1. Introduction
Freedom of conscience and conscientious objection, particularly in healthcare contexts, are back on the European human rights agenda. After a few years of apparent respite from the
big bang of claims of conscience that characterized the second half of the 20th century (
Navarro-Valls and Martínez-Torrón 2012), new laws on euthanasia and assisted suicide in Spain and Portugal, contested changes to the Polish legislation on abortion, and growing right-to-die activism in countries like Italy and the United Kingdom have rekindled the interest for the legal phenomenon of conscientious objection.
1 The European Court of Human Rights (hereinafter the Tribunal, the Court or ECtHR) has contributed to this new situation with its contested 2020 decisions of inadmissibility in two cases related to conscientious objection to abortion against Sweden,
Grimmark and
Steen.Although the European Convention on Human Rights (hereinafter the Convention, the Covenant, or ECHR) protects freedom of religion, conscience, and belief in Article 9, it does not recognize a general right to conscientious objection. Even from the first years of activity of the judicial bodies of the Council of Europe, conscience claims have not been an infrequent source of work for the Commission (hereinafter, the Commission or ECsHR) and the European Court of Human Rights, particularly on the rejection by individuals to domestic laws imposing mandatory armed military service. For many decades, the magistrates sitting in Strasbourg refused to accord any relevance under the Convention to conscientious objection, which was considered to be outside the scope of the European human rights text and to pertain exclusively to the margin of appreciation of the member states. It was for the authorities of each country to decide if, and how, individual claims of conscience should or could be accommodated. The growing change in the worldwide perception of compulsory military service brought about a change in the Court’s doctrine in the early 2010s, in the seminal judgment of Bayatyan v. Armenia. For the first time, the ECtHR was ready to admit to an inherent connection between conscientious objection and the freedoms enshrined in Article 9 of the Convention, and to impose on member states the positive obligation to accommodate individual claims born from a serious and insurmountable conflict of conscience or based on convictions or beliefs that are of sufficient cogency, seriousness, cohesion, and importance.
This new take on conscientious objection has, however, not made its way to the case law of other situations that involve the refusal of individuals, for religious, moral, ethical, or deontological reasons, to submit to a conduct imposed by a legal norm. As has been recently proven in the two decisions against Sweden, the Court is still reluctant to extend its doctrine on conscientious objection to mandatory military service to other areas where individual conscience and the right to life are involved, thus creating a disconcerting disconnect between otherwise strongly related areas of the Court’s jurisprudence. This lack of coherence creates a problematic grey area for physicians and other healthcare providers such as pharmacists, nurses, and midwives who refuse to take part in direct or indirect activities connected to therapeutic abortion or physician-assisted end of life, in what could be interpreted as a step backwards in the effective protection of human rights and the value of human dignity that justifies the Court’s existence.
The purpose of this article is to provide some insight on how the European Court of Human Rights has dealt, so far, with conscience claims of healthcare providers related to human life, and how its current stance could affect future applications on related issues. In order to do so, the article begins with an analysis of the ECtHR’s general jurisprudence on the right to freedom of conscience and to conscientious objection, before moving on to a more specific critical appraisal of its case law on the relationship between the right to life and abortion, and on conscientious objection to the voluntary termination of pregnancy. After a brief consideration on how some of the similarities of Strasbourg’s end-of-life jurisprudence with its decisions on abortion could affect future conscience claims of physicians and other health care professionals regarding euthanasia and assisted suicide, the article concludes with some final reflections on how the European Court of Human Rights could contribute in the next decades to the pacification of controversial and divisive issues such as the ones discussed in this article.
3. Right to Life and Abortion in the European Court of Human Rights
When the European Convention on Human Rights was adopted in the mid-twentieth century, abortion was illegal in most European countries which limited their legislation to a few exceptions in cases where the life or health of the mother was seriously threatened by the pregnancy (
Puppinck 2013). The debate that already existed at that time on questions related to this matter, especially as to whether the unborn child could be considered a person and therefore under the protection of Article 2 ECHR, led the drafters to be particularly cautious.
27With the first two decades of the 21st century behind us, the European panorama is considerably different. Today, the voluntary termination of pregnancy is regulated or decriminalized in practically all the member States of the Council of Europe where both abortion on demand and termination of pregnancy for socioeconomic reasons are becoming increasingly widespread.
28 Only a small group of countries, including Andorra, Liechtenstein, Malta, Monaco, Poland, and San Marino, still maintain a more restrictive legislation
29.
The development by member States of legal systems that are increasingly permissive of abortion, together with the growing attention paid in recent decades by the Council of Europe to women’s sexual and reproductive rights, led its Parliamentary Assembly to adopt Resolution 1607 (2008) on
Access to safe and legal abortion in Europe (
Quirós Fons 2021).
30 Based on the three-fold initial affirmation that abortion can never be considered a method of family planning, that it should be avoided as far as possible, and that mechanisms compatible with women’s rights should be implemented in order to reduce both the number of unwanted pregnancies and abortions, the Resolution expresses its concern that, despite the fact that most countries of the Council of Europe allow abortion, there are still circumstances and contexts that make it difficult for women to have access to it in a real, acceptable, and safe manner.
After affirming that within the framework of the right of every human being to respect for their physical integrity and freedom to control of their own bodies, the ultimate choice of whether or not to have an abortion “should be a matter for the woman concerned, who should have the means of exercising this right in an effective way”, the Assembly invited member States (i) to decriminalize abortion within reasonable gestational periods; (ii) to guarantee the effective exercise of the right of women to have access to safe and legal abortion; (iii) to respect women’s autonomy of choice and implement the necessary conditions to enable them to make a free and informed choice without necessarily promoting recourse to abortion; (iv) to remove restrictions that hinder, de iure or de facto, access to safe abortion by creating the appropriate health, medical, and psychological conditions, and guaranteeing the necessary economic resources; (v) to adopt general strategies and policies on sexual and reproductive health and rights through the allocation of sufficient financial resources; (vi) to guarantee access for men and women to adequate contraceptive methods at reasonable cost; (vii) to introduce compulsory sex and relationships education programs for young people that are adapted to their age and gender in order to prevent unwanted pregnancies and abortions; and (viii) to promote family-friendly attitudes in public information campaigns, and to provide counselling and practical support to women who resort to abortion due to family or financial pressures.
Dating back to the 1960s and up to the present day, the jurisprudence of the Strasbourg Court in relation to abortion has been relatively extensive, and comprises decisions from both the Commission and the Court. In fact, at the time of writing, no fewer than twelve cases against Poland are pending before the Court, all involving the induced termination of pregnancy (
Krajewska 2021).
31 During its years of activity, the ECtHR’s jurisdiction has been called upon in diverse matters such as petitions for in abstracto review of laws decriminalizing abortion,
32 claims by male parents of fetuses aborted by their wives or partners,
33 claims concerning the provision of family-planning services,
34 doubts about the responsibility of the State in cases of forced termination of pregnancies as a result of medical negligence,
35 appeals related to the criminal consequences of the practice of illegal abortions,
36 and finally, claims related to effective access to abortion in countries traditionally reluctant to do so, such as Poland and Ireland.
37The Strasbourg Court has built its corpus of decisions and judgments in this area through three articles of the Convention: Article 2 ECHR (right to life); Article 8 ECHR (right to respect for private and family life); and, more recently, Article 3 ECHR (prohibition of torture and inhuman or degrading treatment).
Article 2 ECHR states that
“Everyone’s right to life shall be protected by law. No one shall be deprived of his life intentionally save in the execution of a sentence of a court following his conviction of a crime for which this penalty is provided by law.
2. Deprivation of life shall not be regarded as inflicted in contravention of this Article when it results from the use of force which is no more than absolutely necessary: (a) in defence of any person from unlawful violence; (b) in order to effect a lawful arrest or to prevent the escape of a person lawfully detained; (c) in action lawfully”.
In relation to this provision, the European Court of Human Rights has established that although the Convention does not recognize a right to abortion
38, nor does it per se exclude intrauterine life from its scope of application.
39 The determination of when human existence begins, as well as the decision to decriminalize or legislate on abortion, is left at the exclusive prerogative of each of the States that make up the Council of Europe, as is the regulation of the recognition and form of exercise of conscientious objection
40.
It has been in the context of cases related to abortion that the Strasbourg jurisdiction has expressed its view on the moment at which human life can be considered to have begun for the Convention. The Commission, and the Court itself, have reiterated on more than one occasion that in a matter as delicate as this in which scientific, philosophical, ethical, and religious opinions, as well as national laws themselves, differ considerably, the initial question arises as to whether the Convention can have anything to say at all
41. The lowest common denominator on this matter identified by the Grand Chamber among the countries belonging to the Council of Europe is, first, that the embryo and the fetus belong to the human race, and second, that their potential capacity to become a person demands that they be protected in the name of human dignity.
42 Any other consideration beyond these two initial assertions is left to the discretion of the States.
The Strasbourg doctrine on the applicability of Article 2 ECHR to the unborn fetus, developed by the Commission before it ceased its activity in 1998, was taken up by the Grand Chamber in the well-known judgment of Vo v. France, which resolved the application of a woman of Vietnamese origin who had been the victim of a medical negligence that had led to an unwanted therapeutic abortion. After the domestic courts rejected that involuntary manslaughter could be applied to a fetus, the claimant appealed to the Strasbourg Court, as she considered that the fact that French law did not attach any criminal consequences to causing the death of an intrauterine life, even involuntarily, amounted to a lack of protection of the right to life protected by Article 2 ECHR. The judges of the Grand Chamber rejected the applicant’s claim on the grounds that since “Article 2 of the Convention is silent as to the temporal limitations of the right to life and, in particular, does not define ‘everyone’ (‘toute personne’) whose ‘life’ is protected by the Convention”, the Court “has yet to determine the issue of the ‘beginning’ of ‘everyone’s right to life’ within the meaning of this provision and whether the unborn child has such a right”.
43In this regard, the judgment recalls that the Commission had already noted in previous rulings that the first paragraph of Article 2 ECHR contains two different, albeit interrelated, basic elements. While the first paragraph of the article establishes the general obligation for the law to protect the right to life, its second sentence contains a prohibition on the intentional termination of life. This prohibition is qualified by the exceptions provided for in Article 2(1) ECHR in fine, as well as in Article 2(2) ECHR, exceptions which, by their very nature, affect persons already born and cannot be applied to a fetus. In short, in the opinion first of the Commission and then of the Court, both the meaning generally attributed to the word “everyone” and the context in which the term is used by the Convention itself would support the idea that it does not include the unborn child. In any case, and without questioning as obvious the legitimate interest that States may have in protecting prenatal life, the Strasbourg Court considered that it is not for it to determine whether a fetus can be entitled to some kind of protection under the first paragraph of Article 2 ECHR. Reality proves that among the members of the Council of Europe there is no unanimity as to whether, or to what extent, Article 2 ECHR protects life before birth.
44 Finally, the Grand Chamber concluded that it is neither possible, nor desirable, to give an abstract answer to the question of whether the unborn child is a person for the purposes of Article 2 ECHR.
45In relation to abortion itself, the Commission determined early on that although it is not expressly included among the exceptions to Article 2 ECHR that qualify the prohibition of intentionally terminating a life, the induced termination of pregnancy is always compatible with this precept when it is justified by the need to protect the life and health of the pregnant mother.
46 As I pointed out in the previous paragraph, although the Strasbourg court has not expressed an opinion as to whether Article 2 ECHR should be interpreted as completely excluding the fetus as the holder of the right to life, what it has categorically rejected is that the unborn child has an absolute right to life: the life of the fetus is intimately connected with, and cannot be considered in isolation from, the life of the pregnant woman, and any interpretation in the sense of granting the fetus an unqualified right to life would lead to the conclusion that abortion would be prohibited even in the case of a pregnancy that involved a serious risk to the life of the mother, which in turn would mean “that the ‘unborn life’ of the foetus would be regarded as being of a higher value than the life of the pregnant woman”.
47Article 8 of the Convention protects private and family life in the following terms:
1. Everyone has the right to respect for his private and family life, his home and his correspondence.
2. There shall be no interference by a public authority with the exercise of this right except such as is in accordance with the law and is necessary in a democratic society in the interests of national security, public safety or the economic well-being of the country, for the prevention of disorder or crime, for the protection of health or morals, or for the protection of the rights and freedoms of others.
As regards to the implication of Article 8 ECHR in abortion-related issues, the connection between induced termination of pregnancy and the right to private and family life was established by the European Commission of Human Rights in 1976 in the case of Brüggemann and Scheuten v. Federal Republic of Germany (
Martínez-Torrón 1986;
Zureick 2015).
48 The complaint arose from the claim of two German citizens that the Constitutional Court’s decision to declare null and void a 1974 law decriminalizing several cases of abortion violated Article 8 ECHR by requiring them either to renounce sexual intercourse, to use contraceptive methods with which they did not agree, or to carry out an eventual pregnancy against their will
49. The Commission admitted that both pregnancy and its termination are part of the notion of private life and, sometimes, of family life. By resorting to a notion of private life that would include sexual life as part of the right to privacy and to “develop relationships with other human beings, especially in the emotional field, for the development and fulfilment of one’s own personality” the 1976 decision ruled that the legal regulation of abortion entails an intrusion into private life which may or may not be justified under Article 8(2) ECHR
50. In a subsequent report issued on the same case, the Commission itself introduced the nuance that pregnancy cannot be considered to belong exclusively to the sphere of a woman’s private life, since when she is pregnant, her own life is connected in a particularly intense and intimate way with that of the fetus. Therefore, not every regulation concerning the termination of unwanted pregnancies can be considered an interference with the mother’s right to respect for her private life, nor can Article 8(1) ECHR be interpreted to mean that the pregnancy, or its termination, is the exclusive responsibility of the pregnant woman.
51As a consequence of this doctrine, and without prejudice to the fact that the Court had considered that Article 8 ECHR includes a right to personal autonomy that extends not only to the respect for physical and psychological integrity but also to the individual decision to have or not to have children,
52 for Strasbourg, any regulation on abortion implies for the State an initial weighing of public and private interests as well as a series of positive obligations aimed at guaranteeing the physical and psychological integrity of the mother.
53 Consequently, the woman’s right to respect for her private life must be weighed against other competing rights and interests, including those of the unborn child.
54 In this balancing exercise, the margin of appreciation that the Court grants to the States to establish the terms of their respective domestic legal systems plays an important role, as we will see in the judgments that are briefly described below.
In 2010, in the judgment A., B., and C. v. Ireland, the Grand Chamber ruled cumulatively on the claims of three women who had traveled to the United Kingdom to each have an abortion that they considered would not be authorized in their country of origin. Along with the violation of other provisions of the Convention, the applicants alleged that the legal limitations on voluntary termination of pregnancy then in force in Ireland constituted an interference with the right to privacy protected by Article 8 ECHR
55. The highest chamber of the Court found an interference with the invoked provision in the three cases, although it only considered such an interference unjustified in the case of the third applicant. In the cases of the first two claimants, the Court ruled based on the State’s negative obligations; in the case of the last one, the judges sitting as a Grand Chamber chose to analyze the claim from the perspective of positive obligations. I will refer to this third case later on.
The first two applicants had decided to terminate their respective pregnancies for reasons of health and/or personal welfare, both of which were not covered by the, then current, Irish law.
56 Based on a broad interpretation of Article 8 ECHR, the Grand Chamber held that the prohibition on the applicants’ being able to terminate their pregnancies in Ireland amounted to an interference with their right to privacy
57. However, in considering whether such an interference could be considered necessary in a democratic society, the Grand Chamber answered in the affirmative. Relying on the doctrine of the margin of appreciation, the majority judges considered that the limitations imposed in Ireland on abortion properly balanced the conflicting legal interests: on one hand, the women’s right to respect for their private lives; on the other hand, the deep moral values of the Irish people concerning the nature of life and the consequent need to protect the unborn child. Without denying that there is indeed a growing consensus in Europe in favor of broadening the circumstances in which abortion would be permitted, the judgment did not consider this sufficient reason to limit Ireland’s margin of appreciation and to question its decision to maintain a more restrictive legislation.
Without going so far as to admit that the margin of appreciation of each State in matters related to abortion is unlimited, since any State regulation must always be compatible with the Convention and subject to the supervision of the Court, the Grand Chamber did establish in A., B., and C. an interesting connection between Articles 8 and 2 ECHR which reinforces the discretion of the countries in this matter. Referring to the previously mentioned case of Vo v. France, A., B., and C. recalls that the question of when the right to life begins falls within the margin of appreciation of the States, precisely because there was no European legal or scientific consensus on the matter at the time the Convention was drafted, nor is there any today. From this initial lack of consensus, it was and is impossible to give a single answer to the question of whether the unborn child can be considered a person for the purposes of the protection afforded by Article 2 ECHR. Since it is the responsibility of the State to define which interests of the unborn child are worthy of protection and because the rights of the fetus and the mother are intrinsically interconnected, the margin of appreciation granted to the national authorities in relation to the protection of the unborn child inevitably conditions the weighing of the interests of the mother when they conflict with those of the child she is carrying. Thus, although most member States have chosen to resolve this conflict of interests by favoring a broad right of women to abortion, this consensus cannot, of itself, be decisive for the Court when assessing the situation in other countries, even in the light of the evolving interpretation of the Convention
58. Paradoxically, in comparison with other cases in which consensus is invoked as a limit to the margin of appreciation, this variable is less decisive in matters of abortion because it arises from a lack of agreement on a fundamental prior question, that being, whether or not the fetus is a person for the purposes of the protection afforded by Article 2 ECHR.
As mentioned above, the Court has also linked Article 8 ECHR and the positive obligations that derive from it for the State with the real possibility for women to access abortion when it is legally permitted in a national legal system.
59 Based on the traditional assertion that the Convention is intended to guarantee rights that are real and effective and not theoretical or illusory, the Court has been particularly critical of some of the procedures established in domestic legal orders for women to access abortions. While recognizing that Article 8 ECHR does not contain any explicit procedural requirements, the Court has pointed out that it is important that fair processes be implemented that adequately respect the interests affected.
60 In particular, since the Tysiąc v. Poland judgment, the Court has questioned national provisions that, while allowing access under certain conditions to voluntary termination of pregnancy, are formulated in terms that may have a chilling effect on the health professionals responsible for certifying the appropriateness or necessity of terminating the pregnancy. Once a State decides to permit abortion, it cannot design a legal framework that de facto limits the real possibilities of obtaining it.
61This was precisely the case of the third claimant in the above-mentioned A., B., and C. case. Her starting situation differed from that of the first two applicants. She had learned of her unplanned pregnancy at a time when she was in remission from a rare type of cancer and after having undergone a series of diagnostic tests that are contraindicated during pregnancy. Although her case could have qualified for the only exception to the general prohibition on abortion then allowed under Irish law—the real and substantial risk to the mother’s life—the alleged deterrent effect of the regulatory framework in force at the time meant that the health professionals who attended her were inconclusive not only about the risk that the pregnancy might cause her to relapse into her illness, but also about the effects that the diagnostic tests already carried out might have had on the fetus. Faced with this uncertainty, the third applicant chose to have an abortion in a clinic in the United Kingdom. In her application to the Strasbourg Court, she argued that the Irish authorities had breached their positive obligations under Article 8 ECHR by failing to establish a clear procedure by which she could have determined whether, because her life was at risk, she could have a legal abortion in her own country.
62Following the precedent of Tysiąc, the Grand Chamber recalled that, without prejudice to the wide margin of appreciation enjoyed by member States to establish their own regulations on abortion, once they have defined the applicable legal framework, it has to be designed in a coherent manner in order to ensure that the different legitimate interests involved are adequately taken into account. The judgment found that in Ireland, there was no clear procedure—neither medical nor before the courts of law—to verify the real risk to the life of the mother arising from a pregnancy. This lack of clarity and certainty necessarily resulted in an undesirable chilling effect, which led health professionals to be extremely cautious in their opinions and decisions for fear of the consequences, even criminal, of their actions
63.
Finally, in a relatively novel line of jurisprudence, the Strasbourg Court has analyzed the question of abortion in relation to Article 3 ECHR, which states that “No one shall be subjected to torture or to inhuman or degrading treatment or punishment”. After having been rejected on previous occasions in 2011 and 2012, the judgments R. R. v. Poland and P. and S. v. Poland recognized the potential implication of this article of the Convention in those cases in which the procedures established by the States so that women can legally have an abortion are made difficult and delayed to the point of causing a vulnerable pregnant woman anguish or suffering that exceeds the limits allowed by Article 3 ECHR (
Zureick 2015).
64 4. Healthcare Professionals and Conscientious Objection to Abortion in the European Court of Human Rights
Conscientious objection to abortion is defined as the refusal to perform an abortion or to cooperate directly or indirectly in its performance, and concerns not only medical or healthcare personnel, but has also been raised “by other citizens with respect to activities only indirectly related to the performance of abortions” (
Navarro-Valls and Martínez-Torrón 2012).
The Court’s meager body of decisions on the direct or indirect conscientious objection of healthcare professionals to abortion appears to be largely ignoring its own legal reasoning and doctrine on freedom of conscience and the rights protected by Articles 2, 3, and 8 of the Convention in claims connected to human life that were discussed in previous sections.
In cases concerning abortion or prenatal life, the Court has carefully declined to express any opinion on the morally and scientifically contentious question of “when does human life begin?” and has delegated to member States what relevance each of them wants to accord to the public and private interests at stake when regulating the voluntary termination of pregnancy. In this weighing of competing interests, the magistrates sitting in Strasbourg have favored national specificities over European consensus by upholding the compatibility with the Convention of national regulations on abortion that are more restrictive than what is the accepted norm in the majority of countries that belong to the Council of Europe. Positive obligations become the threshold of the State’s margin of appreciation, and once its legislation permits the voluntary termination of pregnancy, provided certain conditions are met, public authorities cannot indirectly limit actual access to the procedure, particularly if as a result the woman is caused insufferable anguish or suffering.
Contrarily, in conscience claims by healthcare professionals who object to their direct or indirect involvement in the termination of prenatal life, despite the acknowledged divisive nature of the underlying conflict, the Court appears to be siding with a European social and political consensus that artificially confronts conscientious objection and women’s sexual and reproductive rights. Consequently, the State’s positive obligations to reasonably accommodate claims of conscience that fall under Article 9 of the Convention have, to date, been ignored, and the willingness of the Strasbourg Court to recognize a right to conscientious objection linked to Article 9 ECHR which could be briefly seen in Bayatyan, has not been continued in any of its decisions concerning the refusal of certain healthcare professionals to participate in abortion practices. This position of the Court is surprising for two reasons: first, because conscientious objection to abortion and to military service have a common axiological origin, and that is a deep respect for the sanctity of human life (
Harrison 2021);
65 second, because even before the decision in the case against Armenia, the concern within the Council of Europe for the protection of freedom of religion and conscience in the medical field had given rise to Resolution 1736 (2010) of its Parliamentary Assembly.
66Under the title “The right to conscientious objection in legal medical practice”, Resolution 1736 (2010), begins by recognizing that conscientious objection by health professionals is satisfactorily regulated in most countries in the Council of Europe in such a way that its exercise does not prevent patients from accessing the services which objectors refuse to carry out. The Resolution expresses, however, two concerns: first, that no negative consequences can result from the decision of a person or institution not to perform, accommodate, or assist in the performance of an abortion, euthanasia, or any act that may cause the death of a human fetus or embryo; second, that it is important to reaffirm both the right to conscientious objection of the healthcare professional and the obligation of States to ensure that citizens have effective access to legally recognized medical services. Finally, the Resolution urges countries to weigh the interests of users of national health services against those of healthcare professionals and invites them to develop legislation that guarantees the rights of both parties, especially in cases of emergency.
As was the case for a long time with the Resolutions and Recommendations of the Parliamentary Assembly on conscientious objection to military service (
Valero 2021), the Strasbourg Court has not yet taken the step of incorporating into its jurisprudence the concerns and aspirations contained in the 2010 Resolution. With the exception of Eweida, which resolved two cases of conscientious objection in the medical arena that had nothing to do with the right to life,
67 up to the time of writing this paper, the scarce number of applications that have reached the Court related to conscientious objection in the healthcare field in general, and to direct or indirect objection to abortion in particular, have been declared inadmissible. This was the case in 2001 in Pichon and Sajous v. France; and again in the 2020 cases against Sweden, Grimmark and Steen (
Martínez-Torrón 2020).
68In Pichon and Sajous, the claim was brought by two French pharmacists who ran a pharmacy in a small town near Bordeaux. Both objected to supplying contraceptive drugs in their establishment on religious grounds and were sanctioned for it. After exhausting all domestic remedies without being able to see their conscience-related choice validated before the French courts, they brought an application before the European Court of Human Rights. The Third chamber dismissed their claim, relying on the aforementioned argument that Article 9 ECHR does not guarantee that an individual can always behave in the public sphere in accordance with his personal convictions. The decision included a reflection to the effect that, in the context of a legal activity and a highly regulated profession, such as in France the sale of contraceptives and the management of a pharmacy, one cannot give priority to one’s own religious beliefs, nor impose them on others.
In the most recent Grimmark and Steen cases, the applicants were two nurses who had received specific training to work as midwives. Both were denied employment in that specific professional category after they expressed to their potential employers an objection to abortion based on religious and ethical grounds. Their claims before the Court were dismissed as manifestly ill-founded by a three-judge Committee of the Third section of the ECtHR.
69 Both decisions found that the interference with the right to freedom of conscience protected by Article 9 ECHR of Ms. Grimmark and Ms. Steen was justified and necessary in a democratic society: Sweden provides access to medical abortion throughout its territory and consequently has a positive obligation to organize the national health system in such a way that the exercise of freedom of conscience by health care professionals does not impede the effective provision of abortion. Accordingly, the requirement that all midwives in Sweden be willing to carry out the duties inherent to their position, including performing abortions, is justified and not disproportionate. The applicants had voluntarily chosen their profession, and both should have been aware that accepting employment as midwives entailed performing each and every one of the functions attributed to their professional category (
Martínez-Torrón 2020).
Although the Court’s reluctance to decide on the merits of claims related to conscientious objections to direct or indirect intervention in abortions prevents us from knowing in detail its position in this regard, some of the arguments present in the three inadmissibility decisions, briefly outlined in the preceding paragraphs, and, above all, some of their notable omissions, seem to contradict in many respects both the Court’s current doctrine on conscientious objection to compulsory military service and the Parliamentary Assembly’s Resolution 1736 (2010).
Undoubtedly, the most striking thing about the Pichon and Sajous and Grimmark and Steen decisions is that they avoid any serious and reasoned consideration of the undeniable, and in theory, not denied, right of healthcare professionals to their freedom of conscience and the exercise of conscientious objection. This omission raises numerous doubts that the Court chooses not to address, much less resolve:
1. The first issue raised by the inadmissibility decisions discussed in this section, in particular those concerning the two Swedish midwives, is the fact that the deciding Committee placed so much emphasis on the positive obligations incumbent upon the respondent State “to organize its health system in a way as to ensure that the effective exercise of freedom of conscience of health professionals in the professional context”.
70 This consideration is particularly surprising because Sweden does not recognize a right of conscientious objection for health professionals (
Munthe 2016). Therefore, in this Nordic country, medical practitioners and related personnel are not permitted by law any effective exercise of freedom of conscience in the context of their professional activities. However, this singularity of the Swedish legal order, which directly contradicts the Committee’s express statement, is not only not even mentioned in either of the two inadmissibility decisions, but also does not provoke the slightest reaction from the Court.
This omission could point, in the first place, to an implicit and disproportionate deference by the Committee to the doctrine of the margin of appreciation, which in itself would be questionable if we take into account the parameters set by Resolution 1736 (2010). But equally, it could reveal a more worrying and somewhat myopic, or at least partial, interpretation of the positive obligations of the member States in relation to the organization of their national health systems when it is a matter of protecting the legal and fundamental rights of all the subjects involved. It cannot be denied that, indeed, European countries have a positive obligation to guarantee real and effective access for their citizens to the portfolio of health services established by law, including, where appropriate, abortion, but it is no less certain that they also have, as Grimmark and Steen are careful to point out, a positive obligation to guarantee that the fundamental right to freedom of conscience of healthcare professionals, protected by the Convention, is real and effective and not merely theoretical.
The lack of reflection on this second aspect of the State’s positive obligations is all the more surprising if one considers the Court’s recent case law on conscientious objection to compulsory military service. Since Bayatyan, Strasbourg case law has not hesitated to draw attention to the incompatibility with the Convention of the member States’ legal systems that fail to comply with their positive obligations in relation to the effective exercise of conscientious objection to compulsory military service and do not accommodate conscience-related claims (
Valero 2021).
71 In view of this, one can only speculate as to why the Court has avoided attributing any consequences to the general prohibition in Sweden on the exercise of conscientious objection by health professionals.
2. A second issue that has not merited any consideration by the Court is related to the chilling effect mentioned in the previous pages and which refers to the dissuasive effect that very restrictive or unclear legislation can have on the exercise of certain rights. The concern expressed by the Court that the way in which the rules regulating access to abortion are drafted in less permissive legislations may have a dissuasive effect on health professionals that prevent women from effectively accessing a legally permitted medical service does not seem to have an adequate correlation when what is at stake is the exercise of a fundamental right—freedom of conscience—by health personnel. The Grimmark and Steen cases, and to some extent also Pichon and Sajous, raise the question of the extent to which legislation that denies or restricts the exercise of conscientious objection by health professionals does not produce the same chilling effect denounced by the Court, thus dissuading physicians, pharmacists, nurses, midwives, and other related personnel from exercising not only a right recognized in national legislation, but a freedom protected by the Convention, for fear of the disciplinary consequences or discrimination in employment that such exercise may entail (
Martínez-Torrón 2020).
3. The fact that, to date, the Court has declined to fully consider the merits of the claims that have been brought before it in relation to direct or indirect conscientious objection to abortion by health professionals, has justified the fact that, for the time being, the Court has not carried out a reasoned balancing of the public and private rights and interests at stake in the conflicts that have come before it. The systematic deference to the decisions of the domestic courts in the three cases discussed seems to imply that, at least in the public sector and in highly regulated professions and those related to the organization of national healthcare systems, any allegedly neutral law prevails over a serious and insurmountable conflict of conscience, even if, as the Court has recognized, this conflict is protected by Article 9 ECHR.
72 Once again, the Court avoids considering seriously and rigorously what is one of the fundamental points of Recommendation 1763 (2010) of the Parliamentary Assembly and of the Court’s own jurisprudence: the need that exists, when a dilemma arises between individual conscience and the law, to weigh, and as far as possible, accommodate the rights and interests of all parties involved—health professionals, women who wish to access a legal abortion, and the State—for which it is essential to carry out a careful balancing exercise (
Power-Forde 2016).
4. Linked to some of the reflections already made in the previous point, I do not want to conclude this section without highlighting one last particularly notable omission from the decisions discussed in the cases against France and Sweden: the absence of any mention of the doctrine of reasonable accommodation of religious beliefs in working environments, the essentially fungible nature of the professional activities of the actors in the claims, and the lack of any analysis by which the Court sought to ascertain whether there were practicable options that, while guaranteeing the access of the women concerned to the medicines and services required, would leave the freedom of conscience of the appellants unscathed. On the contrary, in the Pichon and Sajous decision, the Third section affirmed that one’s own beliefs cannot be imposed on third parties. And yet, at no point in the factual account of the case does it appear that the French pharmacists intended to impose their beliefs on anyone, any more than did the Swedish midwives. All they wanted was to be able to pursue their professions without violating their conscience. Comparative experience shows that allowing exceptions to compliance with neutral laws for serious religious, ethical, or moral reasons does not necessarily imply either the imposition of one’s own beliefs on third parties or a reduction in the access of those same third parties to the exercise of their rights (
Laycock 2015–2016).
There is nothing in the account of the cases to suggest that the refusal of two French pharmacists to dispense potentially abortifacient products, or of two Swedish midwives to intervene directly in pregnancy termination procedures, was of such a magnitude as to jeopardize the entire healthcare system of the two respondent States. But the Court does not even raise the possibility that France and Sweden would have any obligation to organize their public health services in a way that would reasonably accommodate the conscientious claims of a minority of professionals while maintaining the quality of care for women who wish to prevent or terminate a pregnancy. As has been observed in the doctrine, maximalist approaches, such as the one suggested, would lead to the undesirable conclusion that in order to fulfill a vocation to contribute to bringing children into the world, one would also have to be willing to terminate their intrauterine life (
Laycock 2015–2016).
In view of these considerations, reasonable doubt arises as to whether there is not a certain reluctance among the Strasbourg judges to apply their own doctrine on the relationship between Article 9 ECHR and the exercise of conscientious objection to a subject as morally and socially sensitive as abortion; a perhaps unjustified fear that an application of its jurisprudence along the lines indicated in the preceding paragraphs, which would force member States to, at least, make the effort to accommodate individual conscientious choices in controversial areas and matters, would be interpreted as meaning that the Court endorses, or at least does not question, the beliefs that inform and underlie the consciences of objectors. As I have pointed out in the first pages of this paper, this would be a mistaken understanding of what freedom of conscience consists in, especially considering the notion of human dignity and the principles of neutrality and pluralism, and one which would be inappropriate in a human rights court.
73 It is true that there are beliefs, religious or not, which differ from the moral values prevalent in European societies today, but it is no less true that such beliefs, and the right to behave in accordance with them, are protected by Article 9 ECHR, and that their limitation is justified only when a real need can be proven. The protection of freedom of conscience does not depend on the objective correctness of each citizen’s conceptions of what is good nor on their conformity with prevailing moral or social values but is based on its status as a human right essential to the dignity of the individual and to the democratic health of the State.
6. Conclusions
Freedom of conscience has become one of the principal areas in which the battle for religious freedom and freedom of thought is being fought in modern Western societies. In a social and political context, often marked by suspicion of the desire of citizens with beliefs—religious or not—to live in public and professional life according to their own moral codes, conscientious objection in matters related to the beginning and end of life has become the tip of the iceberg of a much deeper discussion about whether to admit exceptions to neutral laws for reasons of conscience (
Adhar 2008).
In recent decades, language that approaches the legal dimension of deeply complex moral debates on issues, such as abortion and euthanasia, reflects a profound underlying confrontation of values, and terms and expressions, such as
intolerance,
conscience wars, and
culture wars, are but the reflection of a worrying and divisive reality (
Fredman 2020;
Mancini and Rosenfeld 2018;
NeJaime and Siegel 2015;
Laycock 2014). In view of the analysis in this work, and although it may be argued that where conscientious objection in healthcare is concerned, the European Court of Human Rights has so far carefully avoided stepping out of the realm of social and political correctness by deferring systematically to the doctrine of the margin of appreciation (
Brzozowski 2021), given the precedent of
Bayatyan, I harbor a moderate hope that future pronouncements on conflicts of conscience in contexts where the beginning and end of human life is compromised will contribute to appease this dialectic of conflict, to take it out of the media, social, and political spheres in which it normally unfolds, and to redirect it into the parameters of legal argumentation centered on human dignity, which is the proper home of this jurisdictional body.
The arguments developed by Strasbourg in relation to conscientious objection to military service in particular, the link established between Article 9 of the Convention with serious and unavoidable individual conflicts of conscience, the limitation of the margin of state appreciation, and the firm defense of the need to attend in a balanced way to the rights and interests of all parties involved, have the potential to turn future jurisprudence of the Court into an effective tool for the normalization of the exercise of conscientious objection. However, the Court must assume the challenge of extrapolating it to other fields and applying it outside the strict context of armed military service.
With these concluding reflections, I do not intend in any way to trivialize reality as multifaceted and complex as the exercise of conscientious objection (
Martínez-Torrón 2019). If I had to draw only one conclusion from the analysis made in the pages of this work, it would be that the Strasbourg Court does not have a simple task ahead. If litigation in relation to conflicts of conscience and human life continues to increase in Europe as it has elsewhere in the West, it will not be easy for the judges of the Court to detach themselves from the cacophony surrounding these issues and focus on what their primary task is: to protect the reality and effectiveness of human rights, and the values of human rights and human dignity, “tolerance, equality, and respect for diversity among the 800 million individuals within its jurisdiction” (
Power-Forde 2016).
But in this difficult task assumed by the Court, there is something that it can never forget, and that is that human rights in general, and religious freedom in particular, must never be trivialized, and their instrumentalization to the point of turning them into mere dialectical arguments at the service of alleged social wars or into ideological weapons to be wielded against those who seek to live in common social space in accordance with their conscience, can never be justified.