Positivism and Reasonableness: Authoritarian Leanings in New Atheism’s Thinking
Abstract
:1. Introduction
2. Beyond Agonistic Politics
2.1. Why Reasonableness Is Important for Democracy
2.2. Reasonableness and Reasonable Comprehensive Doctrines
“In Europe up to the eighteenth century the holding of heretical beliefs was one of the public crimes par excellence […], the suppression of heresy was therefore in everyone’s interest. Liberals, however, think that theory (of collective responsibility before God) is wrong and disallow that you are ‘affecting’ your neighbors and fellow citizens in any relevant sense simply by holding a certain belief, even a heretical one. So the liberal can make an effective distinction between public and private in cases like this […] by evaluating the truth or falsity of the theory the agents in question hold about what harms or might harm their interests. The question is then: who does the evaluating? Liberals, of course, think they ought to have the final word […]. In other words, it is the fact that liberals think that the beliefs of religiously minded persons (e.g., that God will hold all responsible for the heresies of any one member of the society) are false that is supposed to count as a reason for thinking that religious people have no grounds for the claim”.
“How is it possible for citizens of faith to be wholehearted members of a democratic society who endorses society’s intrinsic political ideals and values and do not simply acquiesce in the balance of political and social forces? […] How is it possible—or is it—for those of faith, as well as the nonreligious (secular), to endorse a constitutional regime even when their comprehensive doctrines may not prosper under it, and indeed may decline”
“In endorsing a constitutional democratic regime, a religious doctrine may say that such are the limits God sets to our liberty; a nonreligious doctrine will express itself otherwise. But in either case, these doctrines formulate in different ways how liberty of conscience and the principle of toleration can cohere with equal justice for all citizens in a reasonable democratic society”(Rawls ibid.).12
2.3. Elements of Reasonable Comprehensive Doctrines
- In the sense of the duty of civility presented above, reasonable comprehensive doctrines must encourage their bearers to give generally acceptable reasons in the political public sphere when it comes to deliberating legal norms, which are then enforced by the state. Rawls (1997, p. 773; 2003, p. 55) suggests that reasonable comprehensive doctrines encourage those who are convinced of them to give reasons that are generally shareable, which, as already indicated, is a supererogatory demand. Rather, for the purpose of avoiding illegitimate coercion, it is sufficient that reasons advanced in deliberation cannot reasonably be rejected (Scanlon 1998, p. 191; Lafont 2009).
- It has to be added that reasonable doctrines will only advocate generally acceptable norms in all politically relevant questions (Rawls 1997, p. 777). They will not, for example, justify a political claim by saying that it is generally acceptable if and only if it is for their own good. Yet, in the case of another political question, if it is perhaps not for their good, they will suspend the principle of public justification.
- Moreover, citizens with reasonable comprehensive doctrines do not simply happen to give generally acceptable claims of validity, but they likewise only apply such justification procedures that could gain intersubjective acceptance (Schmidt 2008, p. 100). Consequently, not only must the political output be generally acceptable in content if a worldview is to be evaluated in terms of its reasonableness, but also the procedure with which it chooses to reach a concrete justification. Reasonable religious citizens, for example, will not recognise the right of other believers to obey their conscience just because they simply have no political power to impose their faith on them. Rather, they will recognise that the justification of the right to freedom of conscience must also be such that it can be accepted by others.
- This, in turn, is based on the fact that reasonable citizens recognise their fellow citizens as free and equal beings, whose autonomy must be respected (Rawls 1997, p. 778)—“tolerance is a primary virtue”, as Judith Shklar (1964, p. 5) puts it.
- This is also based on the fact that in modern, democratic societies, there will simply be an irrevocable pluralism of different world views. In the words of Fraenkel ([1964] 2011), pluralism is a structural element of modern societies that can only be abolished by the use of coercion or violence. Rawls (1989, p. 235; 1993, pp. 54–58) explains this characteristic of modern societies by reminding us that the anthropologically constant burdens of judgement, the idola tribus, always make most of our judgements conditional on being subjective or even flawed as the cognitive faculty of humans is limited in principle. For example, as is well known in epistemology, no unambiguous inductive conclusions can be drawn from observations; rather, they are always dependent on factors such as theoretical premises. Now, moreover, modern societies are characterised by a high degree of functional differentiation, which goes hand in hand with the differentiation of the possible experiential worlds depending on sociological factors such as occupation, gender, place of residence, milieu, et cetera. This diversification of the possible experiential worlds favours the fact that the already operative burdens of judgement are thus given a much larger contact surface. At the micro-level, those who live in modern societies therefore form differently coloured worldviews depending on their social position. One could say that Rawls is in a way approaching the well-known Marxian hypothesis, according to which social being determines consciousness. The result of this is that modern sociality, mediated by the mechanism of functional differentiation, will on the macro-level develop an irrevocable pluralism of reasonable yet possibly divergent comprehensive doctrines, whereby different worldviews cannot necessarily be attributed to cognitive failures, but rather to different social positions.
- From the acceptance of the burdens of judgement follows the preparedness to learn from others (Benhabib 1992, p. 98; Apel 1993, p. 510).
- From this also comes, at the same time, the preparedness to accept only such truth claims in deliberation—if it is necessary to deal with them—that can be justified beyond different worldviews, which means truth claims made by common sense or science, as far as they are widely undisputed and comprehensible (Rawls 1993, p. 224).
- It follows from what has been said that, as far as the basic institutional order of a society is concerned, reasonable doctrines accept a system of certain fundamental human and citizen rights that cannot be rejected. These are the classical liberal rights to negative liberty and the republican rights of participation, but also social, ecological, and technological rights, which make the realisation of the former possible in the first place (Habermas 1996, 122f.; Rawls 1997, p. 774).
3. New Atheism as an Unreasonable Comprehensive Doctrine
3.1. Outlining New Atheism
“the social aspect of dogmatism includes, above all, institutional arrangements created by groups with dogmatic belief systems […] to immunise their members against the influence of dissenting views and dangerous ideas and information”.(ibid., 97, trans. M.R.)
“The commitment to making religious allegiance a private matter must be maintained, and, in consequence, religious considerations must not be allowed to enter public debate. Campaigning for greater public understanding of science can readily be supported by appeal to democratic principles: insistence on using scientific standards as constitutive of genuine knowledge would support the dissemination of correct information, thus enabling citizens to identify their genuine interests. For, after all, the possibility that democratic involvement will promote freedom seems to depend on giving the citizenry the best possible factual basis for forming their judgement.”
“In my secularist view, those standards [for public reasoning] can only come from insistence on the priority of science, but that insistence must make room for the religious impulses and concerns that militant secularists currently ignore. Secularism must be humane, recognizing the needs for community, for social support, for ways of exploring why human lives matter”.
3.2. Why New Atheism Is an Unreasonable Comprehensive Doctrine
“The assumption that a deterministic nature of the physically observable world (to the extent that may be true) can account for subjective conscious functions and event, is a speculative belief, not a scientifically proven proposition. Nondeterminism, the view that conscious will may, at times, exert effects not in accord with known physical laws, is of course an unproven speculative belief. […] Given the speculative nature of both determinist and nondeterminist theories, why not adopt the view that we do have free will (until some real contradictory evidence may appear, if it ever does)? Such a view would at least allow us to proceed in a way that accepts and accommodates our own deep feelings that we do have free will.”
“What is lacking, to my knowledge, is a credible argument that the story has a nonnegligible probability of being true. […] My skepticism is not based on religious belief, or on a belief in any definite alternative. It is just a belief that the available scientific evidence […] does not in this matter rationally require us to subordinate the incredulity of common sense”.(Nagel ibid., 6f.)
3.3. “Protective Coloration for Their Fanatical Coreligionists”? New Atheism’s Rhetoric of Reaction
“by their good works they provide protective coloration for their fanatical coreligionists, who quietly condemn their open-mindedness and willingness to change while reaping the benefits of the good public relations they thereby obtain.”
4. Conclusions
Funding
Conflicts of Interest
1 | I would like to thank Boris Knorre, Tobias Köllner, Selina Roßgardt and the anonymous reviewers for their helpful comments. |
2 | In general, religion is perceived in its traditional forms in Western societies as monotheism. |
3 | For a contrasting position cf. Schulzke (2013). As will become clear in the course of my article, I do not agree with Schulzke in the sense that at least the premises of New Atheism are incongruent with democratic premises and values, even if the representatives of New Atheism may believe this, thereby following authors such as Peterson (2010) or Wilde (2010). |
4 | While Denett is generally described as a New Atheist, Albert’s and Kitcher’s relationships to New Atheism are more or less pronounced. A major player in New Atheism in Germany is the Giordano Bruno Foundation, of which Hans Albert is a member and which also founded the Hans Albert Institute. Furthermore, other texts dealing with New Atheism also refer to Albert (cf. Viertbauer 2019). Therefore, it seems plausible to engage with his critique of religion to analyse New Atheism. Kitcher, however, does not call himself a New Atheist, but represents a so-called secular humanism, which in turn is also seen as something that can be counted as a part of New Atheism. Furthermore, his critique of political religions is the same as that of New Atheism. Therefore, it seems opportune to engage with his writings if one wants to understand New Atheism. Sociologically, it is therefore important to emphasise at this point that I do not understand New Atheism as a single monolithic social movement, but rather as a specific way of thinking that can be found among various public persons, social movements, parties, and organisations. |
5 | For a detailed critique of the analogy between market processes and (normatively appropriate) democratic procedures, see Rawls (1972, pp. 356–62) or Elster (1992, pp. 103–20). |
6 | This of course raises the question of how to include those who are affected in a relevant manner but are not members of the legal community. As the freedom and equality of human beings is at the core of the democratic ideal, this is not only a general moral question, which, for example, a theory of global justice has to address, but also a genuine democratic theoretical question (cf. Goodin 2007). For reasons of simplicity, however, in the following I only formulate for the state context of democratic self-legislation. |
7 | On the concept of deliberative systems, cf. Mansbridge et al. (2012). |
8 | This situation is different from the obligations (not duties) of actors in the political–administrative system, which come with the specific post (cf. Rawls 1972, pp. 113, 342–44). |
9 | Rawls’s and Habermas’s social theoretical premise is not unusual in political theory. For similar positions cf. Taylor (1995), Audi (1997, p. 16), Pettit (2004), and Böckenförde (2021b). |
10 | In this respect, I assess the critical plea of Gaus and Vallier (2009, pp. 65–70) to shift the research on public reason from the perspective on civic activity to institutional design as at least partially misguided. |
11 | See also Raz (1990). This does not mean that I do not put the enforcement of my convictions last because of tolerance, which among others means in the light of “higher-order reasons” (Forst 2013, p. 20). However, I am convinced by these “higher-order reasons”. |
12 | For Catholic forms of reasonable doctrines cf. Böckenförde (2021a); for Islamic forms cf. Bassiouni (2014). |
13 | In this sense, Audi (1997) developed out of a religious perspective an explicitly natural–theological justification of public reason. However, the problem of the proposal found in Political liberalism is not that it argues (unreasonably) metaphysically by qualifying publicly accepted values as better for whatever reasons but that it is assumed that the citizens of democratic societies see this in such a way themselves and as congruent with their comprehensive doctrines. Therefore, the proposal is relative to a certain political culture. There are no universally good reasons for them do to so, just those which they can find in their comprehensive doctrines. “The epistemic justification of the procedure in which Rawls gains the freestanding conception of justice, however, can […] be understood in terms of a perspectival and contextualist rationalism. On the level of rational procedures themselves, according to this view, there is no rational consensus, but only contextually attuned standards of rationality” (Schmidt 2008, p. 100, trans. M.R.). So, one could justifiably argue that Rawls’s premises for concluding what justice, and therefore public reasoning, demand are culturally and historically relative and contingent. One could, for example, argue that Rawls’s duty of civility might be easy to accept in a society such as the United States of America, which Rawls primarily addresses, because due to historical factors, there is a relatively large number of Protestants, and Protestantism is said to have a primary focus on the individual’s inner religiosity, which does not need to express itself in public and especially not in the political realm. However, when, for example, because of migration and cultural change, new forms of religion and other comprehensive doctrines take on a significant position in this particular society, the concept of public reason as found in Liberalism can no longer justify itself, because the cultural background consensus supporting it has become porous. |
14 | With the assumption of a congruence between the right and the good, Rawls circumvents the supposedly existing motivational problem of Kantian moral theories (cf. Korsgaard 1996, pp. 38–46): reasonable persons act rightly because it seems meaningful and good for them to do so against the background of their comprehensive doctrine. |
15 | I do not turn to the question of how reasonable comprehensive doctrines come into being, but only assume with Rawls that they exist and are important for the existence of stable democracies, despite the fact of pluralism. |
16 | As Jeremy Waldron (2002, p. 20) rightly points out, much of New Atheism‘s hostility to religious belief is one-sided because it is directed at fundamentalist forms of religion, for example denominations that interpret the Bible in a verbally inspired way, often in stark contrast to current scientific knowledge. “Secular theorists often assume that they know what religious argument is like: they present it as a crude prescription from God, backed up with threat of hellfire, derived from general or particular revelation, and they contrast it with the elegant complexity of a philosophical argument by Rawls (say) or Dworkin. With this image in mind, they think it obvious that religious argument should be excluded from public life […]. But those who have bothered to make themselves familiar with existing religious-based arguments in modern political theory know that this is mostly a travesty; and I suspect that it might be as caricatural of religious argumentation in Locke’s day as it is of religious argument in our own“ (ibid.). Of course, it is a problem in terms of democratic theory when fundamentalistic groups try to exert influence, for example on the design of school curricula. However, to identify these cases as pars pro toto for religion in the public sphere is a generalisation that cannot be justified. |
17 | |
18 | Therefore, Kitcher (2008, p. 8) speaks of hybrid epistemologies: “Let’s take a religion to be supernaturalist if it supposes that there are entities or forces quite different in kind from those that are encountered in typical human experience, beings that somehow transcend the events and processes of the ordinary physical world. […] Supernaturalist religions usually come with a body or text or a rich oral tradition, in which the nature of the transcendent entities is explained; the faithful are expected to acquire correct beliefs about these entities and to adopt appropriate attitudes towards them and, derivately, towards the rest of the universe.” Yet, it remains open as to why there cannot be an epistemological pluralism, and Kitcher’s formulation sounds as if supernaturalist doctrines were something close to superstition, whereas naturalism is equalised with “typical human experience”. However, one has to remember that every non-naturalistic worldview, for example Kant’s philosophy or doctrines that think of human beings as in possession of free will, has to be considered as supernaturalistic. |
19 | Habermas (2019a, pp. 75–109) asks in his new work This too a history of philosophy how it could be that nowadays religions continue to enjoy individual and social significance in the face of the world-explaining authority of modern sciences and the normative authority of secular states and tries to explain this via the function of religious rites. In order to contrast the difference, Albert (2000, pp. 215–17), on the other hand, would probably rather interpret their continuing significance as the result of “dogmatisation” that has not been eliminated. |
20 | I leave aside the cases in which the subjective views of certain persons justify politically generally acceptable demands, for example specific freedom rights. |
21 | This distinguishes New Atheism from other exclusive positions such as that of Nagel (1987), which in the end also want to mostly keep religious reasons out of the public sphere. Nagel, however, does not argue that religious convictions are irrational but sees no social basis for deliberating about them. |
22 | Admittedly, Marx’s theory of religion is more complex. Thus, in the context of his critique of the fetishism of commodities and the secret thereof, he addresses not only the critique of religion, but also the critique made by religion. There, however untrue their beliefs may be for Marx, Judaism and Christian nevertheless appear as emancipative and rationalising in comparison to the Nature religions (Marx [1867] 1978, 326f.). Thus, Marx’s critique of religion is three-layered in the sense that it also sees religious thought as an indicator for pathological conditions against which it opposes itself, as well as assigning an at least historically relatively rationalising character to some religions. |
23 | One could try to prove that religious convictions grounded in experiences that are evidential (cf. Plantinga 1999) and therefore also outside of New Atheism’s perspective are epistemically justified. In this respect, the demand for the exclusion of religious reasons and the use of merely evidentialist reasons could be cancelled out as a false contradiction. Such an argumentation, however, will not be pursued here, but I have sketched it elsewhere (Roseneck 2021, pp. 112–34). |
24 | This, of course, is therefore a performative self-contradiction because this statement itself cannot be evidentially substantiated. A methodologically relativistic position, on the other hand, would, for example, for the purpose of biological research, only perceive the world in terms of what can be said about the observable, without immediately saying that the world is only observable. |
25 | I define positivism as an epistemology and a worldview that assumes that only empirically observable entities exist or, in a weaker understanding, that only from these can epistemically justified knowledge be derived. Accordingly, phenomena such as a non-naturalistically understood mind, free will, et cetera cannot exist or, with regard to the weaker conception of positivism, intellectually justifiable knowledge cannot exist about them. In this sense, my conception of positivism can be linked to other concepts, such as scientism or naturalism (cf. Kambartel 1995). |
26 | “Scientism [as a part of New Atheism’s worldview] enters into a genuine relation of competition with religious doctrines, however, once it develops a naturalistic worldview and extends that scientifically objectivating standpoint into the lifeworld by applying it to acting and experiencing persons with the demand for self-objectiviation of everyday knowledge” (Habermas 2008b, p. 245). I thank an anonymous reviewer for explicitly pointing out these passages in Habermas’s work to me. |
27 | Habermas (1972, pp. 214–45) vividly demonstrates this connection between discourse and autonomy outside normative political theory in an early critique of Freud’s contradictory presentation of psychoanalytic theory and method. While Freud still theorises on the basis of the theory of drives, he yet assumes for the psychotherapeutical practice that the analytical discourse would enlighten the individual about repressed aspects of their past and thus lay cognitive foundations for action that would henceforth be counted as mentally caused in the sense of Audi. |
28 | Here, my argumentation has to be differentiated insofar as, on the one hand, there are authors who are at least close to the thinking of New Atheism and who explicitly reject the traditional concept of a free will (Harris 2012; Roth 2016)—Gerhard Roth, for example, advocates a conception of reality that is synonymous with that of Albert. On the other hand, one can of course say that if a New Atheist assumes a strictly positivistic worldview, the rejection of something like free will is logically compelling, even if not all New Atheists necessarily hold this explicitly. |
29 | “Exploring the semantics of the term ‘reaction’ points straight to an important characteristic of ‘reactionary’ thinking. Because of the stubbornly progressive temper of the modern era, ‘reactionaries’ live in a hostile world. They are up against an intellectual climate in which a positive value attached to whatever lofty objective is placed on the social agenda by self-proclaimed, progressives’. Given the state of public opinion, reactionaries are not likely to launch an all-out attack on that objective. Rather, they will endorse it, sincerely or otherwise, but then attempt to demonstrate that the action proposed or undertaken is ill-conceived; indeed, they will most typically urge that this action will produce, via a chain of unintended consequences, the exact contrary of the objective proclaimed and pursued” (Hirschman 1991, p. 11). In this sense, one can differentiate perverse argumentation from justified slippery slope arguments in that the latter give sufficient reasons why a certain action might cause troublesome, perhaps opposite, consequences. |
References
- Albert, Hans. 1973. Theologische Holzwege. Gerhard Ebeling und der rechte Gebrauch der Vernunft. Tübingen: Mohr Siebeck. [Google Scholar]
- Albert, Hans. 1975. Traktat über die Kritische Vernunft, 3rd ed. Tübingen: Mohr Siebeck. [Google Scholar]
- Albert, Hans. 1979. Das Elend der Theologie. Kritische Auseinandersetzungen mit Hans Küng. Hamburg: Hoffmann und Campe. [Google Scholar]
- Albert, Hans. 2000. Kritischer Rationalismus. Vier Kapitel zur Kritik des illusionären Denkens. Tübingen: Mohr Siebeck. [Google Scholar]
- Albert, Hans. 2011. Kritischer Rationalismus und christlicher Glaube. In Kritische Vernunft und rationale Praxis. Tübingen: Mohr Siebeck, pp. 93–104. [Google Scholar]
- Apel, Karl-Otto. 1976. Das Problem der philosophischen Letztbegründung im Lichte einer transzendentalen Sprachpragmatik. Versuch einer Metakritik des "kritischen Rationalismus". In Sprache und Erkenntnis. Edited by Bernulf Kanitscheider. Innsbruck: Amoe, pp. 55–82. [Google Scholar]
- Apel, Karl-Otto. 1993. Discourse ethics as a response to the novel challenges of today’s reality to coresponsibility. The Journal of Religion 73: 496–513. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Apel, Karl-Otto. 2002. Diskursethik als Antwort auf die Situation des Menschen in der Gegenwart. In Diskursethik und Diskursanthropologie. Edited by Karl-Otto Apela and Marcel Niquet. Freiburg: Alber, pp. 13–94. [Google Scholar]
- Audi, Robert. 1992. Rationality and religious commitment. In Faith, Reason, and Scepticism. Edited by Marcus Hester. Philadelphia: Temple University Press, pp. 50–97. [Google Scholar]
- Audi, Robert. 1997. Liberal democracy and the place of religion in politics. In Religion in the Public Square. The Place of Religious Convictions in Political Debate. Edited by James P. Sterba and Rosemarie Tong. Lanham: Rowman & Littlefield, pp. 1–66. [Google Scholar]
- Audi, Robert. 2006. Religion, Wissenschaft und philosophischer Naturalismus. In Religion und Kulturkritik. Edited by Thomas M. Schmidt and Matthias Lutz-Bachmann. Translated by Michael Adrian. Darmstadt: Wissenschaftliche Buchgesellschaft, pp. 85–97. [Google Scholar]
- Bassiouni, Mahmoud. 2014. Menschenrechte zwischen Universalität und islamischer Legitimität. Berlin: Suhrkamp. [Google Scholar]
- Bassiouni, Mahmoud. 2020. Säkularismus als Herrschaftsdiskurs: Europäische und islamische Perspektiven. In Säkular und Religiös. Herausforderungen für Islamische und Christliche Theologie. Edited by Christian Ströbele, Mohammad Gharaibeh, Klaus Hock and Muna Tatari. Regensburg: Pustet, pp. 40–67. [Google Scholar]
- Bechert, Insa. 2021. Of pride and prejudice—A cross-national exploration of atheist’s national pride. Religions 12: 648. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Benhabib, Seyla. 1992. Models of public space. Hannah Arendt, the liberal tradition and Jürgen Habermas. In Situating the Self. Gender, Community and Postmodernism in Contemporary Ethics. Cambridge: Polity Press, pp. 89–114. [Google Scholar]
- Böckenförde, Ernst-Wolfgang. 2021a. The ethos of modern democracy and the church. In Religion, Law, and Democracy. Selected Writings. Edited by Mirjam Künkler and Tine Stein. Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 61–76. [Google Scholar]
- Böckenförde, Ernst-Wolfgang. 2021b. The rise of the state as a process of secularization. In Religion, Law, and Democracy. Selected Writings. Edited by Mirjam Künkler and Tine Stein. Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 152–67. [Google Scholar]
- Buchheim, Thomas. 2004. Wer kann, der kann auch anders. In Hirnforschung und Willensfreiheit. Zur Deutung der Neuesten Experimente. Edited by Christian Geyer. Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp, pp. 158–65. [Google Scholar]
- Christiano, Thomas. 2008. The Constitution of Equality. Democratic Authority and Its Limits. Oxford: Oxford University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Dennett, Daniel. 2006. Breaking the Spell. Religion as a Natural Phenomenon. New York: Viking. [Google Scholar]
- Easton, David. 1968. The Political System. An Inquiry into the State of Political Science, 9th ed. New York: Knopf. [Google Scholar]
- Elster, Jon. 1992. The market and the forum: Three varieties of political theory. In Foundations of Social Choice Theory. Edited by Jon Elster and Aanund Hylland. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 103–32. [Google Scholar]
- Fehige, Yiftach J. H. 2019. Atheism vs. atheism in the encounter between science and religion. A postmetaphysical exploration. Philosophy, Theology and the Sciences 6: 183–210. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Fishkin, James S. 1984. Beyond Subjective Morality. Ethical Reasoning and Political Philosophy. New Haven: Yale University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Forst, Rainer. 2013. Toleration in Conflict. Past and Present. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Fraenkel, Ernst. 2011. Der Pluralismus als Strukturelement der freiheitlich-rechtsstaatlichen Demokratie. In Deutschland und die Westlichen Demokratie, 9th ed. Edited by Alexander von Brünneck. Baden-Baden: Nomos, pp. 256–80. First published 1964. [Google Scholar]
- Frankfurt, Harry G. 1969. Alternative possibilities and moral responsibility. The Journal of Philosophy 66: 829–39. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Gaus, Gerald F., and Kevin Vallier. 2009. The role of religious conviction in a publicly justified polity. The implications of convergence, asymmetry and political institutions. Philosophy & Social Criticism 35: 51–76. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Geuss, Raymond. 2009. Public Goods, Private Goods. Princeton: Princeton University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Gladkich, Anja, and Gert Pickel. 2013. Politischer Atheismus—Der “neue” Atheismus als politisches Projekt oder Abbild empirischer Realität? In Religion und Politik im Vereinigten Deutschland. Was bleibt von der Rückkehr des Religiösen. Edited by Gert Pickel and Oliver Hidalgo. Wiesbaden: Springer, pp. 137–63. [Google Scholar]
- Goodin, Robert. 2007. Enfranchising all affected interests, and its alternatives. Philosophy & Public Affairs 35: 40–68. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Grätzel, Stephan. 2015. Naturalismus als Glaube. In Abschied von der Lebenswelt? Zur Reichweite Naturwissenschaftlicher Erklärungsansätze. Edited by Tobias Müller and Thomas M. Schmidt. Freiburg: Alber, pp. 15–30. [Google Scholar]
- Günther, Klaus. 2000. Verantwortlichkeit in der Zivilgesellschaft. In Das Interesse der Vernunft. Rückblick auf das Werk von Jürgen Habermas seit “Erkenntnis und Interesse”. Edited by Stefan Müller-Doohm. Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp, pp. 465–85. [Google Scholar]
- Habermas, Jürgen. 1972. Knowledge and Human Interests. Translated by Jeremy J. Shapiro. Cambridge: Polity. [Google Scholar]
- Habermas, Jürgen. 1989. Volkssouveränität als Verfahren. In Die Idee von 1789 in der deutschen Rezeption. Edited by Forum für Philosophie Bad Homburg. Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp, pp. 7–36. [Google Scholar]
- Habermas, Jürgen. 1994. Three normative models of democracy. Constellations 1: 1–10. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Habermas, Jürgen. 1996. Between Facts and Norms. Contributions to a Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy. Cambridge: Polity Press. [Google Scholar]
- Habermas, Jürgen. 2002. Auf dem Weg zu einer liberalen Eugenik? Der Streit um das ethische Selbstverständnis der Gattung. In Die Zukunft der Menschlichen Natur. Auf dem Weg zu einer Liberalen Eugenik? 4th ed. Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp, pp. 34–125. [Google Scholar]
- Habermas, Jürgen. 2008a. Religion in the public sphere. Cognitive presuppositions for the "public use of reason" by religious and secular citizens. In Between Naturalism and Religion. Philosophical Essays. Cambridge: Polity Press, pp. 114–47. [Google Scholar]
- Habermas, Jürgen. 2008b. The boundary between faith and knowledge. On the reception and contemporary importance of Kant’s philosophy of religion. In Between Naturalism and Religion. Philosophical Essays. Cambridge: Polity Press, pp. 209–247. [Google Scholar]
- Habermas, Jürgen. 2018. Interview with Jürgen Habermas. Interview by André Bächtiger. In The Oxford Handbook of Deliberative Democracy. Edited by André Bächtiger, John S. Dryzek, Jane Mansbridge and Mark Warren. Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 871–82. [Google Scholar]
- Habermas, Jürgen. 2019a. Auch eine Geschichte der Philosophie. Die okzidentale Konstellation von Glauben und Wissen. Berlin: Suhrkamp, vol. 1. [Google Scholar]
- Habermas, Jürgen. 2019b. Auch eine Geschichte der Philosophie. Vernünftige Freiheit. Spuren des Diskurses über Glauben und Wissen. Berlin: Suhrkamp, vol. 2. [Google Scholar]
- Harris, Sam. 2012. Free Will. New York: Free Press. [Google Scholar]
- Hart, H. L. A. 1968a. Intention and punishment. In Punishment and responsibility. Essays in the Philosophy of Law. Oxford: Clarendon Press, pp. 113–35. [Google Scholar]
- Hart, H. L. A. 1968b. Prolegomenon to the principles of punishment. In Punishment and Responsibility. Essays in the Philosophy of Law. Oxford: Clarendon Press, pp. 1–27. [Google Scholar]
- Hirschman, Albert O. 1991. The Rhetoric of Reaction. Perversity, Futility, Jeopardy. Cambridge: The Belknap Press of Harvard University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Jaeggi, Rahel. 2018. Critique of Forms of Life. Translated by Ciaran Cronin. Cambridge: The Belknap Press of Harvard University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Kaiser, Gerhard. 2004. Warum noch debattieren? Determinismus als Diskurskiller. In Hirnforschung und Willensfreiheit. Zur Deutung der neuesten Experimente. Edited by Christian Geyer. Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp, pp. 261–67. [Google Scholar]
- Kambartel, Friedrich. 1995. Positivismus (systematisch). In Enzyklopädie Philosophie und Wissenschaftstheorie. Edited by Jürgen Mittelstraß. Stuttgart: Metzler, vol. 3, pp. 303–304, P-So. [Google Scholar]
- Kierkegaard, Søren. 1959. Either or, Part Two. Translated by Walter Lowrie. New York: Anchor Books. [Google Scholar]
- Kitcher, Philip. 2008. Science, religion, and democracy. Episteme 5: 5–18. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Köllner, Tobias. 2018. Religious conservatism in post-Soviet Russia and its relation to politics. Empirical findings from ethnographic fieldwork. In New Conservatives in Russia and East Central Europe. Edited by Katharina Bluhm and Mihai Varga. Oxfordshire: Routledge, pp. 245–259. [Google Scholar]
- Kolodny, Niko. 2014. Rule over none I: What justifies democracy? Philosophy & Public Affairs 42: 195–229. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Korsgaard, Christine M. 1996. The Sources of Normativity. Edited by Onora O’Neill. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Lafont, Cristina. 2009. Religion and the public sphere. What are the deliberative obligations of democratic citizenship? Philosophy & Social Criticism 35: 127–50. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Libet, Benjamin. 2005. Do we have a free will? In The Oxford Handbook of Free Will. Edited by Robert Kane. Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 551–64. [Google Scholar]
- List, Christian. 2011. The logical space of democracy. Philosophy & Public Affairs 39: 262–97. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- List, Christian. 2014. Free will, determinism, and the possibility of doing otherwise. Noûs 48: 156–78. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
- Mansbridge, Jane, James Bohman, Simone Chambers, Thomas Christiano, Archon Fung, John Parkinson, Dennis Thompson, and Mark Warren. 2012. A systemic approach to democratic deliberation. In Deliberative Systems. Deliberative Democracy at the Large Scale. Edited by John Parkinson and Jane Mansbridge. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 1–26. [Google Scholar]
- Marx, Karl. 1978. Contribution to the critique of Hegel’s philosophy of right: Introduction. In The Marx-Engels-Reader, 2nd ed. Edited by Robert C. Tucker. New York: Norton & Company, pp. 53–65. First published 1844. [Google Scholar]
- Marx, Karl. 1978. Capital, Volume One. In The Marx-Engels-Reader, 2nd ed. Edited by Robert C. Tucker. New York: Norton & Company, pp. 294–438. First published 1867. [Google Scholar]
- Maus, Ingeborg. 1991. Sinn und Bedeutung von Volkssouveränität in der modernen Gesellschaft. Kritische Justiz 24: 137–50. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Merkel, Reinhard. 2008. Willensfreiheit und rechtliche Schuld. Eine Strafrechtsphilosophische Untersuchung. Baden-Baden: Nomos. [Google Scholar]
- Müller, Tobias, and Thomas M. Schmidt. 2015. Einleitung. In Abschied von der Lebenswelt. Zur Reichweite Naturwissenschaftlicher Erklärungsansätze. Edited by Tobias Müller and Thomas M. Schmidt. Freiburg: Alber, pp. 9–14. [Google Scholar]
- Nagel, Thomas. 1987. Moral conflict and political legitimacy. Philosophy & Public Affairs 16: 215–40. [Google Scholar]
- Nagel, Thomas. 2012. Mind and Cosmos. Why the Materialist Neo-Darwinian Conception of the Nature Is Almost Certainly False. Oxford: Oxford University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Peterson, Gregory R. 2010. Ethics, out-group altruism, and the New Atheism. In Religion and the New Atheism. Edited by Amarnath Amarasingam. Danvers: Brill, pp. 157–77. [Google Scholar]
- Pettit, Philip. 2004. Depoliticizing democracy. Ratio Juris 17: 52–65. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
- Plantinga, Alvin. 1999. Is belief in God rational? In Philosophy of Religion. Toward a Global Perspective. Edited by Gary E. Kessler. Belmont: Wadsworth, pp. 456–64. [Google Scholar]
- Przeworksi, Adam. 1999. Minimalist conception of democracy: A defense. In Democracy’s Value. Edited by Ian Shapiro and Casiano Hacker-Cordón. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 23–55. [Google Scholar]
- Rawls, John. 1972. A Theory of Justice. Oxford: Clarendon Press. [Google Scholar]
- Rawls, John. 1989. The domain of the political and overlapping consensus. New York University Law Review 64: 233–55. [Google Scholar]
- Rawls, John. 1993. Political Liberalism. New York: Columbia University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Rawls, John. 1997. The idea of public reason revisited. The University of Chicago Law Review 64: 765–807. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Rawls, John. 1999. A Theory of Justice, rev. ed. Oxford: Oxford University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Rawls, John. 2003. The Law of Peoples, 5th ed. Cambridge: Harvard University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Raz, Joseph. 1990. Facing diversity: The case of epistemic abstinence. Philosophy & Public Affairs 19: 3–46. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Rorty, Richard. 1999. Religion as conversation-stopper. In Philosophy and Social Hope. London: Penguin, pp. 168–74. [Google Scholar]
- Roseneck, Michael. 2021. Zwischen Tradition und Geltung. Religion als Herausforderung und Ressource für die Öffentliche Vernunft. Baden-Baden: Nomos. [Google Scholar]
- Roth, Gerhard. 2016. Die Perspektive der Hirnforschung: Schuld und Verantwortung. Biologie in Unserer Zeit 16: 177–83. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Sandel, Michael J. 2007. The Case Against Perfection. Ethics in the Age of Genetic Engineering. Cambridge: The Belknap Press of Harvard University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Scanlon, Thomas M. 1998. What We Owe to Each other. Cambridge: The Belknap Press of Harvard University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Schmidt, Thomas M. 2008. Öffentliche Vernunft—vernünftige Öffentlichkeit? Zum Verhältnis von Rationalität und Normativität in Rawls‘ politischem Liberalismus. In Religion in der Pluralistischen Öffentlichkeit. Edited by Thomas M. Schmidt and Michael G. Parker. Würzburg: Echter, pp. 87–103. [Google Scholar]
- Schmidt, Thomas M. 2012. Reflexionsgleichgewicht. Die Rechtfertigung von Gerechtigkeit in einer pluralen Welt. In Herausforderungen der Modernität. Edited by Thomas M. Schmidt, Martin Endreß, Hans-Joachim Höhn and Oliver Wiertz. Würzburg: Echter, pp. 137–58. [Google Scholar]
- Schulzke, Marcus. 2013. The politics of New Atheism. Politics and Religion 6: 778–99. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Shklar, Judith. 1964. Legalism. Cambridge: Harvard University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Taylor, Charles. 1995. Liberal politics and the public sphere. In Philosophical Arguments. Cambridge: Harvard University Press, pp. 289–310. [Google Scholar]
- Viertbauer, Klaus. 2019. Neuer Atheismus. In Handbuch Analytische Religionsphilosophie. Akteure—Diskurse—Perspektiven. Edited by Klaus Viertbauer and Georg Gasser. Stuttgart: Metzler, pp. 257–71. [Google Scholar]
- Waldron, Jeremy. 2002. God, Locke, and Equality. Christian Foundations in Locke’s Political Thought. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Wilde, Lawrence. 2010. The antinomies of aggressive atheism. Contemporary Political Theory 9: 266–83. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Wolterstorff, Nicholas. 1997. The role of religion in decision and discussion of political issues. In Religion in the Public Square. The Place of Religious Convictions in Political Debate. Edited by James P. Sterba and Rosemarie Tong. Lanham: Rowman & Littlefield, pp. 67–120. [Google Scholar]
- Zunke, Christine. 2008. Kritik der Hirnforschung. Neurophysiologie und Willensfreiheit. Berlin: Akademie Verlag. [Google Scholar]
Publisher’s Note: MDPI stays neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations. |
© 2022 by the author. Licensee MDPI, Basel, Switzerland. This article is an open access article distributed under the terms and conditions of the Creative Commons Attribution (CC BY) license (https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/).
Share and Cite
Roseneck, M. Positivism and Reasonableness: Authoritarian Leanings in New Atheism’s Thinking. Religions 2022, 13, 186. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel13020186
Roseneck M. Positivism and Reasonableness: Authoritarian Leanings in New Atheism’s Thinking. Religions. 2022; 13(2):186. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel13020186
Chicago/Turabian StyleRoseneck, Michael. 2022. "Positivism and Reasonableness: Authoritarian Leanings in New Atheism’s Thinking" Religions 13, no. 2: 186. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel13020186
APA StyleRoseneck, M. (2022). Positivism and Reasonableness: Authoritarian Leanings in New Atheism’s Thinking. Religions, 13(2), 186. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel13020186