Protestant Political Theology and Pluralism: From a Politics of Refusal to Tending and Organizing for Common Goods
Abstract
:1. Political Theology
2. Plurality
3. The Secular
4. Democracy
5. The 1790s to the 1970s: For the Love of Country, Neighbor, and Stranger
Funding
Conflicts of Interest
References
- Augustine, Saint. 1998. The City of God against the Pagans. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Barbauld, Anna. 1825. The Works of Anna Lætitia Barbauld. London: Longman, Hurst, Rees, Orme, Brown, and Green, Available online: http://hdl.handle.net/2027/mdp.39015007012860 (accessed on 9 September 2019).
- Berger, Peter L., ed. 1999. The Desecularization of the World: Resurgent Religion and World Politics, 1st ed. Washington: Grand Rapids, Mich: Eerdmans. [Google Scholar]
- Bilgrami, Akeel. 2014. Secularism, Identity, and Enchantment. Cambridge: Harvard University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Bowlin, John R. 2011. Just Democracy, Just Church: Hauerwas and Coles on Radical Democracy and Christianity. Scottish Journal of Theology 64: 80–95. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Bowlin, John R. 2016. Tolerance among the Virtues. Princeton: Princeton University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Bowlin, John R, and Andrew Latham. 2016. Is the Common Good Obsolete? Commonweal Magazine. Available online: https://www.commonwealmagazine.org/common-good-obsolete (accessed on 27 December 2018).
- Bretherton, Luke. 2019. Christ and the Common Life: Political Theology and the Case for Democracy. Grand Rapids: Eerdmans. [Google Scholar]
- Cannon, Katie G. 2006. Black Womanist Ethics. Eugene: Wipf & Stock. [Google Scholar]
- Coakley, Sarah. 2013. God, Sexuality, and the Self: An Essay “On the Trinity”. Cambridge and New York: Cambridge University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Daniel, E. White. 2006. Early Romanticism and Religious Dissent. Cambridge Studies in Romanticism. Cambridge and New York: Cambridge University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Dorrien, Gary. 2019. Social Democracy in the Making: Political and Religious Roots of European Socialism. New Haven: Yale University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Dyson, Michael Eric, and David L. Jagerman. 2000. I May Not Get There with You: The True Martin Luther King, Jr. New York: Simon and Schuster. [Google Scholar]
- Farneth, Molly. 2019. A Politics of Tending and Transformation. Studies in Christian Ethics 32: 113–18. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Gilroy, Paul. 1993. The Black Atlantic: Modernity and Double-Consciousness. Reissue edition. Cambridge: Harvard University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Gregory, Brad S. 2015. The Unintended Reformation: How a Religious Revolution Secularized Society. Reprint Edition. Cambridge: Belknap Press: An Imprint of Harvard University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Gregory, Eric, and Joseph Clair. 2015. Augustinianisms and Thomisms. In The Cambridge Companion to Christian Political Theology. Edited by Craig Hovey and Elizabeth Phillips. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 176–95. [Google Scholar]
- Harrison, Peter. 2015. The Territories of Science and Religion. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. [Google Scholar]
- Hauerwas, Stanley. 1995. Preaching as Though We Had Enemies|Stanley Hauerwas. First Things. Available online: https://www.firstthings.com/article/1995/05/003-preaching-as-though-we-had-enemies (accessed on 23 May 2019).
- Hauerwas, Stanley. 2008. Christianity, Democracy, and the Radical Ordinary: Conversations Between a Radical Democrat and a Christian. Eugene: Wipf & Stock Pub. [Google Scholar]
- Hauerwas, Stanley. 2010. How Real Is America’s Faith?|Stanley Hauerwas: Face to Faith. The Guardian. Available online: https://www.theguardian.com/commentisfree/belief/2010/oct/16/faith-america-secular-britain (accessed on 16 October 2010).
- Hauerwas, Stanley. 2013. Review of Rowan Williams’s Faith in the Public Square. Theology 116: 119–22. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Hauerwas, Stanley. 2015a. Performing the Faith: Bonhoeffer and the Practice of Nonviolence. Eugene: Wipf & Stock. [Google Scholar]
- Hauerwas, Stanley. 2015b. The Work of Theology. Grand Rapids: Eerdmans. [Google Scholar]
- Hauerwas, Stanley. 2017. After the Reformation: How to Be Neither Catholic Nor Protestant. ABC Religion & Ethics. Available online: https://www.abc.net.au/religion/after-the-reformation-how-to-be-neither-catholic-nor-protestant/10095238 (accessed on 1 November 2017).
- Hauerwas, Stanley, and William H. Willimon. 2014. Resident Aliens: Life in the Christian Colony. 25 Exp Anv edition. Nashville: Abingdon Press. [Google Scholar]
- Hector, Kevin W. 2011. Theology Without Metaphysics: God, Language and the Spirit of Recognition. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Herdt, Jennifer A. 2016. Proximate Common Goods in the Context of Pluralism. Journal of Medieval and Early Modern Studies 46: 583–602. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Hovey, Craig, and Elizabeth Phillips, eds. 2015. The Cambridge Companion to Christian Political Theology. Cambridge Companions to Religion. New York, NY: Cambridge University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Jennings, Willie James. 2011. The Christian Imagination: Theology and the Origins of Race. New Haven: Yale University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Lloyd, Vincent, ed. 2012. Race and Political Theology, 1st ed. Stanford: Stanford University Press. [Google Scholar]
- MacIntyre, Alasdair. 2007. After Virtue: A Study in Moral Theory, 3rd ed. Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press. [Google Scholar]
- Maclure, Jocelyn, Charles Taylor, and Jane Marie Todd. 2011. Secularism and Freedom of Conscience. Cambridge: Harvard University Press, Available online: https://www.jstor.org/stable/j.ctt2jbrc0 (accessed on 28 May 2019).
- Markus, Robert Austin. 1989. Saeculum: History and Society in the Theology of St Augustine, 2nd ed. Cambridge and New York: Cambridge University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Mathewes, Charles, and Christopher McKnight Nichols. 2008. Prophesies of Godlessness Predictions of America’s Imminent Secularization from the Puritans to the Present Day, 1st ed. Oxford: Oxford University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Milbank, John, Catherine Pickstock, and Graham Ward, eds. 1998. Radical Orthodoxy: A New Theology, 1st ed. London and New York: Routledge. [Google Scholar]
- Norris, Pippa. 2011. Sacred and Secular: Religion and Politics Worldwide, 2nd ed. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. [Google Scholar]
- O’Neill, Daniel I. 2007. John Adams versus Mary Wollstonecraft on the French Revolution and Democracy. Journal of the History of Ideas 68: 451–76. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Price, Richard. 1790. A Discourse on the Love of Our Country. Boston: Edward E. Powars. First published 1789. [Google Scholar]
- Price, Richard. 1830. Sermons. London: The British and Foreign Unitarian Association, Available online: http://catalog.hathitrust.org/Record/011530849 (accessed on 15 May 2019).
- Pui-lan, Kwok. 2016. Postcolonial Intervention in Political Theology. Political Theology 17: 223–25. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Rasmusson, Arne. 1995. Church as Polis, The: From Political Theology to Theological Politics as Exemplified by Jürgen Moltmann and Stanley Hauerwas. Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press. [Google Scholar]
- Richey, Russell E. 1973. From Puritanism to Unitarianism in England: A Study in Candour. Journal of the American Academy of Religion 41: 371–85. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Rodríguez, Rubén Rosario. 2018. Dogmatics after Babel: Beyond the Theologies of Word and Culture. Louisville: Westminster John Knox Press. [Google Scholar]
- Rosario-Rodriguez, Ruben, ed. 2019. T&T Clark Handbook of Political Theology. London: Bloomsbury Publishing, p. xxi. [Google Scholar]
- Smith, James K. A. 2017. Cultural Liturgies. In Awaiting the King: Reforming Public Theology. Ada: Baker Academic, vol. 3. [Google Scholar]
- Springs, Jason, Cornel West, Richard Rorty, Stanley Hauerwas, and Jeffrey Stout. 2010. Pragmatism and Democracy: Assessing Jeffrey Stout’s Democracy and Tradition. Journal of the American Academy of Religion 78: 413–48. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Stark, Rodney, and Roger Finke. 2000. Acts of Faith: Explaining the Human Side of Religion. Berkeley: University of California Press. [Google Scholar]
- Stepan, Alfred, and Charles Taylor, eds. 2014. Boundaries of Toleration. New York: Columbia University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Stevens, Ralph. 2018. Protestant Pluralism. Suffolk: Boydell Press. [Google Scholar]
- Stout, Jeffrey. 2004. Democracy and Tradition. Princeton: Princeton University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Stout, Jeffrey. 2010. Blessed Are the Organized: Grassroots Democracy in America. Princeton: Princeton University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Taylor, Charles. 2007. A Secular Age, 1st ed. Cambridge: The Belknap Press of Harvard University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Taylor, Mark Lewis. 2011. The Theological and the Political: On the Weight of the World. Minneapolis: Fortress Press. [Google Scholar]
- White, Daniel E. 1804. ‘With Mrs Barbauld It Is Different’: Dissenting Heritage and the Devotional Taste. In Women, Gender and Enlightenment. London: Palgrave Macmillan, pp. 474–92. [Google Scholar]
- Williams, Rowan. 2015. Faith in the Public Square. London and New York: Bloomsbury Continuum. First published 2012. [Google Scholar]
- Wollstonecraft, Mary. 1989. The Works of Mary Wollstonecraft. Edited by Marilyn Butler and Janet Todd. London: W. Pickering. [Google Scholar]
1 | (Hovey and Phillips 2015, p. 46). Hak Joon Lee in the chapter on public theology names three types of pluralism—religious, cultural, and ethic. I am also interested here in moral and theological pluralism, as some of the central figures I engage are primarily concerned with these forms. |
2 | The epithet “modernity’s religious despisers” or “modernity’s despisers” used throughout are not antagonistic, but rather a play on Schleiermacher’s “religion’s cultured despisers.” The declension narratives I have in mind include the following: (MacIntyre 2007; Harrison 2015; Milbank et al. 1998). These narratives share a family resemblance. MacIntyre tells a story of decline. Gregory, while less nostalgic, laments the loss of institutionalized Christendom in the medieval era. With regard to the virtues in modernity, as we will see, the plot lines are strikingly similar. Modernity has arrived and virtue has departed, or so the declensionist story goes. See also (Hauerwas 2015b; Lloyd 2012). All citations from Hauerwas in this essay, unless otherwise noted, come from this 2015 text. Hauerwas and Lloyd do not present narratives of modern decline. Nonetheless, like those above, their portrait of Protestantism is more uniform than the one I present here. Gregory suggests that the Protestant Reformation unintentionally had the effect of secularizing society and that Protestant pluralism, secularism, relativism, liberalism, and democracy all come packaged together. Hauerwas, to his credit, notes that “Christians have not claimed that our vocabularies—and the plural is important—are finished” (158). Nonetheless, his conclusion that “the church does not have a politics, but rather the church is God’s politics for the world” belies the plurality of ecclesial polities and their significance for the Protestants who spilled much blood and ink in their defense (see chapter 9 “How to (Not) be a Political Theologian” specifically 190). Finally, Lloyd raises important questions and points about race, colonialism, and political theology and yet paints Protestantism and “Protestant hegemony” with a broad brush that elides the plurality of protestant perspectives and commitments. |
3 | |
4 | (Farneth 2019). I borrow this basic distinction from Farneth, who draws a distinction between those who endorse a politics of refusal (from the likes of Giorgio Agamben and Slavo Zizek to adherents of Radical Orthodoxy, and the “zombie narratives,” to borrow a phrase from Thomas Lewis, that have followed Alasdair MacIntyre’s declension narrative) and those who advocate for a “politics of tending” (such a Sheldon Wolin who coined the term and James K. Smith whom Farneth commends for adopting this political mode) and I add a “politics of organizing” (such as those elaborated by Jeffrey Stout in Blessed are the Organized and Luke Brethertson in Resurrecting Democracy) for specific political ends and goods. |
5 | For the purposes of this essay, I consider the Protestant tradition as a broad tent that includes any Christian denominations or movements that began after the Reformation and do not belong to the Roman Catholic or Eastern Orthodox church. At the same time, I draw on the work of theologians who most explicitly identify themselves or their work as Protestant in some respect, which is a narrower range. |
6 | Again, the list would be expansive, were I to consider all the theologians and Christian ethicists who provide resources for a politics of tending or organizing. I limit myself here to Protestant theologians and ethicists who either explicitly identify their work with political theology and address questions about pluralism, secularism, and democracy (or reject the term while opting for a another, such as Hauerwas). But I also focus on those who have responded to modernity’s despisers with a more affirming account of these features of modern life. |
7 | (Stevens 2018). |
8 | (Hovey and Phillips 2015, p. 55). Noting the distinctions and similarities among this German tradition of political theology narrowly conceived, public theology, and liberation theology, Hak Joon Lee, argues that “political theology and liberation theology tend to give more weight to the state than to civil society as the primary locus (or instrument) or social change” (55). We will see this is not the case for political theology in the broadest sense. |
9 | See (Lloyd 2012). And forthcoming Ruben Rosariao-Rodriguez’s Introduction in (Rosario-Rodriguez 2019). Here Rosario-Rodriguez notes that “What unites the project, despite the diversity of theological perspectives, is a commitment from all the contributors to engage the political sphere (1) by locating him or herself theologically within the interdisciplinary conversation, (2) by establishing clear methodological parameters for how she or he will participate in the conversation, and (3) by recognizing that this conversation takes place in a religiously and politically pluralist global setting.” For him, the third point about plurality is crucial. “Without denying that certain religious perspectives make exclusivist claims,” he continues, “these claims must be made and defended in the context of political pluralism, tolerance, and cooperation” (xxi). Political theologians should recognize and tolerate plurality even as they advance arguments specific to their own interpretation of their traditions. |
10 | See (Lloyd 2012; Bretherton 2019). |
11 | (Bretherton 2019, pp. 18–19; Taylor 2011; Coakley 2013, p. xvii). See Coakely’s description of theologie totale (xvii ff) |
12 | |
13 | |
14 | (Bretherton 2019). See Bretherton’s first chapter for an excellent overview of these various distinctions and adherents to each. For an account that seeks to blur prevalent distinctions between Augustinian and Thomist accounts see (Gregory and Clair 2015, pp. 176–95). |
15 | (Hauerwas 2015b, p. 171). All references in this paragraph come from this chapter unless otherwise noted. For more on the extent to which Hauerwas identifies as a Protestant theologian see: (Hauerwas 2017). |
16 | (Hauerwas 2015a, p. 34; Rasmusson 1995). It is not precisely clear what this distinction amounts to in the essay itself. Nor do I seek to clarify the muddy water here. Of course, it resembles a similar priority of theology-first politics found, at times, in Karl Barth. Gary Dorrien’s description of Barth’s theology to politics and his conflicts with friends and colleagues over these, could nearly apply to Hauerwas. (Dorrien 2019, p. 267). |
17 | |
18 | (Farneth 2019). Scott’s form of anarchy and Hauerwas’s foot-dragging depend on institutions being in place independent of and prior to episodic disruption. Throughout the chapter, Hauerwas appears to be entirely ambivalent about the form of government or institutions in relation to which the church does its foot-dragging. Of course, the church must be the church in any political context. But I find it hard to believe that Hauerwas would not actually prefer a democratic republic and society like the United States of America (for all its shortcomings) over other totalitarian states as the political context for politics of refusal. The projects of John Milbank and Oliver O’Donovan evince a similar refusal. |
19 | |
20 | (Bowlin 2011). |
21 | See for example (Pui-lan 2016, pp. 223–25). |
22 | (Gregory 2015, p. 112). All of the following citations from Gregory are from this work unless otherwise noted. |
23 | |
24 | See Jennifer Herdt’s perspective response to Gregory’s book. (Herdt 2016). I agree with Herdt that, “Protestantism may have made the issue [of competing views and authorities] more salient, more present to ordinary people throughout Europe. But it did not create the problem of crises of authority, or of rival answers to the big “Life Questions” (587). Still, I would add that Protestantism did not only “make the issue more salient”—it did so by formally challenging the claim that such debates and doctrinal disputes could only be adjudicated by the institutional authority of a single church. While it did not create the problem of the crises of authority, it did provide a very different set of answers, institutions, and polities in response to the crises of authority. One crucial part of that response includes the conviction that authority cannot only be adjudicated or mediated by the institution of the church alone, but depends a community with a priesthood of all believers. |
25 | |
26 | |
27 | (Williams [2012] 2015). See especially Chapter 10 entitled “Pluralism: Public and Religious.” |
28 | (Hauerwas 2013). He finds compelling the idea that “the body is not simply one object among other objects, and therefore, should not be used as an instrument for imposing my will on others.” |
29 | (Herdt 2016). |
30 | The secularization thesis—the idea that traditional religions are in terminal decline in the industrialized world and that as modern societies progress religion loses its authority in all aspects of social life and governance–was a central debate in the sociology of religion in the second half of the twentiety century. |
31 | (Gregory 2015, p. 87). For this reason it is not, as Gregory claims, ironic that Martin Luther would cite Jean Gerson and Augustine as authorities to substantiate his point that “No faithful Christian can be forced beyond the sacred scripture, which is nothing less than [porprie]] divine law…” Luther understood that the foundational importance of scripture is not at odds with but rather depends on a tradition of Christian interpretation and theological reflection. Likewise, while the priesthood of all believers tends to emphasize the unmediated access of each believer to God, still depends on the respective polities and ecclesial forms of accountability. Even at its most extreme, the doctrine does not generally entail the endorsement of subjective beliefs, or the relativity of all truth claims, but rather the access each individual may have to God’s revelation. |
32 | (Augustine 1998, chp. 17). Many scholars have noted this famous passage in Book 19 that “even the heavenly city, therefore, while in its state of pilgrimage, avails itself of the peace of earth, and, so far as it can without injuring faith and godliness, desires and maintains a common agreement among men regarding the acquisition of the necessaries of life, and makes this earthly peace bear upon the peace of heaven.” And yet Augustine’s emphasis on plurality of languages, laws, manners, and institutions that all have their proximate end in earthly peace in the passages directly prior to this one is also particularly notable. “This heavenly city, then, while it sojourns on earth, calls citizens out of all nations, and gathers together a society of pilgrims of all languages, not scrupling about diversities in the manners, laws, and institutions whereby earthly peace is secured and maintained, but recognizing that, however various these are, they all tend to one and the same end of earthly peace. It therefore is so far from rescinding and abolishing these diversities, that it even preserves and adopts them, so long only as no hindrance to the worship of the one supreme and true God is thus introduced” (emphasis mine). |
33 | (Stout 2004, p. 296). Stout is quick to clarify that, “I see this pluralism primarily as an existing feature of the political culture, not as a philosophical doctrine needed to be imposed on it.” Oddly enough, Hauerwas in his response to the book claims that “[Stout] affirms pluralism. And it’s not clear to me he really knows what he’s talking about when he says the word “pluralism.” I take it that despite where you’re standing, to be able to know that we live in a pluralist world is already part of the problem of naming pluralism” (Springs et al. 2010, p. 430). This is an odd claim given Stout’s explicit treatment of the term, in which he clarifies what he means by the word. The onus appears to be on Hauerwas. And is it not so? One could believe in monism and still recognize moral and religious pluralism. |
34 | (Smith 2017). I take Williams’s “interactive pluralism” and James K. A. Smith’s attempt to move beyond “principled pluralism” to signal a similar acceptance and even affirmation of the fact of pluralism. |
35 | (Bowlin 2016). |
36 | |
37 | |
38 | (Stark and Finke 2000, p. 79). They claimed that it is time to bury the secularization thesis: “After nearly three centuries of utterly failed prophesies and misrepresentations of both present and past, it seems time to carry the secularization doctrine to the graveyard of failed theories, and there to whisper ‘requiescat in pace.’” Conversely, Herdt agrees with Gregory that the process of secularization in modernity was largely unintended, but insists that we now live in a post-secular age. (Herdt 2016, p. 601; Taylor 2007). |
39 | (Berger 1999, p. 2; Stark and Finke 2000, p. 79); So too see Norris, especially chapter 1, for an overview of secularization debates. (Norris 2011). |
40 | (Springs et al. 2010, p. 430). Similar anxieties about plurality, subjectivism, and secularity, understood as the way that democratic politics keep “out of public discussion matters that matter exactly because they matter, and represses such conflict,” particularly religious matters, have long animated Hauerwas. |
41 | (Williams [2012] 2015, pp. 2–3). Williams distinction between procedural and programmatic echoes the one that Charles Taylor has recently drawn between two basic notions of secularism—one that that seeks to regulate and control religion and limit the role of religious discourse in public, and the other that seeks to preserve the space for religious or theological difference and plurality. He advocates for the latter. See his chapter “How to Define Secularism” in (Stepan and Taylor 2014). See also Akeel Bilgrami’s response in the following chapter “Secularism: Its Content and Context,” where he offers three defining characteristics of secularism before suggesting that its merits depend on the context. |
42 | |
43 | |
44 | Secularism remains a much-disputed concept. Akeel Bilgrami argues that it is value neutral in the sense that its value depends on the ends sought in a specific context. Others, such as Hauerwas, reject the secular as inherently adversarial toward Christianity or exclusionary and opposed to religious views. While still others, such as Jocelyn Maclure and Charles Taylor, argue that secularism, properly understood, is essential to any liberal democracy and may offer the only path to religious and philosophical freedom. Of course, precisely how secularism should be “properly understood” is at the heart of these debates. (Maclure et al. 2011; Hauerwas 2010; Springs et al. 2010; Bilgrami 2014; Mathewes and Nichols 2008; Gregory 2015). |
45 | |
46 | |
47 | |
48 | |
49 | (Springs et al. 2010, p. 430). In response to Stout’s book, Hauerwas confirmed his fear that “Democratic politics is so adept at keeping out of public discussion matters that matter exactly because they matter, and represses such conflict.” As with pluralism and secularism he is concerned that democratic politics relegate the matters that matter most—religious beliefs, claims, and practices—to the private realm. Yet, this presumption runs explicitly against Stout’s argument for democracy and pluralism (as seen above) which seeks to create space for productive contestation across lines of religious and non-religious difference. |
50 | |
51 | Hauerwas, 177. |
52 | |
53 | |
54 | |
55 | (Stout 2010). |
56 | |
57 | (Bretherton 2019, p. 463). And see chapter 6 and p. 175 for a summary comparison of the differences in Pentecostal, Catholic, and Anglican polities as populist, institutionalized, and fluvial respectively. |
58 | (Bretherton 2019, p. 184). See also p. 161 where he distinguishes this “consociational” vision of sovereignty from “top-down, monistic, and transcendent conceptions of sovereignty.” |
59 | |
60 | (Cannon 2006). |
61 | Penalties against Unitarians were not removed until the Unitarian Toleration Bill (1813). |
62 | (Daniel 2006). |
63 | |
64 | Gregory concedes that rights had a theological inception in the early modern era, but he mourns their secular modern progseny without specifying when this ostensible change occurred. |
65 | |
66 | The Toleration Act, as it is now commonly called, allowed freedom of worship and conscience for all Trinitarian Christians in Maryland. Still, it sentenced to death anyone who denied the divinity of Jesus. Religious tolerance and freedom has apparently always had its limits, even if we draw them quite differently today. |
67 | (Richey 1973). Russel Richey has argued that the history of dissent can be traced through the transformation of the central dissenting virtue of candour, which was expressed in four successive ideals: purity, kindness, open-mindedness or tolerance, and finally open avowal or outspokenness. Thomas Holcroft (1745–1809) fervently believed in human perfectibility. He was tried for and acquitted of high treason in 1794, but continued to remain suspect as a free thinker. Wollstonecraft reviews his novel Anna St. Ives, in the Analytic Review, and notes that it “appears to be written as a vehicle to convey what are called democratical sentiments.” |
68 | (Price [1789] 1790, p. 6). Other citations in this paragraph are from the same text. |
69 | (Daniel 2006). |
70 | (O’Neill 2007). |
71 | (Wollstonecraft 1989). All citations from Wollstonecraft that follow are from this source, unless otherwise noted. The fifth volume includes both of her Vindications. |
72 | Moral and doctrinal plurality within the church has been a more or less conspicuous fact of the Christian church since its inception, even if the schism of 1054 and the Protestant reformation brought institutional plurality. Bretherton’s consociational approach, Kevin Hector pneumatological approach, and Rosario-Rodriguez’s liberation and pneumatological approach provide theological warrant for embracing religious, theological, and moral plurality respectively. In addition to Bretherton, see (Hector 2011; Rodríguez 2018). As Ruben Rosario-Rodriguez asks Dogmatics After Babel, “what happens when we stop viewing theological pluralism as a problem to be solved (Babel) and embrace it as a gift of the Spirit (Pentecost)?” (xiv–xv). |
© 2019 by the author. Licensee MDPI, Basel, Switzerland. This article is an open access article distributed under the terms and conditions of the Creative Commons Attribution (CC BY) license (http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/).
Share and Cite
Dumler-Winckler, E. Protestant Political Theology and Pluralism: From a Politics of Refusal to Tending and Organizing for Common Goods. Religions 2019, 10, 522. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel10090522
Dumler-Winckler E. Protestant Political Theology and Pluralism: From a Politics of Refusal to Tending and Organizing for Common Goods. Religions. 2019; 10(9):522. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel10090522
Chicago/Turabian StyleDumler-Winckler, Emily. 2019. "Protestant Political Theology and Pluralism: From a Politics of Refusal to Tending and Organizing for Common Goods" Religions 10, no. 9: 522. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel10090522
APA StyleDumler-Winckler, E. (2019). Protestant Political Theology and Pluralism: From a Politics of Refusal to Tending and Organizing for Common Goods. Religions, 10(9), 522. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel10090522