1. Introduction
In order to capture the logic of t-norm-based fuzzy logics and their residual [
1], Esteva et al. introduced the t-norm-based fuzzy logic
MTL [
2], and the resulting class of algebras called MTL-algebras. They have interesting algebraic properties and cover all the mathematical structures that appear in a t-norm-based fuzzy logic framework, such as, MV-algebras, BL-algebras, Gödel algebras, IMTL-algebras and
-algebras. Therefore, MTL-algebras are important algebraic structures in which the community of fuzzy logicians have become interested [
1,
2,
3,
4,
5].
The notion of derivations is instrumental in studying properties and structure in fuzzy logical algebraic structures. In 1957, Posner [
6] studied kinds of derivations in a prime ring and some of their basic algebraic properties. Afterward, Jun, Borzooei and Zhan et al. [
7,
8,
9] produced some characterizations of p-semisimple BCI-algebras via derivations with respect to BCI-algebras with derivation. In 2008, Xin, Çeven et al. [
10,
11,
12] characterized modular lattices and distributive lattices by isotone derivations with respect to lattices with derivations. Furthermore, Alshehri, Ghorbain, Yazarli, et al. [
13,
14,
15] derived the derivations on MV-algebras and gave some conditions under which an additive derivation is isotone, in fact, for a linearly ordered MV-algebra. In 2013, Lee et al. [
16,
17] introduced and studied derivations and
f-derivations on lattice implication algebras and discussed the relations between derivations and filters. In 2016, He et al. [
18] investigated the kinds of derivations in residuated lattices, and characterized Heyting algebras with respect to the above derivations. In 2017, Hua [
19] studied derivations in
-algebras, which are equivalent to NM-algebras, and discussed the relation between filters and the fixed point set of these derivations. The paper is motivated by the following considerations:
- (1)
It is well-known that derivations have been studied on MV-algebras, BL-algebras IMTL-algebras and residuated lattices and so on. Although they are essentially different logical algebras they are all particular types of MTL-algebras. Thus, it is meaningful for us to establish the derivation theory of MTL-algebras for studying the common properties of derivations in t-norm-based fuzzy logical algebras.
- (2)
The previous research regarding derivations on logical algebras is multiplicative derivation, which is a map that satisfies
There are few studies, however, regarding derivations defined by → and any other operations on residuated structures so far. Therefore, it is interesting to study these derivations on logical algebras.
- (3)
It has always been known that Galois connections play a central role in studying logical algebras, and the relation between derivations and Galois connections is an important research topic to study. However, there are few research works regarding the relation between derivations and Galois connections on logical algebras so far. Thus, it is necessary for us to study the relation between derivations and Galois connections on logical algebras. Given these considerations, we propose a new type of derivation on MTL-algebras. Indeed,
- (1)
The notion of implicative derivations, which are defined by the operations ↪ and ⋓, is introduced on MTL-algebras, and some characterizations of them are given. (see Definition 3, Theorem 1).
- (2)
Every implicative derivation is principle on IMTL-algebras (see Theorem 2, Remark 2).
- (3)
Every Boolean algebra represents the sets of all implicative derivations on Boolean algebras (see Theorem 6).
- (4)
There is an isotone Galois connection between the sets of multipliers and implicative derivations on IMTL-algebras (see Theorem 7).
- (5)
There is a bijection between the sets of multiplier and implicative derivations on IMTL-algebras (see Theorem 8).
In
Section 2, we review some basic nations and definitions of MTL-algebras. In
Section 3, we introduce implicative derivations on MTL-algebras and provide some of their characterizations. In
Section 4, we give some representations of MTL-algebras by implicative derivations. In
Section 5, we discuss the relationships between implicative derivations with other operators on MTL-algebras.
2. Preliminaries
First, some basic notions of MTL-algebras and their related algebraic results are presented.
Definition 1 ([5]).An algebra is said to be a residuated lattice
if - (1)
is a bounded lattice,
- (2)
is a commutative monoid,
- (3)
iff , for any .
By
we mean that the universe of a residuated lattice
. On
, we define
Then ≤ is a binary partial order on
and for
.
A residuated lattice
is an
MTL-algebra if it satisfies the prelinearlity equation:
An MTL-algebra
is a
Gödel algebra if it satisfies
We denote the set of by .
An MTL-algebra
is an
IMTL-algebra if it satisfies the double negation property:
In every IMTL-algebra, we define further operations as follows:
and also check
An IMTL-algebra
is called an
-algebra if it satisfies:
Proposition 1 ([2]).The following hold in any MTL-algebra , for all , if , then , and ,
,
,
,
,
,
,
,
,
,
,
,
is a distributive lattice,
if and , then
(i) ,
(ii) .
Definition 2 ([20]).Given sets and two order-preserving maps and , the pair establishes a Galois connection
between and if and . 3. Implicative Derivations of MTL-Algebras
Then, we introduce derivations in MTL-algebras and give some of their characterizations.
Definition 3. Let be an MTL-algebra. A mapping is called an implicative derivation
on L iffor any . Denoting to be the set of implicative derivations of .
Some examples of implicative derivations on MTL-algebras are presented.
Example 1. Let be an MTL-algebra. Define a mapping byfor all . Then . Moreover, defining byfor all . Then . Example 2. Let be a chain. Defining operations ⊡ and ↪ are⊡ | 0 | u | v | w | 1 | | ↪ | 0 | u | v | w | 1 |
0 | 0 | 0 | 0 | 0 | 0 | | 0 | 1 | 1 | 1 | 1 | 1 |
u | 0 | u | 0 | u | u | | u | v | 1 | 1 | 1 | 1 |
v | 0 | 0 | v | v | v | | v | u | u | 1 | 1 | 1 |
w | 0 | u | v | w | w | | w | 0 | u | v | 1 | 1 |
1 | 0 | u | v | w | 1 | | 1 | 0 | u | v | w | 1 |
Then is an MTL-algebra. Now, we define as follows: Example 3. Let be a standard n-valued -algebra for some .
Example 4. Let and we define on are
Then is an MTL-algebra. Now, we define as follows: Example 5. Let be an MTL-algebra and . Then for any is an implication derivation on .
Proposition 2. Let . Then, for any ,
,
,
,
,
,
.
Proof. (1)–(3) are easily verified, we only show (4)–(6).
(4) It follows from (2) and Proposition 1(1).
(5) From (4), we have
for any
.
(6) It can be observed directly from (2) and Proposition 1(1). □
Theorem 1. Let be a map on an MTL-algebra . Then the following are equivalent:
,
for any .
Proof. Obviously from Proposition 2(5).
From (2), we have
and hence
which implies
. Then by Proposition 1(1),
for any
. □
Remark 1. The map , as defined byfor any , , which is said to be the principle implicative derivation. Indeed,for any . By Remark 1, whether any implicative derivation g can be represented as the form of .
Indeed, this assertion is not true for MTL-algebra.
Example 6. Let be a chain. Defining operations ⊡ and ↪ are⊗ | 0 | u | v | 1 | | ⇒ | 0 | u | v | 1 |
0 | 0 | 0 | 0 | 0 | | 0 | 1 | 1 | 1 | 1 |
u | 0 | u | u | u | | u | 0 | 1 | 1 | 1 |
v | 0 | u | v | v | | v | 0 | u | 1 | 1 |
1 | 0 | u | v | 1 | | 1 | 0 | u | v | 1 |
Then is an MTL-algebra. Defining as follows: and . ButSo g is not representative of , for any . However, some positive answers are given under certain conditions.
Theorem 2. Let g be an implicative derivation on an IMTL-algebra . Then the following are equivalent:,
,
.
Proof. For any
, by Theorem 1, we have
for any
.
Taking in Remark 1. □
Remark 2. Theorem 2 shows that g is determined by the element on IMTL-algebras. If we take , then every implicative derivation on IMTL-algebras is principle.
Every implicative derivation on IMTL-algebra is isotone. If , then 4. Characterizations of MTL-Algebras Based on Implicative Derivations
Here we study the algebraic structure of the set of implicative derivations and give some representations of MTL-algebras via them.
Theorem 3. If is an MTL-algebra, then is a bounded distributive lattice, wherefor all , and . Proof. For any
, and
, by Proposition 1(10) and (12), we have
and
which implies
.
Furthermore, for any
and
, we have
which implies
.
Moreover, is a bounded distributive lattice. □
Theorem 4. If is a Gödel algebra (or an idempotent MTL-algebra), then is also a Gödel algebra, wherefor all , and . Proof. By Theorem 3,
is a bounded distributive lattice if
is an MTL-algebra. Now, we prove that
is a Gödel algebra if
is a Gödel algebra. For any
and
, by Proposition 1(14)(ii), we have
which implies
.
By Theorems 3 and 4, the operations are well defined if is a Gödel algebra. □
As a result of Theorems 3 and 4, some important findings are obtained.
Theorem 5. If is a Boolean algebra (or an idempotent IMTL-algebra), then is also a Boolean algebra, wherefor any , and . Proof. By Theorem 3
is a bounded distributive lattice if
is an MTL-algebra. Moreover, for any
, and
, we have
that is,
and
. □
Theorem 6. Every Boolean algebra is isomorphic to .
Proof. Define
by
for any
. By Theorem 1,
is well defined.
If , then , and hence for all . Now, if , then , that is, . If , then , and hence , that is, . So , which shows that is an injective function.
For any , there exists a such that , which implies that is a surjection function. Indeed, by Theorem 1(2), we have , for any .
For any
, we have
which implies that
is a homomorphism.
Therefore is isomorphic to . □
5. Relations between Implicative Derivations and Other Operators on MTL-Algebras
Recall in [
21] that a self map
f is called a multiplier of a distributive lattice
L if
for any
. Applying this notion to MTL-algebras as a self
f satisfies
Denoting by the set of all multipliers of .
Proposition 3. Let f be a multiplier on an MTL-algebra . Then, for any ,
,
,
,
if , then .
Proof. The proof is easy, and hence omitted. □
Now, we discuss the relations between and .
Let
be the map
for any
and
, and
be the map such that
for any
, and
.
Theorem 7. Let be an IMTL-algebra. There exists here an isotone Galois connection between and . Namely,for any and . Proof. By Propositions 3(4) and Remark 2(2) that and are isotone.
If , that is , then for any . So , which implies .
Conversely, if , that is for any , then . So for any , which implies . □
Theorem 8. Let be an IMTL-algebra. Then there exists a bijection between and . Namely,
if , then ,
if , then ,
and .
Proof. If
f is a multiplier on
, then
for any
, by Theorem 1,
.
Conversely, if
, then
for any
, which implies that
is a multiplier on
.
Moreover, by Proposition 3(2), we have
for any
, and so
. Similarly,
. □
Borumand Saeid et al. introduced in [
22] that a k-modal operator in BL-algebra, which is a map satisfies the following conditions:
(M1) ,
(M2) if , then ,
(M3) .
Proposition 4. If L is an MTL-algebra and , then is a k-modal operator on .
Proof. (M2) and (M3) are easily verified. Then, we will show that (M1) also holds. Indeed, by Proposition 1(14)(ii), we have
for any
. Then, by Definition 1(3), we get
for any
. □
The condition is necessary.
Example 7. Let with lattice order , and . Defining operations ⊡ and ↪ as follows:⊡ | 0 | u | v | w | x | y | 1 | | ↪ | 0 | u | v | w | x | y | 1 |
0 | 0 | 0 | 0 | 0 | 0 | 0 | 0 | | 0 | 1 | 1 | 1 | 1 | 1 | 1 | 1 |
u | 0 | u | u | u | u | u | u | | u | 0 | 1 | 1 | 1 | 1 | 1 | 1 |
v | 0 | u | v | u | v | u | v | | v | 0 | y | 1 | e | 1 | e | 1 |
w | 0 | u | u | u | u | w | w | | w | 0 | x | x | 1 | 1 | 1 | 1 |
x | 0 | u | v | u | v | w | x | | x | 0 | w | x | y | 1 | y | 1 |
y | 0 | u | u | w | w | x | x | | y | 0 | v | v | x | x | 1 | 1 |
1 | 0 | u | v | w | x | y | 1 | | 1 | 0 | u | v | w | x | y | 1 |
Then is an MTL-algebra. Defining as follows: Then . However, it is not a k-modal operator on since The k-modal operator is not the implicative derivation on MTL-algebra.
Example 8. Let be the MTL-algebra in Example 7. Now, we define as follows:
Then □ is a k-modal operator on . However, it is not an implicative derivation on , since It is interesting to consider under which conditions, is every implicative derivation a k-modal operator on an MTL-algebra.
Proposition 5. Let be an MTL-algebra and satisfiesThen the following statements are equivalent: ,
if , then .
Proof. If
, then it follows from (1) that
which implies
.
If
g satisfies (2), then by
, we have
which implies
. Then by Proposition 2(6), we obtain
for any
. □
Corollary 1. Let be an IMTL-algebra and satisfies . Then g is a k-modal operator on .
Proof. By Remark 2(2), and Propositions 2(1) and 5. □