ and ↪ are
0uv1   0uv1
00000   01111
u0uuu   u0111
v0uvv   v0u11
10uv1   10uv1
Then ( M , min , max , , , 0 , 1 ) is an MTL-algebra. Defining g : M M as follows:
g ( x ) = u , x = 0 v , x = v 1 , x = u , 1 ,
and g G ( M ) . But
g 0 ( 0 ) = 1 u , g u ( 0 ) = g v ( 0 ) = g 1 ( 0 ) = 0 u .
So g is not representative of g p , for any p M .
However, some positive answers are given under certain conditions.
Theorem 2.
Let g be an implicative derivation on an IMTL-algebra M . Then the following are equivalent:,
( 1 ) g D ( M ) ,
( 2 ) g ( u ) = ¬ g ( 0 ) u .
Proof. 
( 1 ) For any u M , by Theorem 1, we have
g ( u ) = g ( ¬ ¬ u ) = g ( ¬ u 0 ) = ¬ u g ( 0 ) = u g ( 0 ) = g ( 0 ) u = ¬ g ( 0 ) u ,
for any u M .
( 2 ) Taking p = ¬ g ( 0 ) in Remark 1. □
Remark 2. ( 1 ) Theorem 2 shows that g is determined by the element ¬ g ( 0 ) on IMTL-algebras. If we take p = ¬ g ( 0 ) , then every implicative derivation on IMTL-algebras is principle.
( 2 ) Every implicative derivation on IMTL-algebra is isotone. If u v , then
g ( u ) = ¬ g ( 0 ) u ¬ g ( 0 ) v = g ( v ) .

4. Characterizations of MTL-Algebras Based on Implicative Derivations

Here we study the algebraic structure of the set of implicative derivations and give some representations of MTL-algebras via them.
Theorem 3.
If M is an MTL-algebra, then ( G ( M ) , , , g 1 , 1 g ) is a bounded distributive lattice, where
( g i g j ) ( u ) = g i ( x ) g j ( x ) , ( g i g j ) ( u ) = g i ( x ) g j ( x ) .
for all g i , g j G ( M ) , and u M .
Proof. 
For any g i , g j G ( M ) , and u M , by Proposition 1(10) and (12), we have
( g i g j ) ( u v ) = g i ( u v ) g j ( u v ) = ( u g i ( v ) ) ( u g j ( v ) ) = u ( g i ( v ) g j ( v ) ) = u ( g i g j ) ( v ) ,
and
( g i g j ) ( u v ) = g i ( u v ) g j ( u v ) = ( u g i ( v ) ) ( u g j ( v ) ) = u ( g i ( v ) g j ( v ) ) = u ( g i g j ) ( v ) ,
which implies g i g j , g i g j G ( M ) .
Furthermore, for any g i G ( M ) and x M , we have
( g i 1 g ) ( u ) = g i ( u ) 1 g ( u ) = g i ( u ) 1 = g i ( u ) , ( g i 1 g ) ( u ) = g i ( u ) 1 g ( u ) = g i ( u ) 1 = g 1 ( u )
which implies g i 1 g = 1 g , g i 1 g = 1 g .
Moreover, ( G ( M ) , , , g 1 , 1 g ) is a bounded distributive lattice. □
Theorem 4.
If ( M , , , , 0 , 1 ) is a Gödel algebra (or an idempotent MTL-algebra), then ( G ( M ) , , , , g 1 , 1 g ) is also a Gödel algebra, where
( g i g j ) ( u ) = g i ( u ) g j ( u ) , ( g i g j ) ( u ) = g i ( u ) g j ( u ) , ( g i g j ) ( u ) = g i ( u ) g j ( u ) .
for all g i , g j G ( M ) , and u M .
Proof. 
By Theorem 3, ( G ( M ) , , , g 1 , 1 g ) is a bounded distributive lattice if M is an MTL-algebra. Now, we prove that ( G ( M ) , , , , g 1 , 1 g ) is a Gödel algebra if M is a Gödel algebra. For any g i , g j G ( M ) and u M , by Proposition 1(14)(ii), we have
( g i g j ) ( u v ) = g i ( u v ) g j ( u v ) = ( u g i ( v ) ) ( u g j ( v ) ) = u ( g i ( v ) g j ( v ) ) = u ( g i g j ) ( v ) ,
which implies g i g j G ( M ) .
By Theorems 3 and 4, the operations , , are well defined if M is a Gödel algebra. □
As a result of Theorems 3 and 4, some important findings are obtained.
Theorem 5.
If ( M , , , 0 , 1 ) is a Boolean algebra (or an idempotent IMTL-algebra), then ( G ( M ) , , , , g 1 , 1 g ) is also a Boolean algebra, where
( g i g j ) ( u ) = g i ( u ) g j ( u ) , ( g i g j ) ( u ) = g i ( u ) g j ( u ) , ( g i ) ( u ) = g i ( u ) g 1 ( u ) .
for any g i , g j G ( M ) , and u M .
Proof. 
By Theorem 3 ( G ( M ) , , , g 1 , 1 g ) is a bounded distributive lattice if M is an MTL-algebra. Moreover, for any g i G ( M ) , and u M , we have
( g i ( g i ) ) ( u ) = g i ( u ) ( g i ( u ) ) = g i ( u ) ( g i ( u ) g 1 ( u ) ) = g i ( u ) g 1 ( u ) = g 1 ( u ) , ( g i ( g i ) ) ( u ) = g i ( u ) ( g i ( u ) g 1 ( u ) ) = g i ( u ) g i ( u ) ) g 1 ( u ) = 1 g 1 ( u ) = 1 = 1 g ( u ) ,
that is, g i ( g i ) = g 1 and g i ( g i ) = 1 g . □
Theorem 6.
Every Boolean algebra M is isomorphic to ( G ( M ) , , , , g 1 , 1 g ) .
Proof. 
Define χ : M G ( M ) by
χ ( x ) ( u ) = x u ,
for any a , u M . By Theorem 1, χ is well defined.
( 1 ) If χ ( x ) = χ ( y ) , then χ ( x ) ( u ) = χ ( y ) ( u ) , and hence x u = y u for all u M . Now, if u = x , then x = x x = x y , that is, y x . If u = y , then x y = y y = y , and hence x y = y , that is, x y . So x = y , which shows that χ is an injective function.
( 2 ) For any g G ( M ) , there exists a g ( 0 ) M such that g = χ ( ( g ( 0 ) ) ) , which implies that χ is a surjection function. Indeed, by Theorem 1(2), we have g ( u ) = ¬ u g ( 0 ) = u g ( 0 ) = u g ( 0 ) = χ ( ( g ( 0 ) ) ) ( u ) , for any u M .
( 3 ) For any x , y M , we have
χ ( x y ) ( u ) = ( x y ) u = ( x u ) ( y u ) = ( χ ( x ) χ ( y ) ) ( u ) , χ ( x y ) ( u ) = ( x y ) u = ( x u ) ( y u ) = ( χ ( x ) χ ( y ) ) ( u ) , χ ( ¬ x ) ( u ) = ¬ x u = x u = ( x u ) ( u u ) = ( x u ) u = ( χ ( x ) ( u ) ) .
which implies that χ is a homomorphism.
Therefore ( M , , , 0 , 1 ) is isomorphic to ( G ( M ) , , , , g 1 , 1 g ) . □

5. Relations between Implicative Derivations and Other Operators on MTL-Algebras

Recall in [21] that a self map f is called a multiplier of a distributive lattice L if
f ( u v ) = u f ( v ) ,
for any u , v M . Applying this notion to MTL-algebras as a self f satisfies
f ( u v ) = u f ( v ) .
Denoting M ( M ) by the set of all multipliers of M .
Proposition 3.
Let f be a multiplier on an MTL-algebra M . Then, for any u , v M ,
( 1 ) f ( 0 ) = 0 ,
( 2 ) f ( u ) = u f ( 1 ) ,
( 3 ) f ( u ) u ,
( 4 ) if u v , then f ( u ) f ( v ) .
Proof. 
The proof is easy, and hence omitted. □
Now, we discuss the relations between M ( M ) and G ( M ) .
Let φ : M ( M ) G ( M ) be the map
φ ( f ) ( u ) = ¬ ( f ( ¬ u ) )
for any f M ( M ) and x M , and ψ : G ( M ) M ( M ) be the map such that
ψ ( g ) ( u ) = ¬ ( g ( ¬ u ) )
for any g G ( M ) , and u M .
Theorem 7.
Let M be an IMTL-algebra. There exists here an isotone Galois connection between M ( M ) and G ( M ) . Namely,
f ψ ( g ) i f f g φ ( f )
for any f M ( M ) and g G ( M ) .
Proof. 
( 1 ) By Propositions 3(4) and Remark 2(2) that φ and ψ are isotone.
( 2 ) If f ψ ( g ) , that is f ( u ) ψ ( g ) ( u ) = ¬ ( g ( ¬ u ) ) , then ¬ ( f ( u ) ) g ( ¬ u ) for any u M . So φ ( f ) ( u ) = ¬ ( f ( ¬ u ) ) g ( u ) , which implies g φ ( f ) .
Conversely, if g φ ( f ) , that is g ( u ) φ ( f ) ( u ) = ¬ ( f ( ¬ u ) ) for any u M , then f ( ¬ u ) ¬ ( g ( u ) ) . So f ( u ) ¬ ( g ( ¬ u ) ) = ψ ( g ) ( u ) for any u M , which implies f ψ ( g ) . □
Theorem 8.
Let M be an IMTL-algebra. Then there exists a bijection between G ( M ) and M ( M ) . Namely,
( 1 ) if f M ( M ) , then φ ( f ) G ( M ) ,
( 2 ) if g G ( M ) , then ψ ( g ) M ( M ) ,
( 3 ) ψ φ ( f ) = f and φ ψ ( g ) = g .
Proof. 
If f is a multiplier on M , then
φ ( f ) ( u v ) = ¬ ( f ¬ ( u v ) ) = ¬ ( f ( u ¬ v ) ) = ¬ ( u f ( ¬ v ) ) = u φ ( f ) ( v ) ,
for any u , v M , by Theorem 1, φ ( f ) G ( M ) .
Conversely, if g G ( M ) , then
ψ ( g ) ( u v ) = ¬ ( g ( ¬ ( u v ) ) ) = ¬ ( g ( u ¬ v ) ) = ¬ ( u g ( ¬ v ) ) = u ¬ ( g ( ¬ v ) ) = u ψ ( g ) ( v ) ,
for any u , v M , which implies that ψ ( g ) is a multiplier on M .
Moreover, by Proposition 3(2), we have
ψ φ ( f ) ( u ) = f ( ¬ ( f ( ¬ u ) ) ) = f ( 1 ) ( ( f ( 1 ) ) u ) = f ( 1 ) u = f ( u )
for any u M , and so ψ φ ( f ) = f . Similarly, φ ψ ( g ) = g . □
Borumand Saeid et al. introduced in [22] that a k-modal operator in BL-algebra, which is a map satisfies the following conditions:
(M1) u v ( u v ) ,
(M2) if u v , then u v ,
(M3) 1 1 .
Proposition 4.
If L is an MTL-algebra and a G ( M ) , then g a is a k-modal operator on M .
Proof. 
(M2) and (M3) are easily verified. Then, we will show that (M1) also holds. Indeed, by Proposition 1(14)(ii), we have
g a ( u v ) = a ( u v ) = ( a u ) ( a v ) = g a ( u ) g a ( v ) ,
for any u , v M . Then, by Definition 1(3), we get g a ( u ) g a ( v ) g a ( u v ) for any u , v M . □
The condition a G ( L ) is necessary.
Example 7.
Let L = { 0 , u , v , w , x , y , 1 } with lattice order 0 u w 1 , 0 v x 1 and v w . Defining operations ⊡ and ↪ as follows:
0uvwxy1   0uvwxy1
00000000   01111111
u0uuuuuu   u0111111
v0uvuvuv   v0y1e1e1
w0uuuuww   w0xx1111
x0uvuvwx   x0wxy1y1
y0uuwwxx   y0vvxx11
10uvwxy1   10uvwxy1
Then ( M , , , , , 0 , 1 ) is an MTL-algebra. Defining g d : M M as follows:
g ( x ) = 0 , x = 0 w , x = u x , x = v y , x = w , y 1 , x = x , 1 ,
Then g d G ( M ) . However, it is not a k-modal operator on M since
g x ( w ) g x ( v ) = w u = g x ( w v ) .
The k-modal operator is not the implicative derivation on MTL-algebra.
Example 8.
Let M be the MTL-algebra in Example 7. Now, we define : M M as follows:
( x ) = 0 , x = 0 , u , v , w , y x , x = x 1 , x = 1 ,
Then □ is a k-modal operator on M . However, it is not an implicative derivation on M , since
( y y ) = 1 0 = y y .
It is interesting to consider under which conditions, is every implicative derivation a k-modal operator on an MTL-algebra.
Proposition 5.
Let M be an MTL-algebra and g G ( M ) satisfies
( * ) g ( u v ) = g ( u ) g ( u v ) .
Then the following statements are equivalent:
( 1 ) g ( u v ) = g ( u ) g ( v ) ,
( 2 ) if u v , then g ( u ) g ( v ) .
Proof. 
( 1 ) ( 2 ) If u v , then it follows from (1) that
1 = g ( 1 ) = g ( u v ) = g ( u ) g ( v ) ,
which implies g ( u ) g ( v ) .
( 2 ) ( 1 ) If g satisfies (2), then by ( ) , we have
g ( u ) g ( u v ) = g ( u ) ( g ( u ) g ( u v ) ) g ( u v ) g ( v ) ,
which implies g ( u v ) g ( u ) g ( v ) . Then by Proposition 2(6), we obtain g ( u v ) = g ( u ) g ( v ) for any u , v M . □
Corollary 1.
Let M be an IMTL-algebra and g G ( M ) satisfies ( * ) . Then g is a k-modal operator on M .
Proof. 
By Remark 2(2), and Propositions 2(1) and 5. □

6. Conclusions

The notion of implicative derivations is beneficial for discussing structures and properties in fuzzy logic algebraic. In order to provide the common properties of implicative derivations in the t-norm-based logical algebras, we introduce the implicative derivations on MTL-algebras and obtain some of their characterizations. We also obtain some characterizations of Boolean algebras via implicative derivations and show the relations between implicative derivations and other operators, for example, multiplier and k-modal operators, on IMTL-algebras. In the future, we will study some of their algebraic properties of derivations on algebraic hyperstructures [23,24].

Author Contributions

Writing—original draft preparation, J.L. and Y.L.; writing—review and editing, Y.Y. and J.W. All authors have read and agreed to the published version of the manuscript.

Funding

This work was funded by a grant from the National Natural Science Foundation of China (11926501,11661073), the Natural Science Basic Research Plan in Shaanxi Province of China (2020JQ-762,2021JQ-580,2020JQ-279) and Natural Science Foundation of Education Committee of Shannxi Province (19JK0653).

Conflicts of Interest

The authors declare no conflict of interest.

References

  1. Jenei, S.; Montagan, F. A proof of standard completeness for Esteva and Godo’s logic. Stud. Logica 2002, 70, 183–192. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  2. Esteva, F.; Godo, L. Monoidal t-norm based logic: Towards a logic for left-continuous t-norms. Fuzzy Sets Syst. 2001, 124, 271–288. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  3. Borzooei, R.A.; Shoar, S.K.; Ameri, R. Some types of filters in MTL-algebras. Fuzzy Sets Syst. 2012, 187, 92–102. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  4. Chen, W.J.; Guan, Y.Y. The set of fuzzy points of coalgebras. Util. Math. 2012, 89, 367–371. [Google Scholar]
  5. Hájek, P. Metamathematics of Fuzzy Logic; Kluwer Academic Publishers: Dordrecht, The Netherlands, 1998. [Google Scholar]
  6. Posner, E. Derivations in prime rings. Proc. Am. Math. Soc. 1957, 8, 1093–1100. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  7. Borzooei, R.A.; Zahiri, O. Some results on derivations of BCI-algebras. Sci. Math. Jpn. 2013, 26, 529–545. [Google Scholar]
  8. Jun, Y.B.; Xin, X.L. On derivations of BCI-algebras. Inf. Sci. 2004, 159, 167–176. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  9. Zhan, J.M.; Liu, Y.L. On f-derivations of BCI-algebras. Int. J. Math. Math. Sci. 2005, 11, 1675–1684. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
  10. Çeven, Y.; Öztürk, M.A. On f-derivations of lattices. Bull. Korean Math. Soc. 2008, 45, 701–707. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
  11. Xin, X.L. The fixed set of aderivation in lattices. Fixed Point Theory Appl. 2012, 218, 1–12. [Google Scholar]
  12. Xin, X.L.; Li, T.Y.; Lu, J.H. On derivations of lattices. Inf. Sci. 2008, 178, 307–316. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  13. Alshehri, N.O. Derivations of MV-algebras. Int. J. Math. Math. Sci. 2010, 2010, 312027. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  14. Ghorbain, S.; Torkzadeh, L.; Motamed, S. (⊗,⊕)-derivations and (⊖,⊗)-derivations on MV-algebras. Iran. J. Math. Sci. Inform. 2013, 8, 75–90. [Google Scholar]
  15. Yazarli, H. A note on derivations in MV-algebras. Miskolc. Math. Notes 2013, 14, 345–354. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  16. Lee, S.D.; Kim, K.H. On derivations of lattice implication algebras. Ars Comb. 2013, 108, 279–288. [Google Scholar]
  17. Yon, Y.H.; Kim, K.H. On f-derivations of lattice implication algebras. Ars Comb. 2013, 110, 205–215. [Google Scholar]
  18. He, P.F.; Xin, X.L.; Zhan, J.M. On derivations and their fixed point sets in residuated lattices. Fuzzy Sets Syst. 2016, 303, 97–113. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  19. Hua, X.J. On derivations of R0-algebras. Comput. Eng. Appl. 2017, 53, 54–57. [Google Scholar]
  20. Grätzer, G. Lattice Theory; W. H. Freeman and Company: San Francisco, CA, USA, 1979. [Google Scholar]
  21. Schmid, J. Multipliers on distributive lattices and rings of quotients I. Houst. J. Math. 1980, 3, 401–425. [Google Scholar]
  22. Omid, Y.K.; Esfandiar, E.; Arsham, B.S. K-modal BL-algebras. Kuwait J. Sci. 2016, 43, 39–60. [Google Scholar]
  23. Du, Y.D.; Zhang, X.H. QM-BZ-algebras and quasi-hyper BZ-algebras. Axioms 2022, 11, 93. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  24. Zhang, X.H.; Du, Y.D. A class of BCI-algebra and quasi-Hyper BCI-algebra. Axioms 2022, 11, 72. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
Publisher’s Note: MDPI stays neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Share and Cite

MDPI and ACS Style

Liu, J.; Li, Y.; Yang, Y.; Wang, J. On Implicative Derivations of MTL-Algebras. Axioms 2022, 11, 340. https://doi.org/10.3390/axioms11070340

AMA Style

Liu J, Li Y, Yang Y, Wang J. On Implicative Derivations of MTL-Algebras. Axioms. 2022; 11(7):340. https://doi.org/10.3390/axioms11070340

Chicago/Turabian Style

Liu, Jianxin, Yijun Li, Yongwei Yang, and Juntao Wang. 2022. "On Implicative Derivations of MTL-Algebras" Axioms 11, no. 7: 340. https://doi.org/10.3390/axioms11070340

APA Style

Liu, J., Li, Y., Yang, Y., & Wang, J. (2022). On Implicative Derivations of MTL-Algebras. Axioms, 11(7), 340. https://doi.org/10.3390/axioms11070340

Note that from the first issue of 2016, this journal uses article numbers instead of page numbers. See further details here.

Article Metrics

Back to TopTop