1. Introduction
One of the major tools supporting the standard probability theory is the notion of expectation of a random variable. In generalizations of the probability theory, for example, in the theory of imprecise probabilities, one needs to have a reasonable counterpart of the expected value. This challenging task is realized by means of coherent lower (upper) previsions. Recall that coherent lower previsions are functionals defined on the linear space of all random variables satisfying the axioms of coherence [
1] and they are related to coherent lower probabilities. However, they need be not determined by coherent lower probabilities since in some cases, when restricted to events, different coherent lower previsions may yield the same lower probability ([
1], Section 2.7.3). Another tool to construct coherent lower previsions is the Choquet integral. Again, they need not be defined always by Choquet integral with respect to a coherent lower probability, because the Choquet integral satisfies the super-additivity, which is one of the defining property of a coherent lower previsions [
1], if and only if it is defined with respect to a super-modular lower probability. So, there is a need to introduce some new approaches to the construction of coherent lower (upper) previsions. This need has motivated our study of some new types of super-additive integrals in our preliminary work [
2]. In this paper, a deeper study of the problem how to construct coherent lower (upper) previsions by means of super-additive integrals with respect to monotone measures (capacities) is presented, illustrated by numerous examples. Several new types of monotone set functions, such as plausibility and belief measures, possibility and necessity measures, coherent upper and lower probability measures, monotone measures, and so forth., have been introduced in the past decades to enrich the framework of classical
-additive measures to represent several types of uncertainty. These measures were axiomatically characterized and relations among them were deeply studied in numerous works, such as Ref. [
1], for example.
Classical Lebesgue integral is heavily based on the additivity (and continuity in the case of infinite spaces) of the considered measures. Therefore, new types of set functions generalizing the classical measures require some modified approach to integration, which, typically, leads to the non-linearity of the introduced integrals. Maybe the most famous among these integrals is Choquet integral [
3,
4], which extends Lebesgue integral (i.e., if the considered measure is a classical one, then both these integrals coincide). As another non-linear integral recall Shilkret integral [
5], which is well defined for any of the above mentioned monotone set functions, but it coincides with the Lebesgue integral only in the case when Dirac measures are considered. Both Choquet and Shilkret integrals are based on the standard real operations of addition and multiplication (what is not the case of Sugeno integral [
6], for example). Recently, an interesting class of non-linear integrals, called decomposition integrals and considering the standard arithmetic operations + and ·, was introduced by Even and Lehrer [
7], see also Ref. [
8]. This class of integrals contains both Choquet and Shilkret integrals, but also the PAN integral [
9,
10] and the concave integral [
11].
The main aim of this paper is a new look on constructions of generalized expectations of random variables, namely of coherent lower previsions and coherent upper previsions [
12,
13]. Recall that one of basic characterizations of the coherent lower previsions is the super-additivity of this functional. Observe that an important class of coherent lower previsions is identified with the (asymmetric) Choquet integral [
3] with respect to a supermodular capacity (ensuring the super-additivity of the related Choquet integral), [
4,
13]. Inspired by this fact, also some other super-additive integral-based functionals could be considered. Recently, we have introduced collection integrals [
2], that is, decomposition integrals [
7] with respect to singleton decomposition systems, that is, decomposition systems consisting from a single collection. Some first results relating coherent lower (upper) previsions and collection integrals were already introduced in Ref. [
2]. In this paper, a significant extension of the results from Ref. [
2] is given, yielding, among others, several interesting by-product results.
Given a non-empty set
, a super-additive integral, with respect to a collection
and a monotone set function
, is introduced in Ref. [
2] to give an integral representation of a coherent lower prevision defined on the linear space of all random variables on
. Note that due to the finiteness of
, any considered random variable is bounded. Different integral representation of coherent upper conditional previsions in terms of Choquet integral, pan integral and concave integral has been analysed in Ref. [
14] where it has been proven that the pan integral and the concave integral with respect to a sub-additive capacity coincide and they represent a coherent upper probability if and only if the underlying capacity is additive.
In this paper the construction method of coherent lower prevision based on the super-additive integral is complemented with motivations and examples. Given a finite non-empty set
, a collection
and a monotone set function
, in Ref. [
15] a collection integral is defined for non-negative functions as a particular case of decomposition integrals; super-additive integrals are extension of shift-invariant collection integrals to the class of all functions. If collections
are classes of disjoint subsets of
, the super-additive integral can be defined for any monotone set function
since the underlying collection integral is shift-invariant and so it can be used to construct a coherent lower prevision. Moreover for any collection
there exists a monotone set function
, which asses the value 1 to the biggest set from
and the value 0 to all other sets from
, so that the corresponding collection integral is shift-invariant and it can be used to define a super-additive integral and a coherent lower prevision.
Collections and monotone set functions are given such that the corresponding collection integrals are not shift-invariant. In Example 8 it is shown that the collection integral with respect to a collection consisting of two non-disjoint sets that do not form a chain, is not shift-invariant for any (non-trivial) capacity; so its extension cannot be used to define coherent lower previsions. Examples of coherent lower previsions constructed by super-additive integrals are given in the following cases: (a) the collection is a chain and the capacity is such that the capacity of the biggest set of the chain is positive; (b) the collection consists of disjoint sets and is any monotone set function, (c) the collection is the power set of and is a super-modular monotone set function; in this case the super-additive integral is the asymmetric Choquet integral with real values. If the monotone set function is not super-modular the corresponding collection integral may be not shift-invariant; an example of capacity is given such that the corresponding collection integral is shift-invariant and the super-additive integral defines a coherent lower prevision and an example of monotone set function, which does not define a coherent lower prevision, is given. Related coherent upper previsions are also defined.
The paper is organized as follows. In the next section, some preliminaries important for the rest of the paper are given.
Section 3 extends the collection integrals which are shift-invariant (and acting on non-negative random variables only) to a functional acting on the space of all (bounded) random variables, preserving the original super-additivity of collection integrals. The main core of this paper is contained in
Section 4, where, based on our results from
Section 3, a novel construction method for coherent lower (upper) previsions is proposed and exemplified. In
Section 5, a further generalization of the proposed construction method for coherent lower (upper) previsions are introduced and exemplified. Finally, some concluding remarks are added.
2. Preliminaries
Throughout this paper, we will consider a finite universe equipped with -algebra . We denote by the set of all random variables on , that is, the set of all functions . Similarly, denotes the set of all non-negative random variables from , and the set of all random variables from attaining the value 0 (i.e., ). Obviously, and is a linear space over the field .
A monotone set function or capacity is any set function such that and implies .
A coherent lower prevision is a functional such that
for all
and
[
1,
13]. A
coherent upper prevision [
1] is defined by the conjugacy property
. From axioms 1-3 we obtain
and in particular
.
A coherent lower prevision, defined on
and such that
is called a
linear prevision, see, for example, Ref. [
16,
17,
18,
19,
20], and it is a linear, positive and positively homogenous functional on
, see Ref. ([
1], Corollary 2.8.5).
For
the indicator function
is defined by
for all
. A
coherent lower probability is the restriction of a linear prevision
to the class of all indicator functions
with
.
A functional
is coherent if and only if there is a class
of linear previsions defined on the class of all random variables defined on
such that
is dominated by every
, that is,
= inf
, see, for example, Ref. ([
1], Section 3.3.3); in this case
is called the
lower envelope of linear previsions.
Knowing the lower and upper probabilities for events does not determine lower and upper previsions for other random variables. Levi ([
21], pp. 407, 416–417) in his example for Case 5 involves two different (closed, convex) sets of probabilities that have the same lower and upper expectations for indicator functions, but where these two sets induce different judgments of E-admissibility for a given decision problem.
The following example shows that coherent lower probabilities may not determine coherent lower previsions since different lower previsions yield the same lower probability when they are restricted to events (for a different example, see, for example, Walley ([
1], Section 2.7.3).
Example 1. Let and let for be the probabilities defined on the atoms of Ω
byEach has a unique extension to a linear prevision defined on bySeveral different coherent lower previsions can be constructed as lower envelopes of these linear previsions such that the lower previsions yield the same lower probabilities when they are restricted to the indicator functions. LetLet so we obtain that are coherent lower previsions which coincide on the indicator functions since they coincide on the atoms of Ω
, that is,Nevertheless, they are different coherent lower previsions because, if we consider the random variable given by , we obtain that Moreover coherent lower previsions can be defined by Choquet integral with respect to a coherent lower probability if and only if the underlying coherent lower prevision is super-modular, that is, if and only if
In this case, Choquet integral is super-additive by the super-additivity theorem, see, for example, Ref. [
3].
As
is finite and
is defined on
, denote by
the atoms of
, which are the minimal elements of
. If the atoms
are enumerated so that
are in descending order, that is,
and
, Choquet integral with respect to
is given by
where
, and
.
Example 2. Let and let for be probabilities of atoms of Ω
given byand let be a coherent lower probability defined by . Let and ; and note that is not super-modular sinceand thusthat is, Choquet integral with respect to is not super-additive. In the next sections we introduce a new integral, called a super-additive integral, to construct coherent lower previsions and to give their integral representation.
3. Super-Additive Integral Defined by Shift-Invariant Collection Integral
In this section a construction method for coherent lower previsions is proposed; to do that we start by proving a super-additivity property of the collection integral and we need to restrict to a special class of collection integrals that allow one to extend their domain to all functions while preserving super-additivity.
A collection integral was introduced in Ref. [
15] as a special case of decomposition integrals, see, for example, Ref. [
7,
8]. A collection
is a non-empty subset of
.
Definition 1. A collection integral with respect to a collection and a monotone set function μ is a functionalwhere ⋁
denotes the supremum. Proposition 1. is a super-additive functional, that is, for all .
Proof. For
let
be non-negative real numbers such that
Then
that is, by summing the previous two we obtain a sub-decomposition of
. This implies the super-additivity of
, that is,
as needed. □
The collection integral is defined only on non-negative functions and the aim of this section to introduce an integral defined on the linear space and preserving super-additivity. We propose a new definition of integral that is based only on shift-invariant collection integrals.
Definition 2. Let be a collection and μ be a capacity. Then is shift-invariant
if and only iffor all and . Remark 1. For any collection there is a monotone set function μ so that is shift-invariant. Indeed, it is enough to consider any maximal set and a monotone set function μ such that and for all . Note that then .
Proposition 2. If is a disjoint system, that is, and if , then the collection integral is shift-invariant for any capacity μ.
Proof. Let
consist of disjoint sets, and let
be any monotone set function. Then one obtains that
from which it follows that
is shift-invariant for any
□
Definition 3. Let be a collection and μ be a monotone set function such that is a shift-invariant collection integral. A functionalis called a super-additive integral
with respect to a collection and a monotone set function μ. Remark 2. Note that the definition of involves non-negative functions and , a and thus is well-defined.
In the following theorem some basic properties of the super-additive integral are proven.
Theorem 1. Let be a super-additive integral. Then
for all , that is, extends ;
for all and , that is, is positively homogeneous;
for all and , that is, is shift-invariant;
for all , that is, is bounded below by a (normed) infimum; and
for all , that is, is super-additive.
Proof. Let
be the super-additive integral. Then
is shift-invariant. Based on these facts and the fact that
one easily obtains
because
. This implies the first property of the theorem.
Now, if
and
, and thanks to the positive homogeneity of
, we obtain that
proving the second property of the theorem. To see that the third statement of the theorem is true, it is enough to notice that
as needed. The fourth property follows directly from the definition, because
is non-negative, that is,
and, lastly, to see that
is super-additive, let
be two functions and let
and note that
. Then
that is,
is a super-additive operator; which proves the theorem. □
On the other hand, there are collections admitting capacity such that is not shift-invariant.
Example 3. Let and let . Then
if for all , it holdsand hence is shift-invariant; ifand is such that , , and , then , , andviolating the shift-invariance of .
6. Conclusions and Discussion
In this paper we have introduced, discussed and exemplified a new construction method for coherent lower previsions acting on finite universe
, and, by duality, for coherent upper previsions. Our approach was based on a so called collection integral with respect to a monotone measure, a super-additive functional acting on non-negative random variables. In the case when this integral was shift-invariant, we have extended it to a super-additive functional acting on all real random variables on
, and called a super-additive integral. Its normalized form was shown to be a coherent lower prevision. We have discussed and exemplified several particular cases, showing the potential of our construction method for obtaining new types of coherent lower (upper) previsions. As a by product of our studies, several new interesting results were obtained. So, for example, we have shown that for any monotone set function
, which represents the belief of the subject about a random phenomenon, there is a collection
, consisting of disjoint subsets of
, such that a coherent lower prevision can be defined by the corresponding super-additive integral. Also, we have shown that for any collection
there is a unanimity measure
(i.e., it asses value 1 to some set in
and each its superset, and value 0 to any other sets) such that a coherent lower prevision can be defined by the super-additive integral. In monotone measure theory, another our result could be of interest, namely, considering any chain collection
and any monotone measure
. Then the related coherent lower prevision applied to characteristic functions yields a super-modular measure. We expect applications of our results in all domains where the imprecise probabilities are applied, in particular in decision problems. As a possible further research expanding our results, we think on the study of simple decomposition systems (consisting, e.g., of two collections) and related decomposition integrals, where our approach considered for single collections could be successfully applied and result into another type of coherent lower (upper) previsions. Another branch of research can deal with super-decomposition integrals introduced in Ref. [
23] and their use for constructing of coherent upper previsions. Note also that all our work was done on a finite universe
. Then, for sure, a challenging task would be the general case, dealing with monotone measure space
, in which case the coherent lower (upper) previsions are functionals on bounded real random variables.
Results proposed in this paper show that any monotone set function which represents uncertainty can be used to define a coherent lower prevision by the super-additive integral and this non-linear integral is a mathematical tool to aggregate in a coherent way information represented by different uncertainty measures in the finite case.